Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Implicit biases in visually guided action

  • S.I.: Between Vision and Action
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

For almost half a century dual-stream advocates have vigorously defended the view that there are two functionally specialized cortical streams of visual processing originating in the primary visual cortex: a ventral, perception-related ‘conscious’ stream and a dorsal, action-related ‘unconscious’ stream. They furthermore maintain that the perceptual and memory systems in the ventral stream are relatively shielded from the action system in the dorsal stream. In recent years, this view has come under scrutiny. Evidence points to two overlapping action pathways: a dorso-dorsal pathway that calculates features of the object to be acted on, and a ventro-dorsal pathway that transmits stored information about skilled object use from the ventral stream to the dorso-dorsal pathway. This evidence suggests that stored information may exert significantly more influence on visually guided action than hitherto assumed. I argue that this, in turn, supports the notion of skilled automatic action that is nonetheless agential. My focus here will be on actions influenced by implicit biases (stereotypes/prejudices). Action that is biased in this way, I argue, is in an important sense intentional and agential.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

From Binkofski and Fink (2005). (Color figure online)

Fig. 3

From McIntosh and Lashleya (2008)

Fig. 4

From Chechlacz (2018)

Fig. 5

From Takemura et al. (2016). Reprinted with permission

Fig. 6

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are auditory, tactile and emotional dual streams that parallel the dual visual streams (Romanski et al. 1999; Reed et al. 2005; Brogaard et al. 2017). However, most research has focused on vision. Here the main focus will also be on vision.

  2. Milner and Goodale's claim that conscious vision is associated with representations in allocentric space is not universally accepted. On the attended intermediate-level representation theory of consciousness (AIR), advocated by Jesse Prinz (2000, 2012), conscious experiences are attended intermediate-level representations. Intermediate-level representations differ from representations in allocentric space. Representations in allocentric space represent abstract viewpoint-independent features of three-dimensional objects that are generated by abstracting away from the vantage point of view and surface details. Intermediate-level representations, by contrast, represent objects and the features they instantiate from the perceiver’s point of view. Because they reflect the retinal imprint (when veridical) yet capture information about Gestalt grouping, e.g., depth and orientation, they are also referred to as ‘2½-D sketches’ in David Marr’s (1982) terminology.

  3. It should be noted that the hypothesis that properties like the size and location of an object are computed in the dorsal stream in the absence of visual awareness should not be taken to imply that these properties are not consciously available. One possibility consistent with Milner and Goodale’s two-stream hypothesis is that the size and location of an object are also computed in the ventral stream, where they can be consciously accessed. On the three-stream hypothesis, which we will introduce below, information about the size and location of an object needed for the action system to generate a motor representation may be computed in the ventral stream before entering the action system.

  4. There has been a lot of debate about whether these kinds of influences count as instances of cognitive penetration of the action system. See e.g. Nanay (2013a, b), Mahon and Wu (2015), Burnston (2017a, b), Toribio (forthcoming). There is a parallel debate about whether the perceptual system in the ventral stream is cognitively penetrable (see e.g. Toribio 2018b for one stance in this debate). As there appear to be substantial cross-communication between the perception/cognition system in the ventral stream and the action system in the dorsal streams, even in online activities, these debates may well be interconnected. I will not take a stance on the question of cognitive penetration here. However, it is arguable that the more philosophically interesting question is that of whether the activation of implicit biases can bias how we act. Here I argue that it probably can bias how we act by modulating our intentions as opposed to modulating our motor representations or actions directly.

  5. While both future- and present-direct intentions are in some sense future-directed, present-directed intentions are intentions occurring immediately prior to the onset of the whole action or intentions occurring during (or in) action.

  6. Others have made similar distinctions. For example, Wilfrid Sellars distinguishes between intentions for the future and volitions, where volitions are what intentions for the future become when it’s time to act (Sellars 1966: p. 110). John McDowell (2010) argues that when ‘volition’ is understood in this way, then it cannot be used to refer to intentions that arise for the first time when it’s time to act. For that reason, he prefers to distinguish the notion of intentions in action, where the latter can be volitions in Sellars’ sense or novel present-directed intentions, which he prefers to express as ‘I am (willfully) ϕ-ing’ rather than ‘I will ϕ now’. For example, ‘I am raising my hand’ as opposed to ‘I will raise my hand now’ or ‘my hand is rising’.

