Skip to main content
Log in

Liberalism, authority, and bioethics commissions

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Bioethicists working on national ethics commissions frequently think of themselves as advisors to the government, but distance themselves from any claims to actual authority. Governments however may find it beneficial to appear to defer to the authority of these commissions when designing laws and policies, and might appoint such commissions for exactly this reason. Where does the authority for setting laws and policies come from? This question is best answered from within a normative political philosophy. This paper explains the locus of moral authority as understood within one family of normative political theories—liberal political theories—and argues that most major “liberal” commentators have understood both the source and scope of ethics commissions’ authority in a manner at odds with liberalism, rightly interpreted. The author argues that reexamining the implications of liberalism for bioethics commissions would mean changing what are considered valid criticisms of such commissions and also changing the content of national bioethics commission mandates. The author concludes that bioethicists who participate in such commissions ought to carefully examine their own views about the normative limits of governmental authority because such limits have important implications for the contribution that bioethicists can legitimately make to government commissions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This is not to say that moral convictions are at root a matter of subjective experience or preference in the same way colors are. Many ethics experts are like design experts, however, in the sense that they do not claim expertise in which morals are the right or true ones, just as design experts do not believe they have expertise in the right or true color schemes for homes.

  2. Many nations either have already or are beginning to develop such commissions. For a partial list of EU countries with such commissions, see [1]. For an overview of the history and progress of several national bioethics commissions in other nations, see [2].

  3. Most people would probably agree that governments can act in such an egregious manner that they lose their authority to impose obligations. I will not treat this complex question here, however.

  4. For more detail on the similarities and differences between varieties of liberalism, see Gaus and Courtland [5].

  5. For Kant, an action is right only if it can be described as compatible with the freedom of everyone else; as Kant says in his Universal Principle of Right, “Any action is right if it can coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal law” [7, sec. 6:230]. Coercion is at root a hindrance to another’s freedom, and so can only be justified when it can be described as a merely reciprocal use of force responding to a prior instance of coercion. Kant says, “There is connected with right by the principle of contradiction an authorization to coerce someone who infringes upon it” [7, sec. 6:231]. The remainder of the Doctrine of Right (the first half of Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals) describes the authorizations and constraints placed on governments following from these basic principles.

  6. The initial situation, for Rawls, is “fair between individuals as moral persons,” and is thus the basis for thinking that their hypothetical agreement is also fair [9, p. 12].

  7. Kant states, “That ethics contains duties that one cannot be constrained by others (through natural means) to fulfill follows merely from its being a doctrine of ends, since coercion to ends (to have them) is self-contradictory” [7, sec. 6:381].

  8. Although most bioethics commissions concern themselves primarily with the giving of reasons, some commissions making proclamations on law, such as the UNESCO general commission responsible for producing the Universal Declaration of Bioethics and Human Rights, do not bother with the giving of reasons. The documents produced by these commissions implicitly derive their authority purely from the supposed epistemic authority of those involved in the process. This does not necessarily mean that such documents have no authority for the liberal, only that in the absence of any compelling explanation given for the conclusions, its authority will be limited to those conclusions that observers already understand to follow from liberal principles. The supposed authority of those discovering these rights will carry little weight in and of itself for most liberals, especially if those conclusions seemingly violate liberal principles.

  9. Crosthwaite is addressing the more general question of expertise in ethics, but she takes a very similar tack to the others in her treatment of moral method and moral expertise.

  10. For Kant, duties of right (i.e. legal obligations) are basically restricted to “perfect obligations to others.” Lying outside the realm of legal obligation are all imperfect duties to others, as well as perfect and imperfect duties towards oneself. This is implied both in the structure of Kant’s most mature work on moral theory, The Metaphysics of Morals, and also in the table he provides delineating the structure of moral theory. See [7, p. 240].

  11. For Mill, “the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not a sufficient warrant” [8, p. 13].

  12. Rawls limited much of his work to questions about “justice,” saying that he did not know if the contract approach could be extended to other moral rules or virtues [9]. Rawls makes clear his commitment to liberty by giving it lexical priority over other kinds of concerns, even concerns he finds connected to “justice,” such as the maximin principle.

  13. A host of other economic, ideological, technological, and cultural changes were also occurring at the time liberalism emerged. A “theory” of why liberalism occurred would take me well beyond the scope of this piece. I only make the limited point that liberalism was and still is widely seen as a solution to some of the ideological conflicts involved in the wars of religion. Carefully defining the correct moral methods or expertise in the contemporary context seems to resurrect that specter.

  14. “Whose realm, his religion,” was the makeshift conclusion settled on at the Peace of Augsburg in 1555.

  15. Although liberalism was intended to quell conflict, I will not here defend a prediction that it (or any other political philosophy) will necessarily lead to more consensus on bioethics commissions. However, at least one author has made such a prediction; see [16].

  16. For more on the discrepancies between democracy and liberalism as rubrics for justifying the conclusions of government ethics commissions, see [18].

  17. See, for example, [2023].

  18. Carl Elliott [24] notices this but finds some merit in the conclusions and approach of that commission.

  19. In contrast to Bush’s PCBE, however, CBAC spent most of its time addressing questions more mundane in nature than the foundations of human dignity or the moral status of embryos [28].

  20. The Belgian Committee further expects that committee members will not reach consensus among themselves even on the limited questions they address, and consequently expects all written opinions to reflect the diversity of positions held by members (an expectation expressed by what they call the “non-consensus rule”). The group’s policy is to leave the work of hammering out compromises to the legislature. In this way, they admirably separate the actual authority of the elected officials from the very limited epistemic authority possessed by committee members.

