Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

This paper focus on the problem posed by the rigidity of categories to the translation/transaction operation of the intercultural approach to law. This rigidity holds subjects back from leaving the more structured paradigms (moral, social, cultural, legal) of their culture. The first methodological issue this paper seeks to clarify is to place the problem of categories within a narrowly delimited research horizon in which this issue can be treated with an appropriate degree of scientific rigor. This need seems to find a solution in a shift from the strictly legal plane to the linguistic plane. In linguistic terms, one could observe categories as the articulation of certain linguistic signs (signifier/signified) to a high degree of abstraction and fixity of meaning. The question, then, is whether and how it is possible to overcome the resistance of this elementary unit of language. This opens to the legal-theoretical problem a strictly linguistic (semiological and semiotic) line of inquiry. The research idea of this contribution is that the linguistic sign has spaces of resilience that remain unknown to the semiological view but visible to a semiotic view. A ‘bridge’ between the abstraction of the semiotic level and the concreteness of the legal level can be find in the most recent developments of cultural anthropology, which will be used here. Following this approach and these tools the aim of this paper is to show the potential of the sign observed from a semiotic perspective in drawing intersubjective and even interspecific semiotic lines useful to intercultural law. The method adopted here consists of an epistemological pluralism that holds together semiotics, anthropology and law, thus showing the fruitfulness of an openly interdisciplinary approach.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I refer here in particular to Mario Ricca’s studies and his latest book [44].

  2. According to Aristotle, categories are supreme groups or genera that collect all the properties that can be predicated of being [3].

  3. I refer to the Kantian twelve categories [26].

  4. An aspect that was already clear to Kant [26]. On this topic, for the scientific relevance of the point of observation, see Schrödinger’s remarks [49: 344–347]. According to Schrödinger, the ‘brilliance’ of Kant’s position ‘lies in the idea that this unique object—spirit or world—may well be susceptible to other aspects that we cannot grasp and that do not involve the forms of space and time’, so that ‘there are probably other ways of manifestation beyond those represented by space and time’ ([49: 346]), and, one might add returning to the point discussed here, by the conceptual categories by which we normally refer to space and time.

  5. Ricca [44: 211].

  6. Saussure writes explicitly: ‘language is a social institution’ [48: 25]. The close relationship between society and language was also underlined by Benveniste, who wrote: ‘language, in fact, is for man the only means to reach another man, to transmit a message to him and to receive one in return. Thus, language places and presupposes the other. With language you immediately give society, which, in turn, brings together only through the use of shared signs of communication. With society language is immediately given. The two entities thus imply each other’ [6: 99].

  7. The signs were also defined by Saussure as the ‘concrete entities of the language’ [48: 125].

  8. See Saussure [48: 83].

  9. Saussure [48: 83–84].

  10. Saussure [43: 84].

  11. Saussure [48: 84].

  12. Saussure [48: 85].

  13. Saussure [48: 84].

  14. Saussure [48: 85].

  15. Saussure [48: 136]. Saussure also explains that ‘The characteristic role of language in the face of thought is not to create a physical material means for the expression of ideas, but to serve as an intermediary between thought and sound, in conditions such that their union necessarily leads to mutual delimitations of unity. Thought, chaotic by its nature, is forced to become specific by decomposing. There is therefore neither materialization of thoughts, nor spiritualization of sounds, but it is the fact, in some mysterious measure, that ‘sound thought’ implies divisions and that language elaborates its unity by forming between two amorphous masses’ [48: 137]. In different words, Benveniste expressed the same fact: ‘the spoken language undoubtedly serves to carry 'what we want to say'’, and this is certainly a ‘thought content’. But "This takes form only and only when it is uttered. It receives form from language and language, which is the matrix of every possible expression cannot be separated from it and cannot transcend it’ [6: 76]. Now, ‘this great structure [language], which contains in itself minor structures and of different levels, gives shape to the content of thought’. Therefore, concludes Benveniste, ‘the linguistic form […] is the condition of transmissibility of thought, but also and above all its condition of realization. We grasp thought only when it is already conforming to the patterns of language. Apart from this, there is only dark volition, impulse that resolves in gestures, mimicry. To a rigorous analysis of the data that we face, wondering if thought can do without language or circumvent it as an obstacle appears a meaningless question’ [6: 77].

