Skip to main content
Log in

The essence of agency is discovered, not defined: a minimal mindreading argument

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I give a novel argument for this view that the AGENT concept has an externalist semantics. The argument argues the conclusion from two premises: first, that our first relationships to agents is through a subpersonal mechanism which requires for its function an agential proto-concept which refers directly; and second, that there is a continuity of reference between this proto-concept and the mature concept AGENT. I argue the first on the basis of results in the developmental psychology of social cognition. I argue the second on the basis of a process of elimination, by considering three possibilities for the relationship between the two concepts. On the basis of these two premises the conclusion is drawn that AGENT is a concept that refers directly. That has the following consequences for the philosophy of action: first, that “action” is not an appropriate term for reductive analysis, as the causal theory of action assumes; and second, that we should be looking to the appropriate empirical disciplines for an elucidation of the concept.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Despite a relatively broad consensus regarding the externalist semantics of natural kind terms, there also exists a neo-descriptivist position that can accommodate the externalist critique of traditional descriptivism (e.g. Jackson 1998). I excuse myself from having to argue for externalism per se, however. I merely wish to show that AGENT specifically is most plausibly conceived as having an externalist semantics.

  2. I follow this convention: words in caps refer to a concept (AGENT), words in double quotes refer to a linguistic term (“agent”), and when the same word is given without any apparatus I will mean the referent itself (agent).

  3. These mirror objections anticipated by Shea and Bayne (2010) in their discussion of consciousness.

  4. One might object at this point that attribution of goals requires attribution of goal-state representations that are distinct from the movement. But recent work in the neuroscience of action planning and perception appears to show that bodily movements are intrinsically coded as goal-directed, so that no additional goal-state representation would be needed (Rizzolatti and Sinigaglia 2010; cf. Butterfill and Apperly 2016).

  5. It may be that other agents can themselves exist in another agent’s field. But that does not level the distinction between agents and objects: agents can have fields, whereas objects cannot.

  6. This animation can be viewed at https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=VTNmLt7QX8E.

  7. This does not mean that everything to which we attribute agency is in fact an agent. It may be that M has evolved such that it has a tendency to over-attribute agency. But that does not mean that the reference of AGENT could not be determined on the basis of the cases in which M attributes agency correctly. In any case, even our reaction to the Heider–Simmel animation is reliable in a derivative sense, given that it was an agent who produced this animation.

  8. “Reference-borrowing” of this kind is mostly discussed with respect to social contexts where usage of a rigid designator is passed from user to user. (Consider my example of the proper name “Mars,” above.) But there is no reason why reference-borrowing could not occur for a concept that is used by different cognitive systems within a single mind. On this, see Recanati (2012).

  9. In a forthcoming paper, Oisin Deery defends the view that freely willed actions constitute a natural kind in Boyd’s sense. Although Boyd’s account of natural kinds is independently attractive, I am much inspired by Deery’s approach.

  10. That this is a theory about the meaning of “action” rather than an empirical hypothesis can be seen from the fact that causally deviant chains are used to object against the theory on the grounds that in these cases the putatively sufficient conditions for action are satisfied but we intuitively feel that an action has not taken place. If the theory was empirical, then this sort of objection would lack force.

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Apperly, I. A., & Butterfill, S. A. (2009). Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychological Review, 116, 953–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. C. (1989). Natural agency: An essay on the causal theory of action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1991). Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61, 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–185). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bugnyar, T., Reber, S. A., & Buckner, C. (2016). Ravens attribute visual access to unseen competitors. Nature Communications, 7, 10506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Apperly, I. A. (2013). How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind and Language, 28, 606–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Apperly, I. A. (2016). Is goal ascription possible in minimal mindreading? Psychological Review, 123, 228–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12, 187–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2012). Perceiving the intended model. In A. Raftopoulos & P. Machamer (Eds.), Perception, realism, and the problem of reference (pp. 96–122). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2016). Two systems for mindreading? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 7, 141–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N. S., Dally, J. M., & Emery, N. J. (2007). Social cognition by food-caching corvids: The western scrub-jay as a natural psychologist. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 362, 507–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons, and causes. Journal of Philosophy, 60, 685–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deery, O. (2015). The fall from Eden: Why libertarianism isn't justified by experience. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93, 319–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiCarlo, J. J., Zoccolan, D., & Rust, N. C. (2012). How does the brain solve visual object recognition? Neuron, 73, 415–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan, K. S. (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review, 75, 281–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heider, F., & Simmel, M. (1944). An experimental study of apparent behaviour. American Journal of Psychology, 57, 243–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heller, M. (1996). The mad scientist meets the robot cats: Compatibilism, kinds, and counterexamples. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56, 333–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L. (2000). Is responsibility essentially impossible? Philosophical Studies, 99, 229–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCormick, K. A. (2015). Companions in innocence: Defending a new methodological assumption for responsibility theorising. Philosophical Studies, 172, 515–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M., & Pereboom, D. (2016). Free will: A contemporary introduction. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2015). Bound: Essays on free will and moral responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, L. (2017). Actions as prime. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 80, 265–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, K., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-olds understand false beliefs? Science, 308, 255–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1970). Is semantics possible? Metaphilosophy, 1, 187–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, 131–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2012). Mental files. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., & Sinigaglia, C. (2010). The functional role of the parieto-frontal mirror circuit: Interpretations and misinterpretations. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11, 264–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N., & Bayne, T. (2010). The vegetative state and the science of consciousness. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 459–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sims, A. (in press). Agency and the metaphysics of nature. Australasian Philosophical Review, 3(1).

  • Steward, H. (2012). A metaphysics for freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2013a). Building better beings: A theory of moral responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2013b). If free will doesn’t exist, neither does water. In G. Caruso (Ed.), Exploring the illusion of free will (pp. 177–202). Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H., Cross, D., & Watson, J. (2001). Meta-analysis of theory-of-mind development: The truth about false belief. Child Development, 72, 655–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1958). Philosophical investigations (2nd ed.) (G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Helen Steward and my colleagues at CEFISES for comments and advice on an earlier version of this paper. This work was funded by the Action Recherche Concertée “Free Will and Causality.”

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew Sims.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sims, A. The essence of agency is discovered, not defined: a minimal mindreading argument. Philos Stud 176, 2011–2028 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1108-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-018-1108-5

Keywords

Navigation