  7. On the distinction between conscious and unconscious intentions, see also Anthony Marcel (2003) and Alfred Mele (2010).

  8. Skilled unreflective actions are actions that (1) involve mastery of a given skill, such as turkey carving, swimming or driving a car; and (2) unfold without the agent explicitly thinking about what she is doing (Brownstein 2014; see also Marcel 2003; Velleman 2008; Railton 2009; Annas 2011).

  9. For details of this type of view, see e.g. Gendler (2011), Holroyd (2012, 2015) and Sullivan-Bissett (2015).

  10. On this model, implicit biases do not encompass implicit prejudices understood as affective responses. I take stereotypes to accommodate evaluative responses, like Muslims are dangerous or Blacks are aggressive (see Haslanger 2012, 2013). On an alternative model, implicit biases are clusters of co-activating representational and affective components (‘aliefs’ in Tamar Gendler’s 2008a, b sense; see also Gendler 2011, 2012; Amodio 2014; Madva and Brownstein 2018; Brogaard 2020).

  11. Doris (2015) offers an appealing, compatibilist account of “accountability” (or “responsibility”) in terms of “agency.” To a first approximation, an agent exercises (full-blown rather than mere causal) agency when her action is an expression of her values. Whether all implicitly intentional, discriminatory actions will turn out to be expressions of agential values is a question I will leave for a future occasion.

References

  • Aglioti, S., Goodale, M. A., & DeSouza, J. F. X. (1995). Size-contrast illusions deceive the eye but not the hand. Current Biology, 5, 679–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amodio, D. M. (2014). The neuroscience of prejudice and stereotyping. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 15(10), 670–682.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andersen, R. A., Andersen, K. N., Hwang, E., & Hauschild, M. (2014). Optic ataxia: From Balint’s syndrome to the parietal reach region. Neuron, 81(5), 967–983. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuron.2014.02.025.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Annas, J. (2011). Intelligent virtue. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe GEM. (1957/2000). Intention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Banfield, J. F., Pendry, L. F., Mewse, A. J., & Edwards, M. G. (2003). The effects of an elderly stereotype prime on reaching and grasping actions. Social Cognition, 21(4), 299–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A., & Barndollar, K. (1996). Automaticity in action: The unconscious as repository of chronic goals and motives. In P. M. Gollwitzer & J. A. Bargh (Eds.), The psychology of action: Linking cognition and motivation to behavior (pp. 457–481). New York, NY: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A., & Chartrand, T. L. (1999). The unbearable automaticity of being. American Psychologist, 54, 462–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bargh, J. A., Chen, M., & Burrows, L. (1996). Automaticity of social behavior: Direct effect of trait construct and stereotype activation on action. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 71, 230–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binkofski, F., & Buxbaum, L. J. (2013). Two action systems in the human brain. Brain and Language, 127, 222–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binkofski, F., & Fink, G. (2005). Apraxien (Apraxias). Nervenarzt, 76, 493–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binkofski, F., Reetz, K., & Blangero, A. (2007). Tactile agnosia and tactile apraxia: Cross talk between the action and perception streams in the anterior intraparietal area. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 30(2), 201–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blomberg, O., & Brozzo, C. (2017). Motor intentions and non-observational knowledge of action: A standard story. Thought, 6, 137–146.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borghi, A. M., & Riggio, L. (2015). Stable and variable affordances are both automatic and flexible. Frontiers and Human Neuroscience, 9(351). https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2015.00351.