  16. It is difficult to render in English—returning the semantic and phonetic proximity between the two different forms used in the continental context—the difference between ‘language’ as a conventional system of signs based on a given phonological system, and ‘language’, understood as a more general ability of expression that every living being—as we will see later—is able to have. Here, to refer specifically to the first meaning hereafter, the French term used by Saussure ‘langue’ will be used.

  17. Saussure [48: 137].

  18. The game of chess is a classic example of Saussure [48: 107–108].

  19. Saussure [48: 139].

  20. I assume here the concept of world as a totality of meaning for man, very close to the Heideggerian idea. According to Heidegger, indeed, world is the ‘existential determination of being-there’ [22: 99], the ‘experience of the context and in the context of life’ operated by being-there [17: 80], or the ‘horizon of human transcendence […] field of possibility toward which man is stretched’, [19, p. 109] whose ‘opening’ is possible only to language [2, p. 224].

  21. See Sapir and Wohrf [47], and Whorf [53].

  22. See Kant [26].

  23. The reference here is obviously to Einstein’s general relativity [16].

  24. A fruitful intuition of Jacques Lacan whose implications go beyond the psychoanalytic dimension. See Lacan [30], Recalcati [41], Bazzanella [5].

  25. For example, Benveniste considered a ‘misunderstanding’ the idea that ‘the temporal system of a language reproduces the nature of 'objective' time’, a misunderstanding due to the fact that it is ‘so strong the [wrong] propensity to see in language the mold of reality’. While rather, concludes Benveniste, ‘languages offer […] different constructions of the real’ [6: 38].

  26. Commenting on Heraclitus, physicist Erwin Schrödinger states: ‘the criterion of reality is only the fact of ‘being common’. Based on this we build the real world’. Now, this ‘common being’ is precisely what—we have seen it clearly explained by Saussure and Benveniste-is made possible and guaranteed by language. [49: 147].

  27. Sacco [46: 193].

  28. Wittgenstein [54: 59].

  29. Ricca [44: 211].

  30. Heidegger [23: 31]. This is the solution identified by Heidegger to get out of the conceptual fences of metaphysics [21: 71–86], which, after all, is the crystallization of (Western) language observed in the philosophical context, the historical-speculative horizon at the end of which, as Galimberti says, ‘language says only the word of the thought it calculates, and the thing, arranged in the enclosure of this language, no longer says about itself, but simply says its correspondence to the calculation of thought’ [19: 215]. So ‘the limitation […] is produced by that representational thinking which reduces and concludes the meaning of the things that appear in the circumscribed sphere of mathematical anticipations, which in themselves resolve all possible meaning and significance. the closed thinking of anticipatory representation arises when man no longer grasps himself in the world, but places the world before him and, objectifying it, disposes of it with a view to its use, its manipulation, its domination’ [19: 215]. So, the problem posed by the linguistic sign widens becoming the problem of representation and involves in depth the philosophical dimension. The question of representation is what will be analyzed below.

  31. See Schrödinger [49: 157–158].

  32. Whorf, who had a scientific background, explicitly related his studies of anthropology and linguistics to the developments of physics of his time. More specifically, Whorf realized that one of the greatest difficulties of physics of those years consisted in the availability of concepts to express the paradoxical relations of particles investigated by quantum mechanics. A solution could come, according to him, from languages other than those of the Indo-European family, accustomed to a rigid ‘spatialization’ of thought, that is to accord thought to the external three-dimensional spatial reality, but rather from exotic languages accustomed to conceiving time and space in a completely different way. This idea was based on Whorf’s deep study of the Hopi North American populations. See Whorf [53].

  33. In English, the difference between semiological and semiotic is difficult to return even conceptually, being the first approach linked to a tradition of research only continental, as will be shown later.

  34. See the entry ‘semiotics’ explained by Umberto Eco and Giovanna Cosenza in Nicola Abbagnano’s Dizionario di filosofia [1: 980–981].

  35. Saussure writes: ‘one can therefore conceive a science that studies the life of signs within the framework of social life; it could form a part of social psychology and, consequently, of general psychology; we will call it semiology. […] Linguistics is only a part of this general science’ [48: 26]. The ability to generalize this discipline is clearly understood by Saussure who states: ‘by this way not only will the linguistic problem [the nature of the linguistic sign] be clarified, but we think that considering the rites, customs etc. as signs, such facts will appear in another light, and one will then feel the need to group them in semiology and to explain them with the laws of this science’ [48: 27].