  21. Although the actual charter for NBAC wisely made only a very brief mention of giving advice about “bioethical issues” as they pertain to governmental activities, this did not discourage NBAC from making wide-ranging pronouncements on moral and ethical topics. For commentary on the ambitious aims of the commission to nail down an understanding of “moral status,” see [16].

References

  1. European Commission. 2008. National ethics committees. http://ec.europa.eu/research/biosociety/bioethics/bioethics_ethics_en.htm. Accessed July 10, 2013.

  2. United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization. 2010. National bioethics committees in action. Paris, France: UNESCO. http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0018/001895/189548e.pdf. Accessed August 6, 2013.

  3. Brock, Dan W. 1995. Public moral discourse. In Society’s choices: social and ethical decision making in biomedicine, ed. Ruth Ellen Bulger, Elizabeth Meyer Bobby, and Harvey V. Fineberg. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Moreno, Jonathan D. 1995. Deciding together: bioethics and moral consensus. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Gaus, Gerald, and Shane D. Courtland. 2011. Liberalism. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/liberalism/. Accessed August 6, 2013.

  6. Locke, John. 1980. Second treatise of government, 1st ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Pub. Co.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Kant, Immanuel. 1996. The metaphysics of morals, ed. Mary J. Gregor. New York: Cambridge University Press.

  8. Mill, John Stuart. 1956. On liberty. New York: Liberal Arts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Johnson, Summer. 2007. A rebuttal to Dzur and Levin: Johnson on the legitimacy and authority of bioethics commissions. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 17(2): 143–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Crosthwaite, Jan. 1995. Moral expertise: a problem in the professional ethics of professional ethicists. Bioethics 9(5): 361–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Gray, John. 2000. Two faces of liberalism. New York: New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Rawls, John. 2005. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Engelhardt, H.Tristram. 1996. The foundations of bioethics, 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Galston, William. 1995. Two concepts of liberalism. Ethics 105(3): 516–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Charo, R.Alta. 1995. The hunting of the snark: the moral status of embryos, right-to-lifers, and Third World women. Stanford Law & Policy Review 6(2): 11–37.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Dzur, Albert W., and Daniel Levin. 2004. The “nation’s conscience”: assessing bioethics commissions as public forums. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 14(4): 333–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Delkeskamp-Hayes, Corinna. 2005. Societal consensus and the problem of consent: refocusing the problem of ethics expertise in liberal democracies. In Ethics expertise: history, contemporary perspectives, and applications, ed. Lisa M. Rasmussen, 139–163. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  19. Engelhardt, H.Tristram. 2003. The ordination of bioethicists as secular moral experts. Social philosophy & policy 19(2): 59–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Blackburn, Elizabeth. 2004. Bioethics and the political distortion of biomedical science. New England Journal of Medicine 350(14): 1379–1380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Bailey, Ronald. 2002. Tallying the new bioethics council—has Leon Kass stacked the deck? Reason.com. January 23.

  22. Noah, Timothy. 2004. Leon Kass, you silly ass! Slate. March 8.

  23. Pinker, Stephen. 2008. The stupidity of dignity. The New Republic. May 28.

  24. Elliott, Carl. 2004. Beyond Politics: why have bioethicists focused on the President’s Council’s dismissals and ignored its remarkable work?. Slate. March 9.

  25. Green, Ronald M. 2006. For richer or poorer? evaluating the President’s Council on Bioethics. HEC forum 18(2): 108–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Kass, Leon R. 2002. Chairman’s opening remarks. Transcript of remarks at the first meeting of the President’s Council on Bioethics, January 17–18. http://bioethics.georgetown.edu/pcbe/transcripts/jan02/opening01.html. Accessed January 17, 2013.

  27. Petrov, Rem, and Boris Yudin. 2010. The development of bioethics in Russia. In National Bioethics Committees in Action, ed. Scientific United Nations Educational, and Cultural Organization, 18–26. Paris, France: UNESCO. http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0018/001895/189548e.pdf. Accessed July 9, 2013.

  28. Health Canada. 2005. Canada’s biotechnology strategy. http://www.hc-sc.gc.ca/sr-sr/biotech/role/strateg-eng.php. Accessed January 17, 2013.

  29. Canadian Biotechnology Advisory Committee. 2002. Patenting of higher life forms and related issues: Report to the government of Canada biotechnology ministerial coordinating committee. Ottawa, ON: CBAC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  30. United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization. 2012. Assisting bioethics committees (ABC). http://www.unesco.org/new/en/social-and-human-sciences/themes/bioethics/assisting-bioethics-committees/. Accessed July 10, 2013.

  31. Clinton, William J. 1995. Executive Order 12975 of October 3, 1995: Protection of human research subjects and creation of national bioethics advisory commission. Federal Register 60(193): 52063–52065.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Stiennon, Jeanine-Anne. 2010. The Belgian Advisory Committee on Bioethics. In National Bioethics Committees in Action, ed. United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization, 27–29. Paris, France: UNESCO. http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0018/001895/189548e.pdf. Accessed July 9, 2013.

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author wishes to thank the research team at Novel Tech Ethics, Dalhousie University, as well as two anonymous readers for their valuable insights and feedback on an earlier version of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to D. Robert MacDougall.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

MacDougall, D.R. Liberalism, authority, and bioethics commissions. Theor Med Bioeth 34, 461–477 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-013-9271-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-013-9271-3

Keywords

Navigation