Skip to main content
Log in

The act of forgetting: Husserl on the constitution of the absent past

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I advance a phenomenology of forgetting based on Husserl’s accounts of time-consciousness and passive synthesis. This theory of forgetting is crucial for understanding the transcendental constitution of the past. I argue that without forgetting, neither memory nor retention suffice for a consciousness of the past as past, since both are irreducibly connected to the Living Present. After an initial survey of the challenges that confront a phenomenology of forgetting (i.e. the “forgotten” is defined by its lack of phenomenality), I provide a descriptive analysis of forgetting as a complex process that integrates an accomplishment of retention that Husserl called “temporal contraction” with an accomplishment of passive synthesis that Husserl called “affective fusion.” Temporal contraction is the accomplishment that creates a qualitative (not quantitative) distinction between near-retentions and far-retentions. Affective fusion enables us to provide a positive (not privative) phenomenological description of the withdrawal of egoic investment in intentional experiences. Taken together, these two syntheses generate a double concealment in which consciousness both forgets its object and forgets that it has forgotten it, thereby constituting it as part of the truly absent past.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Husserl (2001b, p. 201 [Hua XI pp. 153–154]). I will use English translations of Husserl’s works wherever possible and add the corresponding Husserliana edition page numbers in square brackets.

  2. Husserl did make sleep a theme of phenomenology as a “limit phenomenon”: Husserl (2013, pp. 26–46).

  3. Granel (1968) quoted in Bégout (2001, p. 211).

  4. On the connection of forgetting, memory, and the crisis, see: Buckley (1992, pp. 80–92).

  5. Bernet (1983); Boehm (1975); Brough (1975); Sokolowski (1974, pp. 141–158).

  6. Husserl (1991, pp. 55–61 [ Hua X pp. 53–59]).

  7. Deleuze (1994, p. 80). I am admittedly co-opting this statement from Deleuze for my own purposes, but to offer some defence of my appropriation here, see Deleuze’s analysis of the pure past in Bergson: Deleuze (1991, pp. 56–62).

  8. Husserl (1991, p. 31 [Hua X p. 29]).

  9. Husserl (1991, pp. 29–31, 78 [Hua X pp. 27–29, 74]).

  10. Husserl coined the terms Längsintentionalität (horizontal intentionality) and Querintentionalität (transverse intentionality) to describe the two orientations of retention. Husserl (1991, pp. 86–87 [Hua X pp. 81–82]).

  11. I borrow the imagery of “encasement” (emboîtement) from Duval (1990, pp. 49–51).

  12. See Brough, (1972 pp. 318–319).

  13. Husserl (1991, p. 28 [Hua X p. 26]). Brough translates “Zusammengerücktheit” as “compression.”

  14. Husserl (1991, p. 142 [Hua X pp. 137–138]). Kortooms captures this visually with a wonderfully precise diagram. See Kortooms (2002, p. 172).

  15. Rodemeyer offers a much richer image to make this subtle process more intuitive. She describes it in terms of the mise en abîme effect produced by two mirrors facing each other: “Each image is contained within the next into infinity, and yet, each image is distinguishable in itself while relying upon the whole for its existence. Spatially, these two mirrors do not ‘move away’ from each other, and yet their ‘activity’ of reflection causes their images to become less and less clear.” Rodemeyer (2006, p. 90).

  16. Husserl (1991, pp. 377–378 [Hua X p. 367]).

  17. Husserl (2001a, p. 69).

  18. Husserl (2001a, p. 72). My translation and emphasis.

  19. For Husserl’s description of egoity as consisting solely in a wakeful style of carrying out intentional comportments, see Husserl (1974, p. 363).

  20. Husserl (2001b, p. 197 [Hua XI pp. 149–150]).

  21. Husserl (2001b, p. 203 [Hua XI pp. 155–156]).

  22. Husserl (2001b, p. 67 [Hua XI p. 122]).

  23. Husserl (2001b, p. 220 [Hua XI p. 171]).

  24. Husserl (2001b, p. 220 [Hua XI p. 171]).

  25. Husserl (2001b, p. 532 [Hua XI p. 426]).

  26. Husserl (2001b, pp. 526–527 [Hua XI p. 422]). My emphasis.

  27. Casey expresses this eloquently, though he does not tie the doubleness of forgetting to time-consciousness and affectivity specifically, but rather to an inherent complexity or pluriformity of forgetting which modern philosophy has “forgotten” (1992, 285–288, 303–304). For an account of the Greek roots of the doubleness of forgetting, and the German interpretation of those Greek roots, see Chrétien (2002, pp. 1–40). Chrétien does not draw upon Husserl but Heidegger for his discussion of original forgetting—which in Heidegger is not a failure of memory, but a condition of possibility of both memory and repetition (2002, p. 32). The most salient point of contact between our Husserlian analyses in this essay and Heidegger’s own account of the past is facticity (rather than, say, Heidegger’s account of how philosophers have forgotten to pose the question concerning the meaning of being). One always comes to oneself as already existing in the world, before being able to account for how one has gotten here; Heidegger’s description of Dasein’s facticity concerns a form of the past that Dasein does not explicitly represent to itself, but a past that it is. Heidegger (1962, 373–376, 388–389); see also Richardson (1963, pp. 85–90).