  36. Peirce [37: 228].

  37. Kohn [28: 29].

  38. Kohn [28].

  39. The book also attracted the attention of Philippe Descola, who wrote the preface to the French edition [29: 11–17].

  40. See Lévy-Bruhl [31, 32].

  41. A very current anthropological problem. Perhaps, the most well-known attempts outside the anthropological discipline are those of Descola [15] and Viveiros de Castro [52].

  42. Kohn [28: 133].

  43. See Kohn [28: 135].

  44. Kohn [28: 236].

  45. Kohn [28: 135].

  46. Kohn [28: 136].

  47. Chatenet and Di Caterino [7: 11].

  48. Chatenet and Di Caterino [7: 11].

  49. Kohn [28: 83].

  50. ‘Not only the representation is wider than we think, but also completely different’ [29: 123].

  51. Kohn [28: 84].

  52. A space not only metaphorical but also physical: the forest in which humans, animals and plants coexist and interact is the privileged field of these anthropological research.

  53. Kohn [28: 30].

  54. Kohn [28: 30].

  55. Kohn [28: 31].

  56. See Kohn [28: 50].

  57. Kohn [28: 31].

  58. Kohn [28: 32–37]. See also Peirce [37: § 2.248].

  59. Kohn [28: 32].

  60. Kohn [28: 33].

  61. Sacco [46: 190].

  62. See Kohn [28: 163]. In fact, in the French edition of his book, Kohn uses the expression ‘mettre à profit la forme’ that is, ‘to exploit the form’ [29: 218].

  63. See Kohn [28: 55].

  64. See Ricca [44: 227].

  65. The adjective ‘chorological’ is intended here to illuminate a horizon of research that can receive fruitful contributions from anthropology, law, philosophy, and in which physical space and semiotic dynamics are interconnected [44: 211]. As Mario Ricca specifies, ‘the term chorology [is] a word deeply engraved by historical lines and used, with respect to geography, for the analysis of places when considered for their dynamic, organic, ethological and cultural semantic projections’ [44: 226].

  66. See Ricca [44: 228].

  67. See Wittgenstein [54: 10–18].

  68. Kohn [28: 31–32].

  69. Kohn [28: 32].

  70. See Aristotle [4: 1254, 9–10].

  71. See Wittgenstein [54: 17].

  72. See Saussure [48: 29].

  73. Observing the question upside down one could observe, as Sergio Cotta does, that ‘going to the law is not going to a generic ‘thing’, but to a human ‘form of life’, that is, to man himself’ [11: 17].

  74. Kohn [28: 92].

  75. ‘Living beings are loci of selfhood’: this is the ‘general claim’ derived ‘empirically’ by Kohn [28: 94].

  76. Kohn [28: 34].

  77. Kohn [28: 56].

  78. See Kohn [28: 53–55], and Deacon [12, 13].

  79. See Kohn [28: 58].

  80. See Kohn [28: 58].

  81. See Kohn [28: 59].

  82. Kohn [28: 59].

  83. Ricca [44: 13].

  84. See Kohn [28: 59].

  85. Ricca also adds that ‘it is not, however, a kind of thirdness that includes the original spatial/semantic circuits and their differences by annihilating them. It is instead a horizontal one, in the sense that it makes it possible to identify the signical interfaces that are suitable to support the coexistence and the intermingling condensation of these spaces of meaning by preserving their recognizability. The process through which such thirdness will take shape will inevitably produce some changes and make itself a hub for further semiotic relationships. This step, however, will fuel, in turn, new differentiations that trigger the request for new translations along a semiotic direction, virtually without end’. Ricca [44: 235].

  86. See Cotta [11: 68, 80–81], see also Villey [51].

  87. See Kohn [28: 55].

  88. See Cotta [11: 142–152].

  89. See Hénaff [24: 254].

  90. Hénaff [24: 254].

  91. See Hénaff [24: 256].

  92. Hénaff [24: 257].

  93. Hénaff [24: 257].

  94. See Villey [51].

  95. See Hénaff [24: 257–258].

  96. See Cotta [11: 67–68, 138].

  97. See Kohn [28: 16].

  98. Kohn [28: 94].

  99. Kohn [28: 92].

  100. See Kohn [28: 71–81].

  101. See Ciaramelli and Menga [8], Pomarici [38], Slobodian [50].

  102. See Jonas [25].

  103. Ricca [44: 340].

  104. Ricca [44: 298].

  105. See Corrias [10: 894–895].

  106. See Corrias [10: 896–897].

  107. Since ‘it could be said that constitutional enunciations are the bricks; and the edifice of subjectivity requires their utilization within the processes of democratic integration’, Ricca [42: 38].

