1 Introductory remarks: some kinds of definition

There are doubtless different ways in which the expression ‘definition by abstraction’ may be understood.Footnote 1 What I mean by it is definition by means of what are now widely known as abstraction principles, that is, principles of the form: \(\Sigma (\alpha )=\Sigma (\beta )\leftrightarrow Eq(\alpha ,\beta )\), where Eq is to be understood as an equivalence relation on entities of the type of \(\alpha \) and \(\beta \) and, if all goes well, \(\Sigma \) can be taken to be a function from entities of that type to objects. The principle is understood as equivalent to its universal closure with respect to \(\alpha \) and \(\beta \), which may be first- or higher-order variables. This fixes the order of the abstraction. Thus, to give some well-known examples:

Directions::

The direction of line a = the direction of line b iff lines a and b are parallel

with the universal closure: \(\forall x\forall y(Dir(x)=Dir(y)\leftrightarrow x//y)\) is a first-order abstraction, while:

Hume’s principle::

The number of Fs = the number of Gs iff the Fs correspond 1-1 with the Gs

with the universal closure: \(\forall F\forall G(NxF(x)=NxG(x)\leftrightarrow Eq_{x}(F(x),G(x)))\) is second-order.

At least in the context of the neo-Fregean programme, definition by abstraction is viewed as a form of implicit definition which we may employ to establish the meaning of fundamental terms for certain mathematical theories. In the case on which most work has been done, and on which most critical attention has been focused, the idea has been that Hume’s principle may be used to fix the meaning of the number operator \(Nx{\ldots }x{\ldots }\), in terms of which the singular term ‘0’, and the predicates ‘...is a cardinal number’, ‘...precedes_ _’, ‘...ancestrally precedes_ _’, and ‘...is a natural number’ may then be defined in well-known ways:

\(\textit{Cardinal}(x)=_\textit{df}\exists F(x=NxF(x))\)

\(0=_{df}Nx:x\ne x\)

\(P(x,y)=_\textit{def}\exists F\exists z(F(z)\wedge x=Nu(F(u)\wedge u\ne z)\wedge y=NuF(u))\)

\(P^{*}(x,y)=_\textit{df}\forall F((F(x)\wedge \forall u\forall v(F(u)\wedge P(u,v)\rightarrow F(v)))\rightarrow F(y))\)

\(\textit{Natural}(x)=_{df}(x=0\vee P^{*}(0,x))\)

Our emphasis has generally been on the idea that in giving the implicit definition, what we do is to stipulate that the number operator is to mean whatever it needs to mean—no more, no less—for the sentence, Hume’s principle, to express a truth, when the other expressions involved are taken to have their already established meanings, and the syntax is taken at face value. Much discussion has accordlingly focused, quite rightly, upon the questions: Under what conditions, if any, can such a stipulation succeed in fixing a meaning for the definiendum? and: Are those conditions met, in the present case?Footnote 2

