1 Introduction

“True philosophers make dying their profession.”Footnote 1 As this statement of Socrates via Plato indicates, gazing upon and contemplating one’s own death has formed a core aspect in the history of Western philosophy. After being mentioned by the pre-Socratics and eventually Plato, death has been eloquently discussed by several Western philosophers—from Epicurus, the founder of the Epicurean school, to the stoics Cicero, Seneca, and Aurelius.Footnote 2 Over time, moralists such as Montaigne and Pascal have left behind discourses that squarely confront human death.Footnote 3 With the advent of modernity, the main works of existential philosophers, such as Kierkegaard, Heidegger, Jaspers, Sartre, and Jankélévitch, also revolve around the question of death, inheriting from and further developing the Western philosophical tradition’s preoccupation with one’s own death.Footnote 4

Although existential philosophers’ attitudes toward death show some key differences, they share a common trait: They do not address the outcomes of science in their philosophies of death.Footnote 5 Their perspectives are based on the premise that “my death,” which cannot be replaced by anything else, is unapproachable via science and, therefore, is a theme peculiar to philosophy, as exemplified by Heidegger’s definition of the scholarly nature of biology.Footnote 6My death is a common theme in existential philosophy and has generally not been explored in the philosophy of science.Footnote 7

By contrast, this study aims to elucidate that my death is an important point of contact between biology and philosophy. To this end, in Sect. 2, I discuss the movement between continuity and discontinuity as foundational to the history of science by associating it with the relationship between the unknown and the known. In Sect. 3, I delve deeper into this movement by discussing consciousness and body to clarify the concept of “my rearview,” and subsequently explain the three categories of the unknown. As such an investigation prompts us to question the kind of unknown that scientific activities confront, Sect. 4 overviews the relationship between biology and death, and examines the intersection between the philosophical arguments concerning my death and reproductive theory. Consequently, this study concretely demonstrates that the connection between biology and philosophy lies in the universal unknown in the sense that every I has an unknown that can be known to Others but remains unknown only to me, rather than relative unknown, which is usually considered in science. Finally, I suggest that the universal unknown of my death, which completes my rearview, forms the basis of science.

I note in advance that interpreting my death as a point of contact between biology and philosophy is an epistemological project, which does not cover all the aspects of the issues that might be involved in my death in general.Footnote 8

2 Continuity and the unknown in science

2.1 Relationship between continuity and discontinuity

Physicist de Broglie’s ideas from his book Matter and Light, written more than 80 years ago, still provide us with endless suggestions for understanding the relationship between science and philosophy:

In Physics, as in every other branch of knowledge, the problem of continuity and discontinuity has existed at all times: for in this science, as elsewhere, the human mind has always manifested two tendencies at once antagonistic and complementary. On the one hand, there is the tendency which tries to reduce the complexity of phenomena to the existence of simple elements indivisible, and capable of being counted; a tendency whose analysis of Reality seeks to reduce it to a dust-cloud of individuals. On the other hand, there is the tendency based on our intuitive notion of Time and Space, which observes the universal interaction of things and regards every attempt to disengage definite individual entities from the flux of natural phenomena as artificial. The conflict between the continuous view in Physics, and its opposite, has existed through many centuries with varying fortunes, each gaining an advantage over the other in turn, and neither winning a definite victory. For the philosopher there is nothing surprising in this, since the development of theory in every sphere of intellectual activity shows him that, if pushed to an extreme and opposed to each other, the concepts of both the continuous and the discontinuous are unable to give a correct rendering of Reality, which requires a subtle and almost indefinable fusion of the two terms of this antinomy.Footnote 9

Although scientific activity can be characterized in various ways, following de Broglie’s emphasis on continuity and discontinuity in physics, I organize its progress in terms of “divisions” that make a continuum discontinuous. For example, in physics, attempts to identify the ultimate minimum unit have revealed atoms as constituents of matter, electrons and nuclei as constituents of atoms, protons and neutrons as constituents of nuclei, and quarks as constituents of protons and neutrons. In other words, discovering a new element involves dividing something that has been considered indivisible (e.g., an atom into an electron and a nucleus). Similarly, studies in biology have discovered that a body comprises various organs (brain, heart, lungs, intestines, etc.), nerves, blood vessels, blood, bones, and so on. One organ, the brain, comprises the cerebrum, diencephalon, midbrain, cerebellum, and medulla oblongata. These components consist of cells, which consist of organelles, and one organelle, the cell nucleus, contains chromosomes. Chromosomes are made up of proteins and nucleic acids, and nucleotides, the structural units of deoxyribonucleic acid (DNA), consist of sugars, phosphates, and bases. These molecules are further made up of atoms.Footnote 10

