Skip to main content
Log in

Not thinking about the same thing. Enactivism, pragmatism and intentionality

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Enactivism does not have its primary philosophical roots in pragmatism: phenomenology (from Husserl to Jonas) is its first source of inspiration (with the exception of Hutto & Myin’s radical enactivism). That does not exclude the benefits of pragmatist readings of enactivism, and of enactivist readings of pragmatism. After having sketched those readings, this paper focuses on the philosophical concept of intentionality. I show that whereas enactivists endorse the idea that intentionality is a base-level property of cognition, pragmatism offer(ed) us some reasons not to proceed this way. It is therefore doubtful to hold that pragmatists and enactivists would converge in the defence of a common, non-representational conception of intentionality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. For instance, James’ Principles of Psychology were one important source of inspiration for Husserl’s theory of intentionality. Moran (2017: 275) lucidly remarks a paradox which fits very well with the tone of our own paper: it is James’ account of consciousness and its fringes, halos and horizons which inspired Husserl to go beyond object-centered accounts of intentionality. James, in itself, did not propose a theory of intentionality in the Principles of Psychology (or elsewhere). Indeed, Shaun Gallagher (1998) showed that it is with the help of intentionality that Husserl was able to overcome some difficulties faced by James in his account of time-consciousness.

  2. See Miyahara and Robertson (2021) for an analysis and use of Dewey’s account of habits in the context of enactive discussions.

  3. See Varela et al., 1991: 205: “Cognition as embodied action is always about or directed toward something that is missing”. This feature is not present in Brentano, according to whom “intentional” qualifies the mode of being of the objects of thought (see Moran, 1996). Husserl was the first philosopher who proposed to define intentionality as a relation, in terms of directedness: « intentional experiences have the peculiarity of directing themselves (beziehen) in varying fashion to presented objects, but they do so in an intentional sense. An object is ‘referred to’ (gemeint) or ‘aimed at’ (abgezielt) in them, and in presentative or judging or other fashion.» (Husserl, 1970: 5th Logical Investigation, § 11).

  4. Gallagher and Miyahara are not alone in those rapprochements between pragmatism and phenomenological intentionality. For instance, Madzia (2016: 304) proposes to see in George Herbert Mead’s attitudes the equivalent of Merleau-Ponty’s motor intentionality.

  5. For instance in the chapter 6 of his book Between saying and doing (2008).

  6. This approach was also Gilbert Ryle’s approach on intentional objects (Ryle, 1971: 183).

  7. As John McDowell says, « If we start from a conception of thinking as in itself without referential bearing on the world, we shall seem to be confronted with a genuine and urgent task, that of reinstating into our picture the way thinking is directed at the world (…) The need to construct a theoretical "hook" to link thinking to the world does not arise, because if it is thinking that we have in view at all—say being struck by the thought that one hears the sound of water dripping—then what we have in view is already hooked on to the world; it is already in view as possessing referential directedness at reality» (McDowell, 1998: 288).

  8. There are, of course, some minor and revealing exceptions. For example, in a course given on December 7th 1921, Dewey describes the conscious and the unconscious phases of experience. In order to describe a type of connection between these two phases, he uses the notion of intentional reference. “Intentional reference” is not here a relation between experience and some object in the world; it is a relation between two phases of experience (Dewey, 2015: 2.2392).

  9. See also: « what has been completely divided in philosophical discourse into man and the world, inner and outer, self and not-self, subject and object, individual and social, private and public, etc., are in actuality parties in life-transactions» (LW16: 248).

  10. This is the option taken by Chemero in his Radical Embodied Cognitive Science: « it is only for convenience (and from habit) that we think of the organism and environment as separate; in fact, they are best thought of as forming just one nondecomposable system, U. Rather than describing the way external (and internal) factors cause changes in the organism’s behavior, such a model would explain the way U, the system as a whole, unfolds over time» (Chemero, 2009: 26).

  11. There is a literature on Heidegger’s pragmatism. See Okrent (1988).

  12. See also Sebbah (2012).

  13. Concerning (3), many things could be said here on the proximity of this strategy and Elizabeth Anscombe’s approach to intentions in her book Intention (Anscombe, 1957), but this will be a story for quite another occasion. For Anscombe, having an intention is not being in a state of mind, hearing an inner voice or experiencing an inner move (Anscombe, 1957: § 25, § 27). The intention of an agent is what he does. The action one intends to do is not primarily described by the description of its target.

