Skip to main content
Log in

Social construction as grounding; or: fundamentality for feminists, a reply to Barnes and Mikkola

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Feminist metaphysics is guided by the insight that gender is socially constructed, yet the metaphysics behind social construction remains obscure. Barnes and Mikkola charge that current metaphysical frameworks—including my grounding framework—are hostile to feminist metaphysics. I argue that not only is a grounding framework hospitable to feminist metaphysics, but also that a grounding framework can help shed light on the metaphysics behind social construction. By treating social construction claims as grounding claims, the feminist metaphysician and the social ontologist both gain a way to integrate social construction claims into a general metaphysics, while accounting for the inferential connections between social construction and attendant notions such as dependence and explanation. So I conclude that a grounding framework can be helpful for feminist metaphysics and social ontology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this vein Butler (1990: 7; cf. Ásta 2011) says: “Perhaps this construct called ‘sex’ is as culturally constructed as gender… with the consequence that the distinction between sex and gender turns out to be no distinction at all.” Thus Butler accepts Gender but holds that sex is socially constructed too.

  2. For instance, Alcoff (2006: 172) holds that gender has a partly biological basis.

  3. For a more detailed discussion of this notion of grounding, see Schaffer (2009) and (2016). See Koslicki (2016) for critical discussion. See also Wilson (2014) (and the follow-up debate in Schaffer forthcoming and Wilson forthcoming) for concerns about the unity of grounding.

  4. Of course I cannot prove the negative existential that there is no reductive conceptual analysis of grounding to be found (though when has reductive conceptual analysis ever succeeded?) I only mean to say that it is legitimate to use the concept regardless, without any such analysis to hand.

  5. According to Kim (1994; cf. Salmon 1984), the lesson to be drawn from the failure of deductive-nomological accounts of explanation is that explanations must be backed by dependencies, to provide direction and linkage. Grounding is a form of dependence. In this vein Audi (2012: 104) says: “The reason we must countenance grounding is that it is indispensable to certain important explanations.”

  6. I think that Socially constructed fits Haslanger’s (1995: 30) description of gender as “a constitutive social construction,” Haslanger and Ásta’s (2011: §2.3) notion of “social constitution,” and Ásta’s (2011, 2013) notion of gender as “conferred,” by which she means (2011: 62) that gender is “dependent in some way on human thoughts, attitudes, and practices,” and (2013: 219) that gender is “a property that something has in virtue of some attitude, action, or state of subjects, or group of subjects.” On this point I agree with Mikkola (2015: 8), who comments: “rewriting Haslanger’s definition in grounding terms (I submit) is faithful to the original.” I also think that Socially constructed fits Bennett’s (Bennett 2011a) general conception of a “building” relation, where being constructed is equated with being built.

  7. Thus Barnes (2014: 337) explains Haslanger’s view as follows: “Social structures are created by complex, repeated patterns of human social interaction.” Barnes (2016: §4.2) gives the causal analogy of wheel ruts. The connection between American society and {American society} is more of an automatic mathematical relation, and has nothing much to do with complex, repeated patterns of social interaction which constitute social routines.

  8. Work on social ontology before the (re-)turn to grounding (e.g., Searle 1995) makes use of inadequate conceptions of dependence like supervenience. But insofar as grounding supersedes supervenience (Sect. 2.1), such work can be understood to be pointing towards a grounding based approach.

  9. See Sider (2016) for his reply to these concerns.

  10. For instance, Horgan and Potrč (2012) and I (Schaffer 2012) debate whether—on the shared “monistic” premise that the whole cosmos is fundamental—one should also posit non-fundamental parts to the cosmos. I argue for parts, to support Moorean truisms about hands, and provide extensions for referential semantics. And elsewhere I object to Sider’s (2011) refusal of non-fundamental entities, arguing (2013: 750) that “Nonfundamental entities are explanatorily fruitful posits.”

  11. I have changed the example. Barnes (2014: 342–5) considers a debate between Haslanger and Jenkins as to the status of trans women who do not “pass” as cis women. But the underlying point should be the same.