In addition, the identification of substances that cause a certain life phenomenon—for example, identifying the existence, function, and structure of DNA—has been achieved through the division process. Many biological discoveries have stemmed from trial-and-error attempts to demarcate the boundaries of living organisms accurately. Divisions are also crucial for medicine, which closely affects daily life. The structure of the human body has been clarified through anatomy, which etymologically means “cutting up.” Moreover, increased visual capacity, enabled by microscopes and diagnostic imaging equipment, has revealed the subtle mechanisms and abnormalities of small body parts, including those invisible to the naked eye, further advancing our understanding through divisions.

2.2 Relationship between the unknown and the known

As mentioned above, division that makes a continuum discontinuous yields new knowledge for science. For instance, the division of atoms is integrated with the discovery of electrons and nuclei. Before we could divide atoms, their interiors were continuous and unknown. Similarly, in biology, cells, chromosomes, nucleic acids, and other constituents comprised unknown components before they were divided and their components were revealed through their interiors’ discontinuity. The pursuit of discontinuity has never ceased. Presently, every base in the human genome has been sequenced. Furthermore, research on bacteria and viruses, based on isolation and culturing, demonstrates that the discontinuity of what was previously seen as continuous is essentially a conversion of the unknown into the known. The unknown in question here is one that is not considered unknown. For example, before the discovery of electrons, atoms were considered the fundamental unit of matter, and before the discovery of Helicobacter pylori, bacteria were considered incapable of surviving in gastric acid.

In the schematic relationship between the unknown and known, the unknown is unified with continuity and the known with discontinuity. If science aims to replace all unknowns with knowns, then scientific activity involves clarifying the ultimate discontinuity that can no longer be advanced in each research area by maximizing the discontinuity of continuity. However, mastering the known by reaching ultimate discontinuity in science can only be seen as artificial. In fact, the atom, once considered the minimum unit, was divided into almost infinitely smaller particles, illustrating that continuity emerged yet again from the discontinuity that was relentlessly pursued at the time, which beckoned scientists toward a new discontinuity. Thus, the history of science can be seen as a continuous movement between the unknown and the known: When an unknown becomes known, a new unknown emerges in its place, which is displaced by the new known in which the unknown is latent.Footnote 11

The emergence of continuity from discontinuity and new unknowns from previously supposed definitive knowledge is not solely evident in the pursuit of the components of matter. For example, diseases that once appeared to have been suppressed by humankind, such as tuberculosis and measles, have regained power and once again pose a threat. Thus, in principle, there can be no ultimate suppression method that can prevent the proliferation or mutation of diseases, implying that the known cannot completely cover diseases, as their persistence triggers the reemergence of the unknown. In addition, controlling one malignant disease cannot guarantee that a new disease will not emerge to threaten humankind. Thus, there is no ultimate medical perspective that can disrupt the continuity of diseases, and the unknown that overcomes the perspective constantly reemerges. Accordingly, it is impossible for human cognition to fully recognize an object and replace its unknowns with knowns. Even familiar objects always contain unknowns, indicating that our recognition has the scope to exceed apparent limits. Thus, in principle, our recognition of an object can continue indefinitely and there can be no ultimate recognition that disrupts its continuity. If this also applies to scientific recognition, mastering the known in science will always be artificial.

3 Continuity and the unknown in my rearview

3.1 The continuity of my consciousness

The previously discussed matter of continuity is not solely a problem for science. As de Broglie wrote, the problem of continuity and discontinuity is an aporia that philosophy pursued long before the natural sciences emerged. In the earliest days of Western philosophical history, Parmenides and his disciple Zeno meticulously discussed the crux of this problem.Footnote 12 Without delving into the details of the historical arguments, I present the following passage from Plato’s Apology of Socrates, which initially may seem wholly unrelated to this problem. However, Socrates’s death-like dreamless sleep can reflect the problem of continuity and discontinuity in light of our daily understanding and help elucidate the close relationship between this problem and death.