  108. See Pulcini [39, 40].

  109. See Pope Francis [18].

  110. Ricca [43: 129].

  111. See Colli [9].

  112. He meant the Greek verb ‘φαίνεσθαι’. See Heidegger [22: 56].

  113. Heidegger [22: 57].

  114. Typical examples in anthropology are the notions of ‘prelogism’ or ‘totemism’. For a critical perspective on these concepts see, respectively, Keck [27] and Lévi-Strauss [33].

  115. See Ricca [44: 165].

  116. See De Santillana [14].

  117. See Ricca [44: 189–199].

  118. About this concept see Rouland [45: 332–338].

  119. See Ricca [42: 250–252].

  120. Neuwirth [36: 44].

  121. See Neuwirth [35; 36].

  122. See Neuwirth [36: 40, 50].

  123. See Neuwirth [36: 45–46].

  124. See Schrödinger [49: 20–36].

  125. See Neuwirth [36].

  126. Neuwirth [36: 46].

  127. Neuwirth [36: 50].

  128. Neuwirth [36: 52].

  129. A contribution both critical (‘krínein’: separate to better understand and judge), to observe what we already have and denounce what we lack, both speculative, to discover what the Others have realized and/or developed of useful to our current purposes.

  130. Neuwirth [34: 48].

  131. Neuwirth [36: 51].

  132. I refer for example to Malinowski [34].

  133. See Ricca [44: 277].

  134. See Ricca [44: 291–304].

  135. About this concept see Glenn [20: 23–71].

References

  1. Abbagnano, N. 2013. Dizionario di filosofia. Torino: Utet.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Amoroso, L. 2005. Arte, poesia e linguaggio. In Guida a Heidegger, ed. Volpi, F., 209–234. Bari-Roma: Laterza.

  3. Aristotele. 1984. Opere – Organon. Bari: Laterza.

  4. Aristotele. 2007. Politica. Bari-Roma: Laterza.

  5. Bazzanella, E. 2011. Lacan. Immaginario, simbolico e reale in tre lezioni. Trieste: Asterios.

  6. Benveniste, É. 2009. Essere di parola. Semantica, soggettività, cultura. Milano: Mondadori.

  7. Chatenet, L., and A. Di Caterino. 2020. L’horizon sémiotique de l’anthropologie: Paradoxes du ‘tournant ontologique.’ Actes Semiotiques 123: 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ciaramelli, F., and F.G. Menga. 2021. Introduzione. L’interrogazione filosofico-giuridica sugli obblighi verso le generazioni future - Il diritto di fronte al futuro. Cicerone filosofo del diritto. Rivista di filosofia del diritto 2: 254–256.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Colli, G. 2019. La nascita della filosofia. Milano: Adelphi.

  10. Corrias, D.A.L. 2023. Environmental law and youth protests: Future generations. Between speech acts and political representation. International Journal of the Semiotic of Law 36: 893–906.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Cotta, S. 1991. Il diritto nell’esistenza. Linee di ontofenomenologia giuridica. Milano: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Deacon, T.W. 2003. The hierarchic logic of emergence: Untangling the interdipendence of evolution and self-organization. In Evolution and learning: The Baldwin effect reconsidered, ed. B.H. Weber and D.J. Depew, 273–308. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  13. Deacon, T.W. 2012. Incomplete Nature: How Mind Emerged from Matter. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  14. De Santillana, G. Le origini del pensiero scientifico. Milano: Adelphi.

  15. Descola, Ph. 2005. Par-delà nature et culture. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Einstein, A. 1920. Relativity: The Special and General Theory. New York: H. Holt and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Fabris, A. 2005. L’‘ermeneutica della fatticità’ nei corsi friburghesi dal 1919 al 1923. In Guida a Heidegger, ed. Volpi, F., 59–111. Bari-Roma: Laterza.