  12. I was initially inclined to be more concessionary to Barnes with respect to the Haslanger-Stone debate, but I thank Asya Passinsky (personal communication) for convincing me that the “intermediate grounding steps move” works there too.

  13. My thanks to Ásta Sveinsdóttir (personal communication) for helping me get the details right.

  14. Witt (2011) embraces the gender essentialist view that one’s gender is part of what makes one the social individual one is. So for Witt one cannot endure changing one’s gender at all. (For her successful gender reassignment surgery would destroy the old social individual and create a distinct social individual.) So Witt too comes out as holding a distinctive position on the grounds of gender. (Two caveats: first, Witt considers the idea that “transgender” may count as a third gender, in which case a transgendered social individual may preserve their gender; secondly, Witt distinguishes the social individual from both the human organism and the person, so she can allow that the human organism and person survive even if the old social individual does not.) What matters for present purposes is that a grounding framework can succeed in distinguishing different views about the nature of gender.

  15. In a nutshell, Bennett and deRosset accept that the whole grounds necessitate the grounded output, while Mikkola argues that the relevant social relations are contingent. After all, she (2015: 12) reasons: “Perhaps all money has been abolished via political–institutional means even though (in the short run) the appropriate acceptance-dependence still obtains: we accept that certain pieces of paper count as money; the revolution simply destroyed all those pieces of paper!” But I think that Mikkola simply has not specified the whole social grounds fully. The whole grounds must include the political-institutional matters as well, since (by hypothesis) this is a further matter on which the existence of money depends.

  16. One immediate problem is that there are other views of what grounds the grounding facts that Mikkola does not consider (cf. Dasgupta 2014). But for me the deeper problem is that I just don’t see a connection between any alleged failure of the Bennett-deRosset view, and the claim that grounding is normatively loaded.

  17. This paper grew out of comments on Elizabeth Barnes’s “Realism and Social Structure” and Mari Mikkola’s “Non-Ideal Metaphysics: On the Apparent Antagonism between Feminist and Mainstream Metaphysics,” delivered at the 2015 Pacific APA. Thanks to Elizabeth Barnes and Mari Mikkola, and also to Louise Antony, Janelle Derstine, Aaron Griffith, Ron Mallon, Rebecca Mason, Asya Passinsky, Laurie Paul, Ted Sider, Jason Stanley, Ásta Sveinsdóttir, and Charlotte Witt.

References

  • Alcoff, L. (2006). Visible identities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (1995). Knowledge, human interests, and objectivity in feminist epistemology. Philosophical Topics, 23, 27–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ásta, S. (2008). Essentially conferred. Philosophical Studies, 140, 135–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ásta, S. (2011). The metaphysics of sex and gender. In C. Witt (Ed.), Feminist metaphysics: Explorations in the ontology of sex, gender and the self (pp. 47–66). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ásta, S. (2013). The social construction of human kinds. Hypatia, 28, 716–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, P. (2012). A clarification and defense of the notion of grounding. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding: Understanding the structure of reality (pp. 101–121). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. (2014). Going beyond the fundamental: Feminism in contemporary metaphysics. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 114, 335–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. (2016). Realism and social structure. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-016-0743-y.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2011a). Construction area (no hard hat required). Philosophical Studies, 154, 79–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2011b). By our bootstraps. Philosophical Perspectives, 25, 27–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. Londone: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2008). Truthmakers and ontological commitment: Or how to deal with complex objects and mathematical ontology without getting into trouble. Philosophical Studies, 140, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2005). Existential dependence and cognate notions. Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, S. (2014). The possibility of physicalism. Journal of Philosophy, 111, 557–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Beauvoir, S. (2011) [1949]. The second sex, trans. Constance Borde and Sheila Malovany-Chevallier. Vintage Books.