Death is […] annihilation, and the dead have no consciousness of anything […] Now if there is no consciousness but only a dreamless sleep, death must be a marvellous gain. I suppose that if anyone were told to pick out the night on which he slept so soundly as not even to dream, and then to compare it with all the other nights and days of his life, and then were told to say, after due consideration, how many better and happier days and nights than this he had spent in the course of his life—well, I think that the Great King himself, to say nothing of any private person, would find these days and nights easy to count in comparison with the rest. If death is like this, then, I call it gain; because the whole of time, if you look at it in this way, can be regarded as no more than one single night.Footnote 13

In other words, there is nothing that disrupts my stream of consciousness while sleeping soundly without dreaming. Even if I do something in this state, I am not aware of it, or, at least, have no memory of it upon awakening. In reality, no matter how deep my sleep is, I remain gently connected to my waking state. However, when undergoing general anesthesia, such as before surgery, my stream of consciousness ensures perfect continuity, such that I am unaware of my loss of consciousness. In such cases, I have no way of knowing how long I was unconscious for, whether an hour or a day, or whether I screamed or was silent. There is no room for discontinuity in the continuity of my consciousness.Footnote 14

The continuity of my consciousness remains, so to speak, an inner nothingness for me and is never revealed to me of its own accord—inserting discontinuities into this continuity necessarily requires the intervention of Others.Footnote 15 For example, a doctor’s testimony that “you kept screaming while you were unconscious” would be an intervention that would lead me to a discovery. What we ordinarily do to reestablish our continuity of consciousness—for example, confirming our actions with Others or viewing ourselves through the eyes of Others when we briefly lose sight of ourselves—is also an insertion of discontinuity into the continuity of consciousness, even though the dimensions are different. Such an insertion does not stop after one instance. In fact, no matter how unquestionable a doctor’s testimony might seem, its accuracy is not guaranteed. There is always the possibility that someone might contradict it and if the accuracy is to be proven, the testimony of Others must be relied upon. The continuity of the doctor’s consciousness also depends on Others’ consciousness. Although we do not tend to notice this characteristic of consciousness, except under special circumstances, such as after the loss of consciousness described above, the fact that my consciousness cannot show me its complete continuity of its own accord corresponds to any person’s consciousness.

Therefore, discontinuity is endlessly introduced into the continuity of my consciousness from my consciousness. In fact, even if no one else can question a doctor’s testimony, no one can justify it in a way that would end the argument on its own. One testimony could confirm another, while simultaneously calling on a subsequent testimony to confirm itself. This circle of testimony expands sequentially and in principle, extends to the entire world. In this way, the continuity of my consciousness encompasses innumerable discontinuities. Paradoxically, my consciousness is revealed to me as continuous by incorporating innumerable discontinuities. By contrast, discontinuity intervenes in my consciousness by letting the continuity emerge from within it.

As discussed in Sect. 2, in the case of science, the emergence of continuity within discontinuity implies a constant emergence of the unknown within the known. This also applies to the case of consciousness, because as the aforementioned discussion on testimony indicates, my consciousness cannot complete my knowledge by itself. Rather, the unknown connects my consciousness to other consciousnesses. Therefore, there exists a correspondence between the known and discontinuity, and the unknown and continuity with regard to consciousness.

3.2 Dividing the unknown

It is possible to confirm the above assertion by changing the perspective from my consciousness to my body. I am my consciousness, but simultaneously, I am my body: My consciousness is the foundation of my body, and my body is the foundation of my consciousness. The relationship between the two has inspired numerous points of discussion in the history of philosophy.Footnote 16 Here, I focus only on the following point: As I am my body, seeing myself is an event of crucial significance to me. I can see the outside world, but I cannot see my own eyes. I also cannot see other significant parts of my body, such as my face, head, and back, except when using a mirror. This means that they only appear to me indirectly through an “Other.” If this “Other” has significantly enhanced vision, such as a medical device (e.g., endoscope), it can help me see parts of myself that I have not specifically discerned as me or mine, such as polyps in the folds of my internal organs.

This visual characteristic is closely related to the division between my frontal view, which I can directly see before me, and my rearview, which contains what would otherwise escape my sight and could endanger me. This reflects the fate of not only human beings but also of other organisms, as in the eat-or-be-eaten relationship. The division occurs because my body has a material thickness, but it does not correspond to the division between the front and rear of the physical body. As discussed above, my face and my polyps, for example, are located in my rearview.