  • Borra, E., Belmalih, A., Calzavara, R., Gerbella, M., Murata, A., Rozzi, S., et al. (2008). Cortical connections of the macaque anterior intraparietal (AIP) area. Cerebral Cortex, 18(5), 1094–1111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. E. (1984). Two faces of intention. Philosophical Review, 93(3), 375–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. E. (1985). “Davidson’s theory of intention,” reprinted in Faces of Intention (1999) (pp. 209–224). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. E. (1987). Intention, plans and practical reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, E., & Smeets, J. B. J. (1996). Size illusion influences how we lift but not how we grasp an object. Experimental Brain Research, 111, 473–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R., & Schwenkler, J. (2015). Conscious vision in action. Cognitive Science, 39(7), 1435–1467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2011). Are there unconscious perceptual processes? Consciousness and Cognition, 20, 449–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2019). Bias-driven attention, cognitive penetration and epistemic downgrade. In C. Limbeck & F. Stadler (Eds.), Philosophy of perception (pp. 199–216). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2020). Hatred: Our most dangerous emotion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B., Marlow, K., Overgaard, M., Schwartz, B. L., Zopluoglu, C., Tomson, S., et al. (2017). Deaf hearing: Implicit discrimination of auditory content in a patient with mixed hearing loss. Philosophical Psychology. https://doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2016.1268680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, A.-M., Georgiou, I., Glover, S., & Castiello, U. (2006). Adjusting reach to lift movements to sudden visible changes in target’s weight. Experimental Brain Research, 173, 629–636.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brownstein, M. (2014). Rationalizing flow: Agency in skilled unreflective action. Philosophical Studies, 168(2), 545–568.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brozzo, C. (2017). Motor intentions: How intentions and motor representations come together. Mind and Language, 32(2), 231–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, N. (2001). When does action resist visual illusions? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5, 385–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, N., & Franz, V. H. (2009). When is grasping affected by the Müller–Lyer illusion? A quantitative review. Neuropsychologia, 47, 1421–1433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnston, D. C. (2017a). Cognitive penetration and the cognition–perception interface. Synthese, 194, 3645–3668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnston, D. C. (2017b). Interface problems in the explanation of action. Philosophical Explorations, 20(2), 242–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buxbaum, L. J., & Saffran, E. M. (2002). Knowledge of object manipulation and object function: Dissociations in apraxic and nonapraxic subjects. Brain and Language, 82(2), 179–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Sinigaglia, C. (2014). Intention and motor representation in purposive action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(1), 119–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buxbaum, L. J., & Kalénine, S. (2010). Action knowledge, visuomotor activation, and embodiment in the two action systems. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1191, 201–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buxbaum, L. J., Kyle, K. M., & Menon, R. (2005). On beyond mirror neurons: Internal representations subserving imitation and recognition of skilled object-related actions in humans. Cognitive Brain Research, 25(1), 226–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buxbaum, L. J., Sirigu, A., Schwartz, M. F., & Klatzky, R. (2003). Cognitive representations of hand posture in ideomotor apraxia. Neuropsychologia, 41, 1091–1113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caiani, S. Z., & Ferretti, G. (2017). Semantic and pragmatic integration in vision for action. Consciousness and Cognition, 48, 40–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chechlacz, M. (2018). Bilateral parietal dysfunctions and disconnections in simultanagnosia and Bálint syndrome. Handbook of Clinical Neurology, 151, 249–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cisek, P. (2007). Cortical mechanisms of action selection: The affordance competition hypothesis. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 362(1485), 1585–1599.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cloutman, L. L. (2013). Interaction between dorsal and ventral processing streams: Where, when and how? Brain and Language, 127, 251–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corbetta, M., & Shulman, G. L. (2002). Control of goal-directed and stimulus-driven attention in the brain. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 3(3), 201–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daprati, E., & Sirigu, A. (2006). How we interact with objects: learning from brain lesions. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10(6), 265–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, N., & Greenwald, A. G. (2001). On the malleability of automatic atitudes: Combating automatic prejudice with images of admired and disliked individuals. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81(5), 800–814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1978). “Intending,” reprinted in Essays on Actions and Events (1980) (pp. 83–102). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on action and events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 60, 441–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doris, J. (2015). Talking to our selves: Reflection, ignorance, and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, C., Edwards, M. G., Taylor, L. J., & Ietswaart, M. (2016). Impaired communication between the dorsal and ventral stream: Indications from apraxia. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 10, 8. https://doi.org/10.3389/fnhum.2016.00008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fatima, S. (2017). On the edge of knowing: Microaggression and epistemic uncertainty as a woman of color. In K. Cole & H. Hassel (Eds.), Surviving sexism in academia: Feminist strategies for leadership (pp. 147–157). London: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. (2016). Through the forest of motor representations. Consciousness and Cognition, 43, 177–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz, V. H., & Gegenfurtner, K. R. (2008). Grasping visual illusions: Consistent data and no dissociation. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 25, 920–950.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz, V. H., Gegenfurtner, K. R., Bülthoff, H. H., & Fahle, M. (2000). Grasping visual illusions: No evidence for a dissociation between perception and action. Psychological Science, 11, 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz, V. H., Hesse, C., & Kollath, S. (2009). Visual illusions, delayed grasping, and memory: No shift from dorsal to ventral control. Neuropsychologia, 47, 1518–1531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., Craighero, L., Fadiga, L., & Fogassi, L. (1999). Perception through action. Psyche: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness, 5, 21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garcea, F. E., & Buxbaum, L. J. (2019). Gesturing tool use and tool transport actions modulates inferior parietal functional connectivity with the dorsal and ventral object processing pathways. Human Brain Mapping, 40(10), 2867–2883.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2008a). Alief and belief. The Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 634–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2008b). Alief in action (and reaction). Mind and Language, 23(5), 552–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2011). On the epistemic costs of implicit bias. Philosophical Studies, 156, 33–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gendler, T. S. (2012). Between reason and reflex: Response to commentators. Analysis, 72(4), 799–811.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1977). The theory of affordances. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.), Perceiving, acting, and knowing: Toward an ecological psychology (pp. 67–82). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A. (2014). How (and why) the visual control of action differs from visual perception. Proceedings. Biological Sciences, 281(1785), 20140337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., & Milner, A. D. (1992). Separate visual pathways for perception and action. Trends in Neurosciences, 15, 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M. A., Milner, A. D., Jakobson, L. S., & Carey, D. P. (1991). A neurological dissociation between perceiving objects and grasping them. Nature, 349, 154–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafton, S. T. (2010). The cognitive neuroscience of prehension: recent developments. Experimental Brain Research, 204, 475–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grill-Spector, K., Kourtzi, Z., & Kanwisher, N. (2001). The lateral occipital complex and its role in object recognition. Vision Research, 41, 1409–1422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P. (2005). Conscious intention and motor cognition. Trends in cognitive sciences, 9(6), 290–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Eimer, M. (1999). On the relation between brain potentials and the awareness of voluntary movements. Experimental Brain Research, 126, 128–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Libet, B. W. (2001). Conscious intention and brain activity. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(11), 47–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2012). Resisting reality: Social construction and social critique. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2013). Social Meaning and Philosophical Method, Presidential Address, Eastern Division of the American Philosophical Association.