This stipulative conception of how Hume’s principle might be used as a definition is sometimes contrasted with what might be called an interpretative or hermeneutical conception, according to which the aim is rather to capture the meaning of an expression as it is already used. This is of a piece with what Quine, in ‘Two dogmas ...’, described as the kind of definition put forward by lexicographers, aimed at reporting pre-existing relations of synonymy, ‘implicit in general or preferred usage prior to [their] own work’ (Quine 1953, p. 24). Whether Hume’s principle could, with any plausibility, be seen as giving a definition of this sort is—in my view—not a question that is easily answered. The answer must be that it cannot, if we take Quine’s description as definitive—i.e. as requiring of an interpretative definition that it present one complete expression as synonymous with another. Such a definition is what would normally be classified as explicit, but Hume’s principle clearly cannot function as a definition in that sense. What Hume’s principle can be used to define, if it can serve as a definition at all, is the number operator; but it presents no expression as synonymous with it. If, instead, we take recording a pre-existing synonymy relation as inessential to an interpretative definition, we could consider whether Hume’s principle could be regarded as providing an interpretative definition for the expression ‘the number of ...’ (where the ... holds place for a count noun or noun-phrase), or perhaps of ‘the number of things which ...’ (where the ... holds place for a verb-phrase, i.e. a one-place predicate). Perhaps more plausibly, we could take the question to be whether the definitions of ‘cardinal number’ and ‘natural number’ based on the definition of the number operator by means of Hume’s principle can be regarded as capturing some already established meaning borne by these expressions. My impression is that some have thought the answer to this question is obvious: that they could not. I don’t myself think it is so obvious. A case which strikes me as relevantly similar to that of number is that of length. In that case, we have the noun ‘length’, which may function as a concrete noun (as in ‘he was holding a length of rope’), but also as an abstract one, as in ‘the length of my yacht is greater than the length of yours’; and we have the cognate expressions ‘the length of...’ and ‘... (is) as long as_ _’. It seems to me quite plausible that of these expressions, it is the last which is basic or fundamental. Roughly, what we learn first is how to make judgements of the forms ‘x is as long as y’, ‘x is shorter than y’, etc. Only once we have got the hang of these can we, by a kind of abstraction, come to understand talk of lengths—we learn that the length of x is the same as/less than/greater than that of y just when x is as long as/shorter than/longer than y; and by a further kind of abstraction, we come to talk of length and lengths without thinking of them as lengths of anything in particular. While there are doubtless differences between talk of length and talk of number, it does not seem to me obviously implausible that similar relations hold between the relational expression ‘...as many as_ _’, ‘the number of ...’ and ‘number’.

There is, of course, a kind of halfway house between stipulative and interpretative definition—what Carnap called explication. As Quine puts it, “In explication the purpose is not merely to paraphrase the definiendum into an outright synonym, but actually to improve upon the definiendum by refining or supplementing its meaning.” (Quine 1953, p. 25). Since both refinement and supplementation require that the pre-explicative meaning of the definiendum be, to some extent, preserved, one might think of explication as a kind of constrained or guided stipulation. Since the definition of the number operator, and the further definitions based on it, are clearly meant to preserve certain aspects of ordinary talk and thought about number and counting, there is, it seems to me, good reason to view them as explications in something like Carnap’s sense.

In all of these kinds of definition, the aim is to fix the meaning of a word or other expression. All are thus to be distinguished from, and contrasted with, definition in a more Aristotelian sense, sometimes called real, as opposed to verbal or nominal, definition, where what is defined is not the word or phrase, but the thing—what the word stands for or applies to. The aim of this kind of definition is to capture the essence or nature of whatever it is that the corresponding word stands for. Such a definition can be assessed as correct or incorrect, not in the sense that it captures or fails to capture the meaning of the word, but according as it is a true or false statement of what it is to be what the word stands for. Some of the theoretical identifications Kripke discusses in Naming and Necessity (Kripke 1980), although not expressly presented as such, may plausibly be seen as definitions of this kind:

Water is \(\hbox {H}_{2}\hbox {O}\)

Light is electromagnetic radiation between certain wavelengths

Heat is the motion of molecules

Lightning is an electrical discharge

Obviously these are only rough and ready, but they capture the essential ideas of more accurate scientific statements of the nature of water, light, etc., as contrasted with explanations of the ordinary meanings of the corresponding words.

The central question I wish to discuss concerns the relations between definition by abstraction and definition of this last kind. In particular, what is the relation between Hume’s principle, taken as an implicit definition of the number operator, along with the further definitions it supports (of cardinal and natural number predicates, etc.), on the one hand, and the essence or nature of the corresponding entities—the function from concepts or properties to objects, and those objects themselves, i.e. the cardinal numbers in general, and the natural numbers? Can the now familiar sequence of Fregean definitions serve both as fixing meanings and as definitions in the more Aristotelian sense, as correct statements of the essence of the numbers, etc.?

An obstacle to returning an affirmative answer seems to me to suggest itself right at the outset. Is there not a direct clash between treating something as a definition in accordance with the stipulative conception and treating it as a real definition? Doesn’t that require treating the definition, not as a stipulation of any sort, but as a true or false proposition aimed at articulating some independently constituted fact about the nature of the worldly correlate of the relevant word?