  14. Indeed, let me repeat here that all along this paper, I am only discussing intentionality as a general, basic and natural property, not intentionality as an occasional semantic, linguistic property, equated with meaningfulness and/or grammatical aboutness.

References 

  • Alessandroni, N., & Malafouris, L. (2023). Blurring ontological boundaries: The transactional nature of material engagement. Adaptive Behavior, 31(2), 127–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957). Intention. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1997). Topics. Books I and VIII. Translated with a commentary by R. Smith. Oxford University Press.

  • Baggio, G. (2023). Gesture, meaning and intentionality: From radical to pragmatist enactive theory of language. Phenomenology and Cognitive Science. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09936-9

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1994). Making it explicit. Reasoning, representing and discursive commitment. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2002). Tales of the mighty dead. Historical essays in the metaphysics of intentionality. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2008). Between saying and doing: Towards an analytic pragmatism. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (2011). Perspectives on pragmatism: Classical, recent, and contemporary. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Casper, M.-O. (2018). Social enactivism: On situating high-level cognitive states and processes. De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, T. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2013). The feeling body: Affective science meets the enactive mind. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2007). Participatory sense-making: An enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (2015). The class lectures of John Dewey. Volume 2: Education, logic, ethics and political philosophy. Edited by Donald F. Koch and The Center for Dewey Studies. Intelex.

  • Dewey, J. (1916). Essays in experimental logic. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (EW). The early works: 1882–1898. ed. by J.A. Boydston. Volume 5. Southern Illinois University Press (quoted “EW” followed by the volume and the pages numbers).

  • Dewey, J. (MW). The middle works: 1899–1924. ed. by J.A. Boydston. Volume 15. Carbondale & Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1976–1983 (quoted “MW” followed by the volume and the pages numbers).

  • Dewey, J. (LW). The later works: 1925–1953. ed. by J.A. Boydston. Volume 17. Carbondale & Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University (quoted “LW” followed by the volume and the pages numbers).

  • Di Paolo, E. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2008). Extended life. Topoi, 28(1), 9–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., Bhurman, Th., & Barandiaran, X. (2017). Sensorimotor life: An enactive proposal. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dray, W. H. (1989). On history and philosophers of history. Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dreon, R. (2022). Human landscapes: Contributions to a pragmatist anthropology. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. L. (2002). Intelligence without representation: Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel, A. K., Maye, A., Kurthen, M., & König, P. (2013). Where’s the action? The pragmatic turn in cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(5), 202–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Sh. (1998). The inordinance of time. Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Sh. (2017). Enactivist interventions: Rethinking the mind. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Sh. (2019). Mindful performance. In A. Pennisi & A. Falzone (Eds.), The extended theory of cognitive creativity: Interdisciplinary approaches to performativity (pp. 43–58). Springer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Sh. (2023). Pragmatism and cognitive science. In S. Aikin & R. Talisse (Eds.), The Routledge companion to pragmatism (pp. 239–251). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, Sh., & Miyahara, K. (2012). Neo-pragmatism and enactive intentionality. In J. Schulkin (Ed.), New directions in philosophy and cognitive science: Adaptation and cephalic expression. Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1990). The Intentionality All-Stars. In J. Tomberlin (Éd.), Philosophical Perspectives (4: Action Theory and Philosophy of Mind, pp. 383–427). Ridgeview.

  • Heidegger, M. (1988). Basic problems of phenomenology, revised edition. Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hildebrand, D. (2003). Beyond realism and antirealism: John Dewey and the neopragmatists. Vanderbilt University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1970). Logical investigations. English translation J. N. Findlay, 2 vols. Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • Hufendiek, R. (2016). William James and John Dewey on embodied action-oriented emotions. In M. Jung & R. Madzia (Eds.), Pragmatism and embodied cognitive science: from bodily intersubjectivity to symbolic articulation (pp. 269–288). De Gruyter

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism. Basic minds without content. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2017). Evolving enactivism. Basic minds meet content. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Satne, G. (2015). The natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 521–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ingold, T. (2017). On human correspondence. Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 23(1), 9–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1911). The meaning of truth. Longmans, Green, and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J., & Rietveld, E. (2015). The primacy of skilled intentionality: On Hutto & Satne’s the natural origins of content. Philosophia, 43(3), 701–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lévinas, E. (1978). Existence and existents. Duquesne University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Madzia, R. (2016). Presentation and re-presentation: Language, content, and the reconstruction of experience. In H. Joas & D. R. Huebner (Eds.), The timeliness of George Herbert Mead (pp. 296–314). University of Chicago Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2010). Knapping intentions and the marks of the mental. In L. Malafouris & C. Renfrew (Eds.), The cognitive life of things: Recasting the boundaries of the mind (pp. 13–22). Cambridge, McDonald Institute Monographs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malafouris, L. (2013). How things shape the mind. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998). Meaning, knowledge & reality. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mead. (1934) Mind, self and society, edited by Charles Morris, Chicago and London, University of Chicago Press.

