Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Relational autonomy and the clinical relationship in dementia care

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The clinical relationship (or doctor-patient relationship) has been underexplored in dementia care. This is in part due to the way that the clinical relationship has been articulated and understood in bioethics. Robert Veatch’s social contract model is representative of a standard view of the clinical relationship in bioethics. But dementia presents formidable challenges to the standard clinical relationship, including ambiguity about when the clinical relationship begins, how it weathers changes in narrative identity of patients with dementia, and how the intimate involvement of family fits alongside a paradigmatically dyadic relationship. Drawing on work in recent feminist theory, a critique is offered of the standard clinical relationship in bioethics as underwritten by an individualistic conception of autonomy. An alternative view of the clinical relationship in dementia, one that embraces a relational account of autonomy, is put forward.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Veatch initially called this the doctor-patient relationship, but like many others, he came to change his terminology to recognize the primacy of the patient within the relationship as well as different types of professionals who enter into relationships with patients. Ultimately, Veatch settles on the term “patient-provider relationship” [13].

  2. This monopolistic power has evolved since Veatch’s early formulation of the triple contract view but continues to be a feature of the medical profession in many societies.

  3. For Veatch, the point is not that the interests of the state always trump (after all, there may be deontological constraints, e.g., principles of veracity or confidentiality arising from the first level contract that put additional limits on the contract between society and the medical profession), but just that the duties of the physician fall out of, and are exhausted by, this contract and do not have an independent source in the clinical relationship itself [13].

  4. This is not dissimilar to psychiatric evaluations in which the determination of capacity is a catch 22. Though everyone has a right to refuse medical evaluation, so long as they have the capacity to do so, the only way to determine if this capacity is present is to conduct a capacity evaluation.

  5. It is worth noting that there are other examples that run against the dyadic paradigm, including care of children, adults with developmental disabilities, individuals with disorders of consciousness, and some kinds of psychiatric illness.

  6. This does not imply that just because dementia does not feature prominently in Veatch’s work that he did not take it to be important. One might credit Veatch with contributing to a movement in bioethics and medicine that improved the lives of many groups previously disempowered in medicine and society, including those with dementia. Though he talks little about dementia specifically, he does discuss cognitive disability [27].

References

  1. Kass, Leon R. 1975. Regarding the end of medicine and the pursuit of health. The Public Interest 40: 11–42.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Engel, George L. 1977. The need for a new medical model: A challenge for biomedicine. Science 196 (4286): 129–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Siegler, Mark. 1981. Searching for moral certainty in medicine: A proposal for a new model of the doctor-patient encounter. Bulletin of the New York Academy of Medicine 57 (1): 56–69.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Engelhardt, HTristram, Jr. 1983. The physician-patient relationship in a secular, pluralist society. In The Clinical Encounter: The Moral Fabric of the Patient-Physician Relationship, ed. E.E. Shelp, 253–266. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  5. Jonsen, Albert R. 1983. The therapeutic relationship: Is moral conduct a necessary condition? In The Clinical Encounter: The Moral Fabric of the Patient-Physician Relationship, ed. E.E. Shelp, 267–287. Dordrecht, Holland: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  6. Childress, James F., and Mark Siegler. 1984. Metaphors and models of doctor-patient relationships: Their implications for autonomy. Theoretical Medicine 5 (1): 17–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Ozar, David T. 1984. Patients’ autonomy: Three models of the professional-lay relationship in medicine. Theoretical Medicine 5 (1): 61–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Brody, Howard. 1987. The physician-patient relationship: Models and criticisms. Theoretical Medicine 8 (2): 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Pellegrino, Edmund D. 1987. Toward a reconstruction of medical morality. The Journal of medical humanities and bioethics 8 (1): 7–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Brock, Dan W. 1991. The ideal of shared decision making between physicians and patients. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 1 (1): 28–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Emanuel, Ezekiel J., and Linda L. Emanuel. 1992. Four models of the physician-patient relationship. Journal of the American Medical Association 267 (16): 2221–2226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. May, William F. 1996. Code, covenant, contract, or philanthropy. Journal of Pharmacy Teaching 5 (1–2): 49–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Veatch, Robert M. 1996. Modern vs. contemporary medicine: the patient-provider relation in the twenty-first century. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 6 (4): 366–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Veatch, Robert M. 1972. Models for ethical medicine in a revolutionary age. The Hastings Center report 2 (3): 5–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Veatch, Robert M. 2000. Doctor does not know best: Why in the new century physicians must stop trying to benefit patients. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (6): 701–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Veatch, Robert. 1981. A Theory of Medical Ethics. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Veatch, Robert M. 1991. The Patient-Physician Relations: The Patient as Partner, Part 2. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Veatch, Robert M. 2006. Assessing Pellegrino’s reconstruction of medical morality. The American Journal of Bioethics 6 (2): 72–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. The World Health Organization. https://www.who.int/news-room/fact-sheets/detail/dementia. Accessed August 2, 2021.