I believe this apparent tension can be resolved, and that its resolution can shed light both on the notion of a thing’s essence or nature—at least as I wish to understand this notion—and on an important part of the epistemology of essence. To prepare the ground for the resolution I shall propose, it will be useful to begin with the question: How, in general, are verbal and real definition related?

2 Aristotle and Locke

Although I shall not discuss the views of Aristotle, or those of Locke, at any length, the account I shall present has affinities with both, whilst diverging from both in important respects—so I think it will be useful to comment briefly on those aspects of their views which bear most closely on my main question.

2.1 Aristotle

Aristotle discusses both kinds of definition:

Since a definition is said to be an account of what something is, it is clear that one type will be an account of what its name, or some other name-like account, means – e.g. what triangle means. When we grasp that this exists, we seek why it is. But it is difficult to take anything in this way if we do not know that it exists (Barnes 1993, pp. 93b29–34)

This, as is typical of Aristotle’s logical works, is a very compressed statement. But it is clear enough that here he is talking, in part, about what is sometimes called nominal definition. On the plausible interpretation defended by Charles (2000, ch. 2), defining a word is the first preliminary step in a three-stage process which, if successful, culminates in the kind of definition Aristotle sees as the goal of scientific enquiry—an account of the nature or essence of what the word, with that meaning, stands for. The second, intermediate stage consists in verifying that the word, with that meaning, does indeed stand for something—it is only in regard to what exists that we can discover its nature, in Aristotle’s view. As my short quotation illustrates, he seems to identify the final stage—establishing the nature of something—with explaining why it exists. This may at first appear somewhat odd, but we can see roughly what he is driving at by considering some of his examples. Thus a little further on in Post.An. B10, he writes:

One definition of definition is the one we have just stated [i.e. saying what the word means]. Another is an account which shows why something exists. Hence the former type means something but does not prove it, whereas the latter will clearly be like a demonstration of what something is, differing in arrangement from a demonstration. For there is a difference between saying why it thunders and what thunder is. In the one case, you will say: Because fire is extinguished in the clouds. But: What is thunder?—A noise of fire being extinguished in the clouds. (Barnes 1993, pp. 93b38–94a7)

What he seems to mean here is that what the word ‘thunder’ means is ‘noise in the clouds’, whereas a definition of what thunder is will incorporate an explanation of this type of noise—it is noise made by fire being extinguished in the clouds. The explanation of thunder is repackaged, as it were, as its definition.

2.2 Locke

Locke discusses essence at length in the Essay BkIII, as part of his discussion of words. Central to his discussion is his distinction between ‘nominal’ and ‘real’ essence. But even before he makes that distinction, the central tenets of his position are laid down:

Words become general by being made the signs of general ideas: and ideas become general by separating from them the circumstances of time and place, and any other ideas that may determine them to be this or that particular existence. By this way of abstraction they are made capable of representing more individuals than one... (Locke 1924, III,3,6)

He that thinks general natures or notions are anything else but such abstract and partial ideas of more complex ones, taken at first from particular experiences, will, I fear, be at a loss where to find them ... This whole mystery of genera and species, which makes such a noise in the schools, and are, with justice, so little regarded out of them, is nothing else but abstract ideas, more lor less comprehensive, with names annexed to them. (op.cit., III,3,9)

... That then which general words signify, is a sort of things; and each of them does that by being a sign of an abstract idea in the mind: to which idea as things existing are found to agree, so they come to be ranked under that name; or, which is all one, be of that sort. Whereby it is evident, that the essence of the sorts ... are nothing else but these abstract ideas. (op.cit. III,3,12)

They [i.e. the abstract ideas, and so the essences of sorts of things] are the workmanship of the understanding, but have their foundation in the similitude of things. (op.cit. III,3,13)

After drawing the inevitable conclusion that each distinct abstract idea is a distinct essence, Locke finally comes to the distinction between nominal and real essences:

First, Essence may be taken for the being of anything, whereby it is what it is. And thus the real internal, but generally in substances unknown, constitution of things, whereon their discoverable qualities depend, may be called their essence ...