  • deRosset, L. (2013). Grounding explanations. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13, 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diaz-Leon, E. (2013). What is social construction? European Journal of Philosophy. doi:10.1111/ejop.12033.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorr, C. (2005). What we disagree about when we disagree about ontology. In M. E. Kalderon (Ed.), Factionalism in metaphysics (pp. 234–286). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, B. (2015). The ant trap: Rebuilding the foundations of the social sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2001). The question of realism. Philosophers’ Imprint, 1, 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2012). Guide to ground. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding: Understanding the structure of reality (pp. 37–80). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Griffith, A. (manuscript). Social construction and grounding.

  • Hacking, I. (1999). The social construction of what?. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (1995). Ontology and social construction. Philosophical Topics, 23, 95–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2000). Gender, race: (What) are they? (What) do we want them to be? Nous, 34, 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2004). Future genders? Future races? Philosophical Exchange, 34, 5–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2011). Ideology, generics, and common ground. In C. Witt (Ed.), Feminist metaphysics: Explorations in the ontology of sex, gender and the self (pp. 179–208). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S., & Sveinsdóttir, Á. (2011). Feminist metaphysics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/feminism-metaphysics/.

  • Horgan, T., & Potrč, M. (2012). Existence monism trumps priority monism. In P. Goff (Ed.), Spinoza on monism (pp. 51–76). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (Ed.). (1993). Postscripts on supervenience. In Supervenience and mind: Selected philosophical essays (pp. 161–74). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Kim, J. (1994). Explanatory knowledge and metaphysical dependence. Philosophical Issues, 5, 51–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a physical world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2016). Where grounding and causation part ways: Comments on Schaffer. Philosophical Studies, 173, 101–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, A. (2013). Social constructivism and the philosophy of science. Londone: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. (2004). Projection and objectification. In B. Leiter (Ed.), The future for philosophy (pp. 285–303). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (1990). Science as social knowledge: Values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mallon, R. (2013). Naturalistic approaches to social construction. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/social-construction-naturalistic/.

  • Mikkola, M. (2011). Ontological commitments, sex and gender. In C. Witt (Ed.), Feminist metaphysics: Explorations in the ontology of sex, gender and the self (pp. 67–84). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mikkola, M. (2015). Doing ontology and doing justice: What feminist philosophy can teach us about meta-metaphysics. Inquiry. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2015.1083469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mikkola, M. (2016). Non-ideal metaphysics: On the apparent antagonism between feminist and mainstream metaphysics. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-016-0732-1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Passinsky, A. (manuscript). Plenitude, normativity and social objects.

  • Rosen, G. (2010). Metaphysical dependence: Grounding and reduction. In B. Hale & A. Hoffmann (Eds.), Modality: Metaphysics, logic, and epistemology (pp. 109–136). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). On what grounds what. In D. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 347–383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2012). Why the world has parts: Reply to Horgan and Potrè. In P. Goff (Ed.), Spinoza on monism (pp. 77–91). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2013). Metaphysical semantics meets multiple realizability. Analysis Reviews, 73, 736–751.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2016). Grounding in the image of causation. Philosophical Studies, 173, 49–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (forthcoming). Ground rules: Lessons from Wilson. In: K. Aizawa & C. Gillett (Eds.), Composition and ground. Palgrave-MacMillan.

  • Searle, J. (1995). The social construction of reality. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2016). Comments on Barnes and Mikkola. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-016-0739-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stone, A. (2007). An introduction to feminist philosophy. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2014). No work for a theory of grounding. Inquiry, 57, 535–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (forthcoming). The priority and unity arguments for grounding. In K. Aizawa, & C. Gillett (Eds.), Scientific composition and metaphysical ground. Palgrave-MacMillan.

  • Witt, C. (2011). What is gender essentialism? In C. Witt (Ed.), Feminist metaphysics: Explorations in the ontology of sex, gender and the self (pp. 11–26). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Schaffer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Schaffer, J. Social construction as grounding; or: fundamentality for feminists, a reply to Barnes and Mikkola. Philos Stud 174, 2449–2465 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0738-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0738-8

Keywords

Navigation