My rearview becomes a crucial concern for me during some stages of development and remains so throughout my life. The gaze of a particular individual that captures my appearance and behavior; the public gaze that eyes my educational background, status, and property; and the gaze of doctors or medical devices that tell me about my illness or remaining lifespan are extremely important, because my rearview, which is mine, but never seen directly by me, can be directly accessed by Others, at least more directly than by me. My acknowledgment of Others’ perspectives is an event integrated with the division of my frontal view and rearview.

This division occurs for everyone, such that there can be no situation in which one person’s perspective is more privileged than that of Others. I am simultaneously the one who sees and the one who is seen. I am the subject as well as the object. No matter how powerful people might be, they cannot solely be subjects who see Others unilaterally without being seen by them. Similarly, no matter how weak people might be, they cannot solely be objects seen unilaterally by Others without seeing them. Even if I am completely indifferent to how I appear to Others, I am forced to expose to Others my face, back, and other parts that I can only see indirectly, leaving these parts at their disposal.Footnote 17 As the division of my frontal view and rearview does not depend on a particular person, this disposal is endlessly chained.

Although my rearview is both threatened and guaranteed by Others, it cannot be revealed to me directly. The unknowns of my rearview can, in principle, be known to any Other, but will remain directly unknown only to me. Therefore, the unknown in question here is neither “pure” unknown, completely disconnected from the known, nor relative unknown in the sense that some others know and some do not.Footnote 18 It can be described as universal unknown considering that every I has an unknown that can be known to Others but remains unknown only to me.

Thus far, I have distinguished between my consciousness in everyday life and my consciousness in a dreamless sleep or under general anesthesia. The former is a normal waking consciousness that involves entrusting to Others what I cannot perceive alone (a continuity that is unified with discontinuity), while the latter is a consciousness that can never be revealed of its own accord (a continuity that can have no relationship with discontinuity), except to be subsequently recreated as unconsciousness in consciousness.Footnote 19 Thus, continuity has a division that corresponds to the unknown divisions.

3.3 Perspective of the universal unknown

Applying the above considerations to science, I ask, “What unknowns does science confront?” Scientists usually confront relative unknowns. Today, fierce competition for scientific discoveries has arisen, because the unknowns in question are relative unknowns that are not yet known to anyone, but we assume that they will eventually be known to someone. The same can be said of the state of scientific progress. There has been tremendous progress in scientific inquiry since the scientific revolution of the 17th century, opening up vast areas of the known within what was previously unknown. Although its momentum remains unabated, science has not replaced all unknowns with knowns. When considering this state as the unknown outpacing current scientists’ abilities, we assume that scientists confront relative unknowns regardless of whether we believe that the unknown will come to an end in the future or that it will continue forever.Footnote 20

By contrast, science does not seem to be concerned with “pure” or “universal” unknowns, both of which will never be directly knowable to me. However, within the natural sciences, reproductive theory is one area of biology that seeks to pursue the universal unknown in depth, without being aware of doing so. In the following section, I clarify this claim by examining reproductive theory in conjunction with my death, a theme unique to philosophy.Footnote 21 Connecting my death with my interpretation of continuity and discontinuity through the dialogue between biology and philosophy can greatly deepen our understanding of this theme.Footnote 22

4 Continuity and the unknown in reproductive theory

4.1 Death and science

We cannot experience “I died.” The dreamless sleep that Socrates equates with death is an experience one cannot have if one never wakes up again.Footnote 23 Based on the disconnection between my life and death, it is understandable that unlike life, I cannot experience my death. As Epicurus noted, “so long as we are existent death is not present and whenever it is present we are non-existent.”Footnote 24 The only way we can gauge the experience of death is through the death of Others. The distinction between my death and the death of Others has a decisive meaning in converting unknown death into the known.