Secondly, ... [the word ‘essence’] has been almost wholly applied to the artificial constitution of genus and species. It is true, there is ordinarily supposed a real constitution of the sorts of things; and it is past doubt that there must be some real constitution, on which any collection of simple ideas coexisting must depend. But it being evident that things are ranked under names only as they agree in certain abstract ideas to which we have annexed those names, the essence of each genus or sort comes to be nothing but that abstract idea. ... These two sorts of essences, I suppose, may not unfitly be termed, the one the real, the other the nominal, essence. (op.cit. III,3,15)

Locke mainly discusses essence in connection with general terms for substances: here, Locke claims, real and nominal essence are quite different, and it is nominal essence on which he focuses attention, arguing that it is this which does all the important work, and that talk of real essences is idle and useless—in particular, his view seems to be that it is the abstract idea (i.e. the nominal essence) which defines what it is for something to be of a certain sort, such as man or horse—we need not trouble ourselves about the generally unknown (and, Locke seems sometimes to suggest, unknowable) internal constitution of things which causally explains the features we do know about.

2.3 Comments

There are important differences between Aristotle’s and Locke’s positions, symptomatic of a deep opposition between them. Both focus mainly on ‘substances’—in a sense of that term which covers both kinds or sorts of thing, such as horses and meteors, and kinds of stuff, such as gold and water—and on our words for them. But whereas for Aristotle, defining the term or word for something is merely a preliminary stage in the search for essence, for Locke it is the key. The important thing for him is the nominal essence; he does not deny that there is a real essence, and indeed insists that there must be ‘some real constitution, on which any collection of simple ideas coexisting must depend’. But in general, we do not know what that is, and its importance, if known, lies only in its providing a causal explanation of those ideas which collectively constitute the nominal essence. It remains Locke’s view that it is possession of those properties corresponding to those simple ideas which make up the abstract general idea—the nominal essence—which determine whether or not something is of a certain kind—and not the ‘real internal constitution’ on which those properties depend. His view thus stands opposed, not only to Aristotle’s, but also to the modern essentialist view promoted by Kripke, according to which the surface properties by which we generally identify natural kinds are not what make them what they are, that being rather the essential properties underlying and explaining presence of the surface properties in normal circumstances. On the Kripkean view, even if it is not naturally possible that things of stuff should be of a certain natural kind—be tigers, or gold, say—whilst lacking certain of those surface features, it is at least metaphysically possible; and conversely, it is metaphysically, even if not naturally, possible that there should be things possessing all the surface features, which are not of that kind (fool’s tigers or fool’s gold, say). But not on Locke’s view. Underlying this difference is a deeper divergence over essential modalities. For Kripke, as for Aristotle, the necessity with which things possess their essential properties is de re; but for Locke, it is de dicto. To be gold, say, is to conform to a certain abstract general idea which includes having a certain colour and weight, being fusible and fixed (i.e. able to be melted, but not evaporating or losing weight when heated), etc. As we might somewhat anachronistically put it, it is, for Locke, analytic that gold is yellow, heavy, fusible, etc. This is why Locke is so adamant that individuals cannot sensibly be taken to have essential properties:

That essence, in the ordinary use of the word, relates to sorts, and that it is considered in particular beings no farther than as they are ranked into sorts, appears from hence; that take but away the abstract ideas by which we sort individuals, and rank them under common names, and then the thought of anything essential to any of them instantly vanishes ... Let anyone examine his own thoughts, and he will find, that as soon as he supposes or speaks of essential, the consideration of some species, or the complex idea, signified by some general name, comes into his mind; and it is by reference to that, that this or that quality is said to be essential.