  • Holroyd, J. (2012). Responsibility for Implicit Bias. Journal of Social Philosophy, 43(3), 274–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holroyd, J. (2015). Implicit bias, awareness and imperfect cognitions. Consciousness and Cognition, 33, 511–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (2006). Motor cognition: What actions tell the self. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. J., Decety, J. F., & Michel, F. (1994). Impairment of grasping movements following a bilateral posterior parietal lesion. Neuropsychologia, 32, 369–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kawakami, K., Dovidio, J., & van Kamp, S. (2007). The impact of counterstereotypic training and related correction processes on the application of stereotypes. Group Processes and Intergroup Relations, 10(2), 139–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, M., & Carruthers, P. (forthcoming). Responsibility and consciousness. In D.K. Nelkin and D. Pereboom (Eds.), Oxford Handbook on Moral Responsibility.

  • Kriegeskorte, N., Mur, M., Ruff, D. A., Kiani, R., Bodurka, J., Esteky, H., et al. (2008). Categorical object representations in inferior temporal cortex of man and monkey. Neuron, 60(6), 1126–1141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (1985). Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 529–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., Faucher, L., & Kelly, D. (2010). On the alleged inadequacy of psychological explanations of racism. The Monist, 93(2), 228–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Madva, A., & Brownstein, M. (2018). Stereotypes, prejudice, and the taxonomy of the implicit social mind. Noûs, 52(3), 611–644.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahon, B. Z., & Wu, W. (2015). Cognitive penetration of the dorsal visual stream? In J. Zeimbekis & A. Raftopoulos (Eds.), The cognitive penetrability of perception: New philosophical perspectives. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198738916.001.0001.