  28. Husserl calls affection a “function of contrast” (2001, p. 197 [Hua XI p. 149]).

  29. Husserl (2001, p. 217 [Hua XI p. 168]).

  30. Tyman (1983), Biceaga (2010) and Kozyreva (2018) also characterize the liminal awareness of past experience as a kind of background, horizonal consciousness, though none explicitly distinguish the operations of time-consciousness and affectivity in this regard.

  31. Husserl (2001b, pp. 591–623 [Hua XI pp. 304–335]).

  32. Husserl (2001b, p. 220 [Hua XI p. 171]; see also p. 609 [Hua XI p. 321]).

  33. Husserl (2001b, p. 619 [Hua XI p. 331]).

  34. Husserl (2001b, pp. 218–219 [Hua XI p. 170]).

  35. Husserl (2001b, pp. 219–220 [Hua XI p. 171]).

  36. Husserl (2001b, pp. 220–221, 223 [Hua XI pp. 172, 174]).

  37. Husserl (2001b, p. 216 [Hua XI p. 167]).

  38. Bégout makes this clear (2001, pp. 33–38). See also Holenstein’s articulation of the distinction between “Urassoziation” and “Assoziation im gewöhnlichem Sinn”; Holenstein (1972, pp. 32–39).

  39. As Husserl sometimes maintained; see Husserl (1991, pp. 202–203 [Hua X pp. 195–196]) and Husserl (1977, pp. 324–325). The basic thought is that since absolute consciousness continues to constitute new impressional moments while one is remembering, the reproduced track of experience can never catch up to the impressional track of experience. I think this is right but offering a full defence and demonstration of the phenomenological virtues of this position would require its own lengthy treatment.

  40. Augustine (1961, pp. 222–223).

References

  • Augustine of Hippo. 1961. Confessions, tr. R. S. Pine-Coffin. London: Penguin.

  • Bégout, Bruce. 2001. La généalogie de la logique. Husserl, l’antéprédicatif et le catégorial. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernet, Rudolf. 1983. La présence du passé dans l’analyse husserlienne du temps. Revue de métaphysique et de morale 88 (2): 178–198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biceaga, Victor. 2010. The Concept of Passivity in Husserl’s Phenomenology. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boehm, Rudolf. 1975. Bewußtsein als Gegenwart des Vergangenen. The Monist 59 (1): 21–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brough, John. 1975. Husserl on Memory. The Monist 59 (1): 40–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brough, John. 1972. “The Emergence of an Absolute Consciousness in Husserl’s Early Writings on Time-Consciousness. Man and World 5: 298–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckley, Philip. 1992. Husserl, Heidegger and the Crisis of Philosophical Responsibility. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Casey, Edward. 1992. Forgetting Remembered. Man and World 25: 281–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chrétien, Jean-Louis. 2002. The Unforgettable and the Unhoped for, tr. J. Bloechel. New York: Fordham UP.

  • Deleuze, Gilles. 1994. Difference and Repetition, tr. P. Patton. New York: Columbia UP.

  • Deleuze, Gilles. 1991. Bergsonism, tr. H. Tomlinson and B. Habberiam. New York: Zone Books.

  • Granel, Gérard. 1968. Le sens du temps et de la perception chez E. Husserl. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duval, Raymond. 1990. Temps et vigilance. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and Time, trs. J. Macquarrie and E. Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Holenstein, Elmar. 1972. Phänomenologie der Assoziation. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2013. Grenzprobleme der Phänomenologie. Husserliana, vol. XLII. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2001a. Die Bernauer Manuskripte über das Zeitbewusstsein (1917/1918). Husserliana XXXIII. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 2001b. Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis, tr. A. J. Steinbock. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1991. The Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time, tr. J. B. Brough. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1977. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch. Husserliana, vol. III/1. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1974. Formale und Transzendentale Logik Husserliana, vol. XVII. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1969. Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins. Husserliana, vol. X. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1966. Analyse der Passiven Synthesis. Husserliana, vol. XI. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kortooms, Toine. 2002. Phenomenology of Time. Edmund Husserl’s Analysis of Time-Consciousness. Phenomenologica, vol. 161. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kozyreva, Anastasia. 2018. Non-Representational Approaches to the Unconscious in the Phenomenology of Husserl and Merleau-Ponty. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17 (1): 199–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, William. 1963. Heidegger: Through Phenomenology to Thought. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rodemeyer, Lanei. 2006. Intersubjective Temporality. It’s About Time. Phenomenologica, vol. 176. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, Robert. 1974. Husserlian Meditations. Evanston: Northwestern UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tyman, Stephen. 1983. The Phenomenology of Forgetting. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44 (1): 45–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Eldridge.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Eldridge, P. The act of forgetting: Husserl on the constitution of the absent past. Cont Philos Rev 53, 401–417 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-020-09501-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-020-09501-0

Keywords

Navigation