... to talk of specific differences in nature, without reference to general ideas and names, is to talk unintelligibly. For I would ask any one, What is sufficient to make an essential difference in nature, between any two particular beings, without any regard had to some abstract idea, which is looked upon as the essence and standard of a species? All such patterns and standards being laid quite aside, particular beings, considered barely in themselves, will be found to have all their qualities equally essential; and everything in each individual will be essential to it. Or, which is more, nothing at all. (op.cit. III,6,4–5)

There could not be a clearer rejection of de re necessity. Locke’s position is, in effect, an anticipation of that championed by Quine some two and a half centuries later: necessity resides, not in the things we talk about, but in the way we talk about them.Footnote 3

Although, in my view, Locke’s central claims about essence—driven by his animus against scholastic claims about it, cf. ‘This whole mystery of genera and species, which makes such a noise in the schools’—are mistaken, what he says about nominal and real essence in relation to non-substance terms merits separate comment. Immediately following the section in which he introduces his distinction, he remarks:

Essences being thus distinguished into nominal and real, we may farther observe, that in the species of simple ideas and modes, they are always the same; but in substances, always quite different. Thus a figure including a space between three lines, is the real as well as the nominal essence of a triangle; it being not only the abstract idea to which the general name is annexed, but the very essentia, or being of the thing itself, that foundation from which all its properties flow, and to which they are all inseparably annexed. (op.cit. III,3,18)Footnote 4

The kind of coincidence of nominal with real essence to which Locke here draws attention—or, what comes to essentially the same thing, agreement between verbal and real definition—seems to me quite certainly to occur, and indeed to be well illustrated by Locke’s own example. To give another, if we ask what it is to be a circle, a good answer is that it is a collection of all and only those points in a plane equidistant from some fixed point in the plane; but this answer is every bit as good, as an answer to the question: What does the term ‘circle’ mean? Similarly, to be a vixen is to be an adult female fox, and that is what ‘vixen’ means. Examples are easily multiplied. This happy coincidence, where real and verbal definitions may be given by the same words, is the starting point for my own answer to my leading questions.Footnote 5

3 A priori knowledge of essence

In many cases, then—or so I claim—a correct definition of what a word stands for may serve as a good definition of the word itself. But in many other cases, it will not. For example, a correct definition of the stuff, water, is probably something along the lines of: the liquid form of a substance composed of molecules consisting of two hydrogen atoms bonded with one oxygen atom; but this is not a good definition of the word ‘water’. You will easily think of other examples. There may also be—indeed, it seems to me that there are—examples where there may be no clear answer whether a correct definition of a thing is also a correct definition of the word, in part because word-meanings change over time, so that what starts out being a discovery about something’s nature may become part of what a word for it means. This might be the case with tigers, for example. A tiger is a large carnivorous mammal of the cat family, of the genus panthera, distinguished from other species by certain further characteristics, including its striped skin and coat. I doubt that the whole zoological definition would, even now, amount to a correct definition of the word, as used by most speakers. But it is quite plausible that it is now part of the word’s meaning that tigers are mammals and that they are large cats, even if it wasn’t when the word was first used.

The coincidence of correct verbal and real definition helps to explain how it is that, in some cases, we may have a priori knowedge of something’s essence or nature. The kind of explanation I have in mind is most readily illustrated by reference to cases in which we can give an explicit definition of a word. Thus we can define the noun ‘square’ by:

A square is a plane figure bounded by four straight sides of equal length meeting at right-angles

Such an explicit definition can always be rewritten as a biconditional:

\(\forall x(x\) is a square \(\leftrightarrow x\) is a plane figure bounded by four straight sides of equal length meeting at right-angles)

The definition tells us that being a plane figure, etc., is a necessary and sufficient condition for the noun ‘square’ to be correctly applied to something. But if the noun ‘square’ is correctly applicable to something, that thing is a square. So anyone who is in a position to give this definition of the word can recognize that being a plane figure, etc., is a necessary and sufficient condition for being a square—that is, that that is all there is to being a square. But to know that much is to know what it is to be a square. On the reasonable assumption that if all one needs to know, if one is to know a priori that p, is the meaning of some sentence S which expresses the proposition that p, such knowledge is a priori.Footnote 6 What could be easier?