  • Mandelbaum, E. (2016). Attitude, association, and inference: On the propositional structure of implicit bias. Noûs, 50(3), 629–658.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcel, A. (2003). The sense of agency: Awareness and ownership of action. In J. Roessler & N. Eilan (Eds.), Agency and self-awareness (pp. 48–93). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision. San Francisco: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • McConnell, A., & Leibold, J. (2001). Relations among the implicit association test, discriminatory behavior, and explicit measures of racial attitudes. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 37(5), 435–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mcdowell, J. (2010). What is the content of an intention in action. Ratio, 23(4), 415–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh, R. D., & Lashley, G. (2008). Matching boxes: Familiar size influences action programming. Neuropsychologia, 46(9), 2441–2444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (1992). Springs of action. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (2010). Conscious intentions. In J. K. Campbell, M. O’Rourke, & H. S. Silverstein (Eds.), Action, ethics, and responsibility (pp. 85–108). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mendoza, S., Gollwitzer, P., & Amodio, D. (2010). Reducing the expression of implicit stereotypes: Reflexive control through implementation intentions. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 36(4), 512–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1945/1965). Phenomenology of perception. London: Routledge.

  • Milner, A. D., Dijkerman, H. C., Pisella, L., McIntosh, R. D., Tilikete, C., Vighetto, A., et al. (2001). Grasping the past: Delay can improve visuomotor performance. Current Biology, 11, 1896–1901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (1995). The visual brain in action. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, A. D., & Goodale, M. A. (2008). Two visual systems reviewed. Neuropsychologia, 46, 774–785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mozaz, M., Rothi, L., Anderson, J., Crucian, G. P., & Heilman, K. (2002). Postural knowledge of transitive pantomimes and intransitive gestures. Journal of the International Neuropsychological Society, 8, 958–962.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2013a). Between perception and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2013b). Is action-guiding vision cognitively impenetrable? In N. J. Hillsdale (Ed.), Procceedings of the 35th annual conference of the cognitive science society (CogSci 2013) (pp. 1055–1060). New York: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelissen, K., & Vanduffel, W. (2011). Grasping-related functional magnetic resonance imaging brain responses in the macaque monkey. Journal of Neuroscience, 31(22), 8220–8229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Shea, R. P., Chandler, N. P., & Roy, R. (2013). Dentists make larger holes in teeth than they need to if the teeth present a visual illusion of size. PLoS ONE, 8(10), e77343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2011). Nonconceptual representations for action and the limits of intentional control. Social Psychology, 42(1), 67–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2018). Motor Intentionality. In A. Newen, L. De Bruin, & S. Gallagher (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of 4E cognition, Chapter 19. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelgrims, B., Andres, M., Seron, X., Duhamel, J.-R., Sirigu, A., & Olivier, E. (2005). Role of the left supramarginal gyrus in coding hand gestures: Implication for ideomotor apraxia (p. 2005). New York: Cognitive Neuroscience Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perenin, M. T., & Vighetto, A. (1988). Optic ataxia: A specific disruption in visuomotor mechanisms. Brain, 111, 643–674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pisella, L., Binkofski, F., Lasek, K., Toni, I., & Rossetti, Y. (2006). No double dissociation between optic ataxia and visual agnosia: Multiple sub-streams for multiple visuo-manual integrations. Neuropsychologia, 44, 2734–2748.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2000). A neurofunctional theory of visual consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 9(2), 243–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2012). The conscious brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. (2009). Practical competence and fluent agency. In D. Sobel & S. Wall (Eds.), Reasons for action (pp. 81–115). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Randerath, J., Goldenberg, G., Spijkers, W., Li, Y., & Hermsdörfer, J. (2010). Different left brain regions are essential for grasping a tool compared with its subsequent use. Neuroimage, 53(1), 171–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, C. L., Klatzky, R. L., & Halgren, E. (2005). What vs. where in touch: an fMRI study. Neuroimage, 25, 718–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Camarda, R., Fogassi, L., Gentilucci, M., Luppino, G., & Matelli, M. (1988). Functional organization of inferior area 6 in the macaque monkey. II. Area F5 and the control of distal movements. Exp Brain Res., 71(3), 491–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Matelli, M. (2003). Two different streams form the dorsal visual system: Anatomy and functions. Experimental Brain Research, 153, 146–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romanski, L. M., Tian, B., Fritz, J., Mishkin, M., Goldman-Rakic, P. S., & Rauschecker, J. P. (1999). Dual streams of auditory afferents target multiple domains in the primate prefrontal cortex. Nature Neuroscience, 2, 1131–1136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sakreida, K., Effnert, I., Thill, S., Menz, M. M., Jirak, D., Eickhoff, C. R., et al. (2016). Affordance processing in segregated parieto-frontal dorsal stream sub-pathways. Neuroscience Biobehavior Review, 69, 89–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. (2012). Ranking exercises in philosophy and implicit bias. Journal of Social Philosophy, 43(3), 256–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul, J. (2013). Implicit bias, stereotype threat, and women in philosophy. In F. Jenkins & K. Hutchison (Eds.), Women in philosophy: What needs to change? (pp. 39–60). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schenk, T. (2006). An allocentric rather than perceptual deficit in patient D.F. Nature Neuroscience, 9, 1345–1347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schenk, T., & McIntosh, R. D. (2010). Do we have independent visual streams for perception and action? Cognitive Neuroscience, 1, 52–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schenk, T., Ellison, A., Nichola, R., & Milner, A. D. (2005). The role of V5/MT+ in the control of catching movements: An rTMS study. Neuropsychologia, 43, 189–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1966). Thought and action. In K. Lehrer (Ed.), Freedom and determinism. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shepherd, J. (forthcoming). Skilled action and the double life of intention. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Smeets, J. B. J., & Brenner, E. (2006). 10 years of illusions. The Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 32, 1501–1504.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smeets, J. B. J., Brenner, E., de Grave, D. D. J., & Cuijpers, R. H. (2002). Illusions in action: Consequences of inconsistent processing of spatial attributes. Experimental Brain Research, 147, 135–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sue, D. W. (2010). Microaggressions in everyday life: Race, gender, and sexual orientation. New York: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan-Bissett, E. (2015). Implicit bias, confabulation, and epistemic innocence. Consciousness and Cognition, 33, 548–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takemura, H., Rokem, A., Winawer, J., Yeatman, J. D., Wandell, B. A., & Pestilli, F. (2016). A major human white matter pathway between dorsal and ventral visual cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 26(5), 2205–2214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toribio, J. (forthcoming). Are visuomotor representations cognitively penetrable? Biasing action-guiding vision. Synthese, 1–19.