Science’s conception of death relies on the recognition of the death of Others and death as discontinuity as two sides of the same coin. In biology, death is defined as “the point at which the processes that maintain an organism alive no longer function.”Footnote 25 This definition of a cessation of continuous functioning, a separation from life, is derived from the death of Others, not my own.Footnote 26 In anatomy, a branch of science that depends on divisions, the scientific definition of death also focuses on discontinuity. Moreover, biology has made several important discoveries regarding the death of Others that are related to: (1) cell lifespans or the limits of cell division, (2) the mechanisms of lifespans and aging (e.g., a specific gene related to longevity as well as telomeres and telomerase), (3) the cellular suicide mechanism, or apoptosis, that is crucial for the formation and maintenance of living organisms, and (4) a method for initializing differentiated cells into undifferentiated cells, offering a glimpse into the possibility of “unwinding” life.Footnote 27 These discoveries and other biological findings have driven the development of bold hypothetical theories about the mysteries related to the origins of sexual reproduction and death.Footnote 28

Despite these remarkable findings, biology in general does not focus on death as a theme, let alone my death. In other words, biology’s position on the concept of death is unclear. Standard biology textbooks do not discuss death as a single concept; even the word “death” is rarely used.Footnote 29 Rather, biologists prefer to use the term “lifespan,” indicating that biological research is essentially conducted within the scope of life phenomena.Footnote 30 In addition, medicine is especially concerned with life up to the point of death, as its purpose is to help people avoid death. Thus, death itself is outside its scope.Footnote 31 Overall, as science assumes the distinction between my death and the death of Others and does not even focus on death as an inherent theme, it is not surprising that the dialogues between science and philosophy have not traditionally focused on my death as a theme.Footnote 32

4.2 My death

The universal unknown described previously can serve as a basis for this dialogue between philosophy and science, with a view of my death as something not only different from the death of Others, embodied by the cessation of life functions, but also different from my death as a pure unknown. In this subsection, I specifically refer to Sartre’s arguments on my death.Footnote 33 For Sartre, my death is the death captured by the gaze of Others, who observe calmly and seek to expose everything as anatomists do. He wrote, “the very existence of death alienates us wholly in our own life to the advantage of the Other. To be dead is to be a prey for the living. This means therefore that the one who tries to grasp the meaning of his future death must discover himself as the future prey of others.”Footnote 34 Being a dead person or a corpse, Others can look down on me and observe me thoroughly. In principle, any Other has the possibility of doing so, irrespective of whether they actually do. The only one who cannot is me. Neither can I look back at those who are doing so, nor can I experience my death through them. My death is never given to me; in my death, I am completely entrusted to Others. In other words, “to die is to be condemned […] to exist only through the Other” and “the fact of death […] gives the final victory to the point of view of the Other.”Footnote 35My death constitutes an unknown formed in my rearview that Others can see. From the perspective of continuity and discontinuity, this death corresponds to continuity that contains discontinuity or to continuity that emerges from discontinuity.Footnote 36

I extend this argument to biology through an in-depth consideration of my death, drawing on and exceeding Sartre.Footnote 37 As long as my face or back can be shown to me indirectly, my rearview cannot constitute a complete unknown. As exemplified by microscopic polyps, scientific and technological progress has provided us with a vision of ourselves that was previously unthinkable. Correspondingly, the unknowns in my rearview have been successively introduced into my known. This has allowed us to detach ourselves from our entrustment to Others and increase our degree of “self-sufficiency.”Footnote 38 However, my death can never be witnessed by me, even though the most advanced scientific and technological devices. Therefore, entrusting myself to Others, which occurs in my rearview, takes its perfect form in my death. This makes my death the perfect embodiment of the unknown that in principle can be known to any Other but remains unknown to me alone (universal unknown). As long as everyone dies and must be seen unilaterally by Others, the complete entrustment of myself to Others extends to the entire world.Footnote 39 The eyes of the Other, which see all of me, cannot, in principle, be the eyes of any particular Other, but must be those of all mortal people. Thus, my death—a state that comes to all—terminates my life and connects me to Others. Based on my death, the continuity of the Other emerges in the midst of the discontinuity of my life.Footnote 40

4.3 For dialogue between biology and philosophy

At first glance, the statement “my death terminates my life” is completely self-evident: Not just human beings, but all living things inevitably die. However, based on the evolutionary history of reproduction, it is possible to question the self-evident nature of this fact. For example, bacteria continually divide and multiply through asexual reproduction. They die from lack of food, being eaten, or being physically destroyed. Hypothetically, if their ideal conditions were met (i.e., sufficient food, absence of predators, and a safe environment), they could continue to divide forever.Footnote 41 This is decisively different from organisms born through sexual reproduction, who always die, regardless of ideal conditions. For approximately 1.8 billion years after the emergence of life (i.e., approximately 3.8 billion years ago), prokaryotes were the only living organisms on Earth. Thus, death was not an inevitable event for organisms.Footnote 42 Even today, death is not inevitable for organisms that reproduce asexually. Life has created a strategy within the evolutionary process, such that death always intervenes to sustain life. In this way, organisms first possessed a lifespan that is inextricably linked to sexual reproduction. Lifespan and death are not of the same dimension, as bacteria, which do not possess a lifespan, also die.