  20. Karlawish, J.H.T., D.J. Casarett, B.D. James, S.X. Xie, and S.Y. Kim. 2005. The ability of persons with Alzheimer disease (AD) to make a decision about taking an AD treatment. Neurology 64 (9): 1514–1519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Blass, David M. 2007. The physician–patient relationship in dementia care. Neurotherapeutics 4 (3): 545–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Autonomy and the demented self. The Milbank Quarterly. 4–16.

  23. Dworkin, Ronald. 1993. Life’s Dominion. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Dresser, Rebecca. 1995. Dworkin on dementia: Elegant theory, questionable policy. Hastings Center Report 25 (6): 32–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. DeGrazia, David. 1999. Advance directives, dementia, and ‘the someone else problem.’ Bioethics 13 (5): 373–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Jaworska, Agnieszka. 1999. Respecting the margins of agency: Alzheimer’s patients and the capacity to value. Philosophy & Public Affairs 28 (2): 105–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Veatch, Robert M. 2004. Consent and persons with marginal mental impairment. Ethics and Intellectual Disability 8 (1): 6–7.

    Google Scholar 

  28. McCrea, Jacqueline B., W. Gary Erwin, Samuel D. Uretsky, and Robert M. Veatch. 1990. Forgoing antimicrobial therapy for a patient with advanced Alzheimer’s disease. American Journal of Hospital Pharmacy 47 (7): 1588–1591.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Veatch, Robert M., and Laura K. Guidry-Grimes. 2020. The Basics of Bioethics, 4th ed. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  30. O’Neill, Onora. 2002. Autonomy and Trust in Bioethics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  31. Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. 2013. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 7th ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Engelhardt, HTristram, Jr. 1986. The Foundations of Bioethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Feinberg, Joel. 1989. Autonomy. In The Inner Citadel: Essays on Individual Autonomy, ed. John Christman, 27–53. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Verkerk, Marian A. 2001. The care perspective and autonomy. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 4 (3): 289–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Reader, Soran. 2007. The other side of agency. Philosophy 82 (4): 579–604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Kittay, Eva Feder, and Licia Carlson, eds. 2010. Cognitive Disability and its Challenge to Moral Philosophy. New York: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Baier, Annette. 1985. Postures of the Mind: Essays on Mind and Morals. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Baier, Annette. 1995. Moral Prejudices: Essays on Ethics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Kittay, Eva Feder. 1999. Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Equality, and Dependency. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Sandel, Michael J. 1998. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  41. Mackenzie, Catriona, and Natalie Stoljar, eds. 2000. Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Meyers, Diana T. 1989. Self, Society, and Personal Choice. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Nussbaum, Martha C. 2007. Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  44. Donchin, Anne. 2001. Understanding autonomy relationally: Toward a reconfiguration of bioethical principles. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 26 (4): 365–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Lindemann, Hilde. 2009. Holding one another (well, wrongly, clumsily) in a time of dementia. Metaphilosophy 40 (3–4): 416–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I wish to thank and remember Bob Veatch for his kindness, scholarship, and mentorship, and for his tireless commitment to the field he helped birth.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eran Klein.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Klein, E. Relational autonomy and the clinical relationship in dementia care. Theor Med Bioeth 43, 277–288 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-022-09580-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-022-09580-5

Keywords

Navigation