  • Toribio, J. (2018a). Implicit bias: From social structure to representational format. Theoria: An International Journal for Theory, History and Foundations of Science, 33(1), 41–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toribio, J. (2018b). Visual experience: Rich but impenetrable. Synthese, 195(8), 3389–3406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Polanena, V., & Davare, M. (2015). Interactions between dorsal and ventral streams for controlling skilled grasp. Neuropsychologia, 79(Part B), 186–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (2008). The way of the wanton. In C. Mackenzie & K. Atkins (Eds.), Practical identity and narrative agency. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiskrantz, L. (1986). Blindsight: A case study and implications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For helpful comments or discussion of issues addressed in this paper, I am grateful to three anonymous reviewers for this journal, Bartek Chomanski, Jonathan Cohen, Andy Cui, John Doris, Dimitria E. Gatzia, Sally Haslanger, Aleks Hernandez, Bob Kentridge, Casey Landers, Azenet Lopez, Eric Mandelbaum, Chris Peacocke, Jesse Prinz, David Rosenthal, Mark Rowlands, Michael Slote, Thomas Alrik Sørensen, and audiences at the 2017 Meeting of the SPP, the 2018 Meeting of the SSPP, Duke University, NYU, Stanford University, University of Miami, University of Missouri, St. Louis, University of Oslo, University of Aalborg, University of Washington University, St. Louis, Aarhus University, and the Center for Humanities Fellowship Recipients, University of Miami 2018–2019.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Berit Brogaard.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Brogaard, B. Implicit biases in visually guided action. Synthese 198 (Suppl 17), 3943–3967 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02588-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-020-02588-1

Keywords

Navigation