  18. Francesco. 2015. Laudato si’. Lettera enciclica sulla cura della casa comune. Roma: Paoline Editoriale Libri.

  19. Galimberti, U. 2020. Heidegger e il nuovo inizio. Il pensiero al tramonto dell’Occidente. Milano: Feltrinelli.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Glenn, H.P. 2011. Tradizioni giuridiche nel mondo. La sostenibilità della differenza. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Heidegger, M. 2001. Che cos’è metafisica. Milano: Adelphi.

  22. Heidegger, M. 2006. Essere e tempo. Milano: Mondadori.

  23. Heidegger, M. 2022. In cammino verso il linguaggio. Milano: Mursia.

  24. Hénaff, M. 2018. Il dono dei filosofi. Ripensare la reciprocità. Pisa: Ets.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Jonas, H. 2009. Il principio responsabilità. Torino: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Kant, I. 2005. Critica della ragion pura. Bari-Roma: Laterza.

  27. Keck, F. 2008. Lévy-Bruhl: Entre philosophie et anthropologie, contradiction et participation. Paris: Cnrs.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  28. Kohn, E. 2013. How Forests think. Toward an Anthropology beyond the Human. California-US: University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  29. Kohn, E. 2017. Comment pensent les forêts. Vers une anthropologie au-delà de l’humain. Bruxelles: Zones Sensibles.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Lacan, J. 2006. Dei Nomi del Padre - Il trionfo della religione. Torino: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Lévy-Bruhl, L. 1985. How Natives Think. Princeton-US: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Lévy-Bruhl, L. 2019. Primitive Mentality. UK: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Lévi-Strauss, C. 1962. Le totémisme aujourd’hui. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Malinowski, B. 2020. Crime and custom in savage society. Milano: Mimesis.

  35. Neuwirth, R.J. 2018. Law in the Time of Oxymora. A Synaesthesia of Language, Logic and Law. New York: Routledge.

  36. Neuwirth, R.J. 2022. Future Law, the Power of Prediction, and the Disappearance of Time. Law, Technology and Humans 4–2: 38–59.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Peirce, C.S. 1932. The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Vol. II. Cambridge (MA).

  38. Pomarici, U. 2021. Natura umana, intersoggettività, idea del futuro. Alle soglie della responsabilità intergenerazionale. Rivista di filosofia del diritto 2: 257–267.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Pulcini, E. 2009. La cura del mondo. Paura e responsabilità nell’età globale. Torino: Bollati Boringhieri.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Pulcini, E. 2020. La sfida ecologica: Un cambio di paradigma? Iride 2: 237–249.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Recalcati, M. 2019. Il vuoto e il resto. Il problema del reale in Jacques Lacan. Milano: Mimesis.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ricca, M. 2008. Oltre Babele. Codici per una democrazia interculturale. Bari: Dedalo.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ricca, M. 2013. Culture interdette. Modernità, migrazioni, diritto interculturale. Torino: Bollati Boringhieri.

  44. Ricca, M. 2023. Intercultural Spaces of Law. Translating Invisibilities. Cham-Switzerland: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  45. Rouland, N. 1992. Antropologia giuridica. Milano: Giuffrè.

  46. Sacco, R. 2007. Antropologia giuridica. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Sapir, E., Whorf, B.L. 2017. Linguaggio e relatività. Roma: Castelvecchi.

  48. Saussure, F. de. 1967. Corso di linguistica generale. Bari: Laterza.

  49. Schrödinger, E. 2017. L’immagine del mondo. Torino: Bollati Boringhieri.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Slobodian, L. 2020. Defending the future: Intergenerational equity in climate litigation. Georgetown Environmental Law Review 32: 569–589.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Villey, M. 1986. La formazione del pensiero giuridico moderno. Milano: Jaca Book.

  52. Viveiros de Castro, E. 2014. Cannibal Metaphysics: For a Post-structural Anthropology. Minnesota: Univocal.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Whorf, B.L. 2018. Linguaggio, pensiero e realtà. Torino: Bollati Boringhieri.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Wittgenstein, L. 2014. Ricerche filosofiche. Torino: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ishvarananda Cucco.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cucco, I. Below and Beyond the Signifier: Space as a Living Semiotic Horizon, a Key to Interculturality and a Challenge for Law. Int J Semiot Law (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-024-10106-6

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-024-10106-6

Keywords

Navigation