Of course, we cannot always give explicit definitions. But I can see no reason why this simple and straightforward model for a priori acquistition of knowledge of essence should not be extended to other cases—both those in which, although we cannot explicitly define a word, we can give an implicit definition, and others in which neither kind of definition can be given. These cases can be illustrated by reference to our understanding of logical constants. We cannot define the truth-functional connectives explicitly. But provided that the meanings of some of them can be taken as already understood, we can implicitly or contextually define others. Thus taking words for negation and disjunction as already understood, we can implicitly define the truth-functional conditional by stipulating that \(A\rightarrow B\) is to be true iff \(\lnot A\vee B\) is. \(\rightarrow \) stands for a certain function from propositions to propositions. Someone who understands the implicit definition is able to recognize that the function for which it stands is that function which takes an ordered pair of propositions to a true proposition iff the first of them is false or the second is true. To know this is to know the essence of the truth-functional conditional. Supposing negation and disjunction to be our basic connectives, we cannot define either of them, either explicitly or implicitly. But we can learn what they mean. Anyone who knows what truth-functional disjunction means knows that \(A\vee B\) is true iff at least one of the pair AB is true. This knowledge of what the word means equips them to recognize that truth-functional disjunction is that function from propositions to propositions which takes a pair of propositions to a true proposition iff at least one of the pair is true.

If I am right, there are many cases in which a priori knowledge of essence can be based upon knowledge of the meanings of relevant words. Definition by abstraction can be seen as a special case. Hume’s principle, construed as an implicitly definitional stipulation, serves—if all goes well—to fix the meaning of the number operator. Once that is done, we may explicitly define

x is a cardinal number \(\leftrightarrow _\textit{def}\exists F(x=NxFx)\)

and

\(0=_\textit{def}Nx(x\ne x)\)

and finally

x is a natural number \(=_\textit{def}x=0\vee P^{*}(0,x)\)

where \(P^{*}\) is ancestral predecession, where, as Frege himself proposed, predecession is defined by:

Pxy \(=_\textit{def}\exists F\exists z(y=NuFu\wedge x=Nu(Fu\wedge u\ne z)\)

and its ancestral by:

\(P^{*}xy=\forall F((Fx \wedge \forall u\forall v((Fu\wedge Puv)\rightarrow Fv))\rightarrow Fy)\)

On the basis of these definitions one can gain knowledge a priori of the nature of cardinal and natural numbers.

4 Definition and essence

4.1 An obvious lacuna

If I am right, knowledge of essence in the kind of case in which my proposed explanation applies is much more easily obtained than in cases in which only a posteriori knowledge is possible. No painstaking empirical investigation or scientific breakthrough is required. Essence is, as it were, open to view. I think this explanation of how we may get a priori knowledge of essence is good as far as it goes. But it does not go far enough. There is, in particular, at least one further question which clamours for an answer: The explanation tells us how, when the definition of a word and a real definition of the thing for which it stands coincide, we can gain knowledge of the nature of the thing from our grasp of the meaning of the word. But how is this happy coincidence—between the definition of the word and the essence of the thing—itself to be explained? The meanings of words are, in some suitably broad sense, a matter of convention. We fix them, either expressly by explicit or implicit definition, or in less formal ways, by our ongoing linguistic practice. So how does it come about that in cases of the kind I have been discussing, we fix them so that they match up so well with the essence or nature of the things the words stand for?

4.2 Direction of fit

Put like that, the question is liable to appear intractable. For putting it like that assimilates the cases with which we are concerned to those involving natural kinds, which, we assume, have independently constituted natures which we seek to capture by investigation a posteriori. If we think of our cases on this model, preserving the same direction of fit, it may well seem that achieving fit, without empirical investigation, requires some mysterious kind of pre-established harmony. But that is, fairly obviously, the wrong picture. To a first approximation, we might say that the right picture reverses the direction of fit: it is not that we somehow miraculously fix meaning so that it conforms to an independently pre-determinate essence—instead, in these cases, we fix essence by fixing meaning. I will explain why this can only be at best a first approximation shortly.

If this alternative picture is approximately right, it immediately resolves the apparent tension noted previously, between endorsing the stipulative conception of how Hume’s principle may be used to define the number operator and regarding it and the further definitions based upon it as revealing essence. The tension results from a false assimilation to cases in which we seek to capture the essence of natural kinds. Cardinal and natural numbers are not natural kinds—at least not in the sense sense in which gold and tigers are. They are, as one might say, artificial kinds.

