Skip to main content
Log in

Simplicity and scientific progress in the philosophy of Philipp Frank

  • Published:
Studies in East European Thought Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Philipp Frank was a central figure in the Vienna Circle, but his ideas vary significantly from those of his peers. Despite the growing body of literature on Frank, his account of simplicity has not yet received the attention it deserves even though it succinctly captures many of the most distinctive elements of Frank’s philosophy of science. This is because Frank’s account of simplicity is not restricted to the epistemology of scientific theories; his treatment of simplicity provides us with a way of accounting for the influence of social and political agendas on the rejection of scientific theories. In this paper I trace the development of Frank’s account of simplicity from 1947 to 1954 and explain how social and political considerations came to inform his mature account in 1954. Furthermore, I demonstrate the continued relevance of Frank’s thought by showing that it can be helpfully applied to a contemporary issue associated with the rejection of scientific theories, identity protective cognition.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a more detailed account of Frank’s conception of school philosophy see (Frank 1930/1949), and for a contemporary discussion of school philosophy and it’s role in Frank’s thought, see (Uebel 2011).

  2. Readers should note that a 2014 meta-analysis, which included 15,660 respondents, confirmed these findings (Xue et al. 2014).

  3. It is also worth noting that this problem is not just a problem seen on the political right (i.e., political ideologies that value authority and individualism). Campbell and Kay (2014) have shown that individuals on both the political right and left may display “solution adverse” tendencies since they are both less willing to accept a scientific theory or claim if they are opposed to the associated policy solutions.

  4. Dake (1991) is used here because his work provided the foundations on which the study discussed above and (Xue et al. 2014) were built.

References

  • Campbell, T. H., & Kay, A. C. (2014). Solution aversion: On the relation between ideology and motivated disbelief. Journal of personality and social psychology, 107(5), 809.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dake, K. (1991). Orienting dispositions in the perception of risk an analysis of contemporary worldviews and cultural biases. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 22(1), 61–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1920/1954). Reconstruction in philosophy. New York: The New American Library.

  • Douglas, H. E. (2014). A history of the PSA before 1970. Philosophy of Science Association: History of the discipline. Available via http://www.philsci.org/about-the-psa/history-of-the-association. Cited October 22, 2014.

  • Einstein, A. (1912/1993). Report to the Philosophical Faculty of the German University on a successor to the chair of theoretical physics. In M. J. Klein, A. J. Kox & R. Schulmann (Eds.), The collected papers of Albert Einstein. Volume 5. The Swiss years: Correspondence, 19021914 (pp. 470–473). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Frank, P. (1930/1949). Physical theories of the twentieth century and school philosophy. In P. Frank (Ed.), Modern science and its philosophy (pp. 90–121). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Frank, P. (1947/1953). Einstein: His life and times. New York: A. A. Knopf.

  • Frank, P. (1949a). Modern science and its philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, P. (1949b). Introduction. In P. Frank (Ed.), Modern science and its philosophy (pp. 1–52). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, Ph. (1954). The variety of reasons for the acceptance of scientific theories. In Ph. Frank (Ed.), The validation of scientific theories (pp. 3–17). Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, P. (1956). The role of authority in the interpretation of science. Synthese, 10(1), 335–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haller, R. (1991). The first Vienna Circle. In T. Uebel (Ed.), Rediscovering the forgotten Vienna Circle. Austrian studies on Otto Neurath and the Vienna Circle (pp. 95–108). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, D. M., et al. (2007). Culture and identity protective cognition: Explaining the white male effect in risk perception. Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, 4(3), 465–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2003). On the Austrian roots of Logical Empiricism: The first Vienna Circle. In P. Parrini, M. Salmon, & W. Salmon (Eds.), Logical Empiricism. Historical and contemporary perspectives (pp. 67–93). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2005). Political philosophy of science in Logical Empiricism: The left Vienna Circle. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 36(4), 754–773.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. (2011). Beyond the formalist criterion of cognitive significance: Philipp Frank’s later antimetaphysics. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science, 1(1), 47–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xue, W., Hine, D. W., Loi, N. M., Thorsteinsson, E. B., & Phillips, W. J. (2014). Cultural worldviews and environmental risk perceptions: a meta-analysis. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 40, 249–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Amy Wuest.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wuest, A. Simplicity and scientific progress in the philosophy of Philipp Frank. Stud East Eur Thought 69, 245–255 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11212-017-9291-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11212-017-9291-z

Keywords

Navigation