In contrast to asexual reproduction, in which death may or may not occur, the emergence of sexual reproduction sublimated the coincidence of death into an inevitability that no individual could avoid, in principle. Organisms in which individuals are necessarily genetically different from each other through sexual reproduction and in which all inevitably die have acquired the concept of generations, which is not present in organisms that reproduce asexually. Correspondingly, the impossibility of experiencing this inevitable event and of converting it into a known has been passed down intergenerationally. An understanding of the universal unknown lies behind the biological concept of alternation of generations, which is related to the most fundamental division of organisms: prokaryotes and eukaryotes. Without being aware of doing so, biological science’s examination of evolution from asexual to sexual reproduction has revealed a completely new dimension of life—my death.

The fact that the concept of my death emerged along with sexual reproduction can also be understood from the perspectives of continuity and discontinuity. As my death always interrupts an individual’s life, it naturally connects to a discontinuity, but not to one that is not unified with continuity or does not bring about continuity. When the survival strategy is to divide and multiply, if at all possible, it follows that the death of each individual should be avoided, if at all possible. Given the harsh realities of the environment, many cells that divide and multiply will die, leaving only a few to survive; however, death in asexual reproduction is a matter of “chance” for individuals, because they do not die equally. By contrast, sexual reproduction destines individuals to inevitable death as the key to reproduction; its survival strategy is to ensure that each individual’s life is interrupted, allowing the life that runs through it to survive.Footnote 43 Therefore, this death can be seen as one that is discontinuous yet connected to continuity at its foundation, or one that secures the continuity that emerges from discontinuity.

Thus, my death is both existential and biological. One can argue that reproductive theory approaches and describes my death concretely as a concept that completes my rearview. In this regard, this theory has the potential to bring biology closer to an understanding of my death, not just death. However, as mentioned, biology does not focus on death as an inherent theme. Even in reproductive theory, death is just a potential theme and my death is only addressed as the obverse of reproduction. Therefore, to a large extent, the task of expanding this potential falls to the philosophers.

5 Conclusion

This study focused on the movement between the unknown/continuity and the known/discontinuity, elucidating the essential commonality between the foundation of science’s progress and the foundation of my consciousness and body, the kind of unknown that scientific activities confront, and the contact point between biology and philosophy. The investigation of the scientific importance of my death reveals the scholarly significance of the unknown, which penetrates different fields. Although the discussion has been limited to interpreting the outcomes of reproductive theory and clarifying the relationship between biology and my death, not just biology but science as a whole can be regarded as having my death at its foundation. No one can confirm that the universe will not end with my death. Scientists, who are mortal, can present the truth only based on the premise that the universe that science seeks to reveal will continue to exist after my death. Importantly, this fact does not imply that the outcomes of science are equivocal. As this study has clarified, the continuity of the universe, which encompasses discontinuities, can be affirmed, especially because my death disrupts my life and completes my rearview. As no I can confirm the survival of the universe after my death, science and its outcomes are meaningful to us. Future scientific progress could place a greater distance between me and my death, but it should not be able to cause me to experience my death. My death should continue to remain beyond the reach of science, constituting the foundation of the universe that science seeks to reveal.

For future studies, philosophically interpreting biological research on reproduction from the perspective of my death, especially in line with the evolution of reproductive mechanisms, should be an important direction. In this sense, hypothetical theories on the mysterious origins of sexual reproduction and death are important themes. Additionally, whether we consider lifespans to be “present” or “absent” also constitutes an interesting philosophical question from the perspective of continuity and discontinuity. Regarding limitations of the study, I was unable to concretize how the continuity that emerges within the discontinuity corresponds to the unknown of my rearview, as my study’s focus is restricted to clarifying the relationship between continuity and discontinuity. Continuity within discontinuity is like magma, gushing forth with enormous energy. Future research can attempt to elucidate this aspect to clarify the inherent relationship between biology and philosophy further. In addition, clarifying how an epistemological project like this study could relate to my death as a question with emotional earnestness, such as feelings for my family that has been left behind, is an important subject for expanding the scope of this study and further clarifying its significance.