  • Mead. (1938). Philosophy of the act, edited by Charles Morris. University of Chicago Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1983). The structure of behavior. Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002). Phenomenology of perception. Routledge Classics.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Metzinger, Th. (2003). Being no one: The self-model theory of subjectivity. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miyahara, K. (2011). Neo-pragmatic intentionality and enactive perception: A compromise between extended and enactive minds. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 10(4), 499–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miyahara, K., & Robertson, I. (2021). The pragmatic intelligence of habits. Topoi, 40(3), 597–608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, D. (1996). Brentano’s thesis. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes, 70, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moran, D. (2017). Phenomenology and pragmatism: Two interactions From horizontal intentionality to practical coping. In M. Baghramian & S. Marchetti (Eds.), Pragmatism and European traditions. Encounters with analytic philosophy before the great divide (pp. 269–287). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2012). On overintellectualizing the intellect. In J. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell-Dreyfus debate (pp. 178–193). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 883–917.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okrent, M. (1988). Heidegger’s pragmatism: Understanding, being, and the critique of metaphysics. Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1931). The collected papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. C. Hartshorne & P. Weiss (Eds.) vol. I - VI; A. W. Burks (Ed.) vol. VII – VIII. Harvard U.P., 1931–1958.

  • Putnam, H. (1988). Representation and reality. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1992). Renewing philosophy. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1999). The threefold cord: Mind, body, and world. Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1990). Objectivity, relativism, and truth. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1993). Consciousness, intentionality, and pragmatism. In S. M. Christensen & D. D. Turner (Eds.), Folk psychology and the philosophy of mind (pp. 388–404). Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1998). Truth and progress: Philosophical papers (Vol. 3). Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, S., & Bourgeois, P. (Eds.). (1980). Pragmatism and phenomenology: A philosophic encounter. B.R. Grüner Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, S., & Bourgeois, P. (Eds.). (1983). Thematic studies in phenomenology and pragmatism. B.R. Grüner Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1971). Collected Papers (Vol. I). Hutchinson.

  • Sachs, C. B. (2014). Discursive and somatic intentionality: Merleau-Ponty contra “McDowell or Sellars.” International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 22(2), 199–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sebbah, F.-D. (2012). Testing the limit: Derrida, Henry, Lévinas and the phenomenological tradition. English translation S. Barker. Stanford University Press.

  • Steiner, P. (2017). Pragmatism in cognitive science: from the pragmatic turn to Deweyan adverbialism. Pragmatism Today, 8(1), 9–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, P. (2020). Habits, meaning, and intentionality. A Deweyan reading. In F. Caruana & I. Testa (Eds.), Habits. Pragmatist approaches from cognitive science, neuroscience and social theory (pp. 223-244). Cambridge University Press.

  • Steiner, P. (2023). The structure of intentionality. Insights and challenges for enactivism. Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. https://doi.org/10.1080/0020174X.2023.2216753

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E., & Varela, F. J. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 5(10), 418–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, Ch. (2013). Perception: Essays after Frege. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tugendhat, E. (1982). Traditional and analytical philosophy: Lectures on the philosophy of language. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1991). Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In A. I. Tauber (Eds.), Organism and the origins of self. Boston studies in the philosophy of science (Vol. 129). Springer.

  • Varela, Fr. (1992). Autopoiesis and a biology of intentionality. In B. McMullin (Ed.), Proceedings of the workshop “Autopoiesis and Perception” (pp. 4–14). Dublin City University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, Fr., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ward, D., Silverman, D., & Villalobos, M. (2017). Introduction: The varieties of enactivism. Topoi, 36(3), 365–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

None.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Not applicable.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierre Steiner.

Ethics declarations

Ethical approval

Not applicable.

Statement regarding research involving human participants and/or animals

Not applicable.

Informed consent

Not applicable.

Competing interests

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Steiner, P. Not thinking about the same thing. Enactivism, pragmatism and intentionality. Phenom Cogn Sci (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09949-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09949-4

Keywords

Navigation