4.3 Some objections answered

That description risks misunderstanding of a sort that relates closely to a likely cause of resistance to the proposal that we fix essence by fixing meaning. If things of a certain sort—numbers, say—are an artifical kind, doesn’t that mean that they are mere artefacts, which would not exist, were it not for our activity? Mustn’t the view that we fix essence by fixing meaning carry with it an intolerable sacrifice of objectivity?

Soberly understood, the claim that, in certain cases, we fix essence need have no such unpalatable consequences. To explain why not, I shall draw on two points—one is a point about the specific character of definition by abstraction; the other is a more general point about properties.

The specific point about abstraction is one which Hale and Wright have emphasized on many occasions. Definition by abstraction creates no objects. What, if successful, it creates is only a concept. Or to put it more accurately, what it does is to fix the meaning of a term-forming operator, such as the number operator. It does this by fixing the condition for identities configuring singular terms formed by applying that operator to suitable arguments to be true. Such identities are to have the same truth-conditions as those of corresponding statements asserting those arguments to stand in a certain equivalence relation. The existence of referents for those terms—numbers, say—is required by the truth of such identities. If the definition succeeds, such identities are true iff the corresponding statements involving the relevant equivalence relation are. It follows that so long as it is a matter of objective, mind-independent fact that, say, there is a one-one correlation between the Fs and the Gs, the existence of the number of Fs and the number of Gs (and their identity) is an equally objective, mind-independent fact.

That point may be thought enough, by itself, to dispel any reasonable concern about loss of objectivity. But my more general point about properties is worth making, because it illuminates the kind of existence numbers, and other pure abstract objects, enjoy. As just noted, if Hume’s principle can be used to define the number operator, standing for a certain function from properties to objects, the existence of numbers depends only upon there being properties which are one-one correlated. No more is required for the existence of numbers than that of first-level properties and a certain second-level equivalence relation. According to the abundant or deflationary conception of properties and relations, no more is required for the existence of any purely general property or relation than that there could be a predicate with the appropriate satisfaction condition.Footnote 7 Provided that this very weak existence condition is met for some suitable purely general properties and the purely general relation of one-one correlation, no more is required for the existence of cardinal numbers. This brings out the sense in which numbers are ‘metaphysically lightweight’ objects. Numbers no more depend upon us for their existence than does the relation of one-one correlation or the purely general properties which stand in that relation. They all depend for their existence on the possibility of expressions of the appropriate logico-syntactic type having them as their semantic values, but the requisite facts about possibility are themselves in no way dependent upon us or any other thinkers and speakers. Provided that it is agreed that the kind of possibility involved in formulating the existence condition for general properties conforms to S5 principles, it can easily be shown that their existence, and hence that of numbers, is absolutely necessary.Footnote 8 To put the point slightly paradoxically, whilst we fix what it is to be a cardinal or natural number, their being is absolutely necessary and hence quite independent of merely contingent beings, such as—on one widely but, of course, not universally accepted view—we are!

4.4 Direction of fit again

Against the backdrop of the abundant conception of properties (and objects), it is easier to pinpoint what is wrong, and also what is right, in the suggestion that we fix essence by fixing meaning.Footnote 9 What is wrong with it is that it does insufficient justice to the fact that the properties that constitute a thing’s essence or nature exist quite independently of any definitional activity on our part. We fix the meaning of the word—‘square’ say—by stipulating that to be square, a plane figure must be composed of four sides of equal length meeting at right angles. But that there exists such a property—the property of being a figure so composed—is entirely independent of any such definition being given (though not, on the abundant conception, independent of the possibility of such a definition). What is right about it—or at least very nearly right—lies in the suggestion that there is little or no room for error. But the explanation how we achieve such a happy match between our definition and the essence is not that we fix the essence to suit our definition; it is rather that, given the abundant conception, we cannot very well miss the target. For according to that conception, provided that there could be a predicate with the appropriate satisfaction-condition, the existence of the corresponding property is guaranteed. Thus provided only that our purported definition is in good order, it cannot fail to pick out the requisite defining property.