Skip to main content
Log in

Depth and deference: When and why we attribute understanding

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Four experiments investigate the folk concept of “understanding,” in particular when and why it is deployed differently from the concept of knowledge. We argue for the positions that (1) people have higher demands with respect to explanatory depth when it comes to attributing understanding, and (2) that this is true, in part, because understanding attributions play a functional role in identifying experts who should be heeded with respect to the general field in question. These claims are supported by our findings that people differentially withhold attributions of understanding (rather than knowledge) when the object of attribution has minimal explanatory information. We also show that this tendency significantly correlates with people’s willingness to defer to others as potential experts. This work bears on a pressing issue in epistemology concerning the place and value of understanding. Our results also provide reason against positing a simple equation of knowledge(-why) and understanding(-why). We contend that, because deference plays a crucial role in many aspects of everyday reasoning, the fact that we use understanding attributions to demarcate experts reveals a potential mechanism for achieving our epistemic aims in many domains.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some participants were assigned to a third false condition that we do not report here. In it Richard held a coherent set of false beliefs that he used to explain Mercury’s observed orbit. On average, participants ascribed very little knowledge or understanding to Richard in this condition.

  2. As Mauchly’s test indicated that the assumption of sphericity had been violated, χ 2(5) = 83.73, p < .001, the Greenhouse-Geisser correction for degrees of freedom was used, ε = .65.

  3. Of 65 participants, the correlation between the across-domains deference question and knowledge and understanding attributions was undefined for 34 of them. Among those participants for whom the correlation was defined, there was no significant difference between the correlation with knowledge attributions and the correlation with understanding attributions, t(30) = .057, p = .96.

References

  • Bartsch, K., & Wellman, H. M. (1995). Children talk about the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Michael. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. R. (2006). Is understanding a species of knowledge? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(3), 515–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofer, B. K., & Pintrich, P. R. (1997). The development of epistemological theories: Beliefs about knowledge and knowing and their relation to learning. Review of Educational Research, 67, 88–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C. (2003). Folkscience: Coarse interpretations of a complex reality. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(8), 368–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C. (2006). Explanation and understanding. Annual Review of Psychology, 57, 227–254.

  • Keil, F. C., Stein, C., Webb, L., Billings, V. D., & Rozenblit, L. (2008). Discerning the division of cognitive labor: An emerging understanding of how knowledge is clustered in other minds. Cognitive Science, 32, 259–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2015). Understanding phenomena. Synthese, 1–18. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0616-x

  • Kim, J. (1994). Explanatory knowledge and metaphysical dependence. Philosophical Issues, 5(Truth and Rationality), 51–69.

  • Koenig, M. A., & Harris, P. L. (2005). Preschoolers mistrust ignorant and inaccurate speakers. Child Development, 76, 1261–1277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, D., Cheney, R., & Weinstock, M. (2000). The development of epistemological understanding. Cognitive Development, 15, 309–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, D., & Park, S. (2005). Epistemological understanding and the development of intellectual values. International Journal of Educational Research, 43, 111–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombrozo, T. (2006). The structure and function of explanations. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, 464–470.

  • Lombrozo, T. (2012). Explanation and abductive inference. In K. J. Holyoak & R. G. Morrison (Eds.), Oxford handbook of thinking and reasoning (pp. 260–276). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Machamer, P. K., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pritchard, D. (2009). Knowledge, understanding and epistemic value. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 64, 19–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, J. (1981). On understanding the difficulty in understanding understanding. In Herman Parret & Jacques Bouveresse (Eds.), Meaning and Understanding. Berlin: W. De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scriven, M. (1962). Explanation, prediction, and laws. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 3, 170–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shatz, M., Wellman, H. M., & Silber, S. (1983). The acquisition of mental verbs: A systematic investigation of the first reference to mental state. Cognition, 14, 301–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2000). For the love of truth. In Linda Zagzebski (Ed.), Virtue epistemology: Essays on epistemic virtue and responsibility (pp. 49-62) Oxford University Press.

  • Starmans, C., & Friedman, O. (2012). The folk conception of knowledge. Cognition, 124, 272–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. M., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29, 429–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiskopf, D. A. (2011). Models and mechanisms in psychological explanation. Synthese, 183, 313–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. A. (2013). Understanding as representation manipulability. Synthese, 190, 997–1016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. A. (2014). Functional explaining: A new approach to the philosophy of explanation. Synthese, 191, 3367–3391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank the University of California, Berkeley, the John Templeton Foundation’s Varieties of Understanding project, and a James S. McDonnell Foundation Scholar Award for support of this work.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel A. Wilkenfeld.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wilkenfeld, D.A., Plunkett, D. & Lombrozo, T. Depth and deference: When and why we attribute understanding. Philos Stud 173, 373–393 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0497-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0497-y

Keywords

Navigation