Skip to main content
Log in

A hermeneutical sketch of memory and the immemorial

  • Published:
Continental Philosophy Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In one of his more recent works, Paul Ricoeur attempts to re-instate the philosophical discussion of memory at the very center of a more general discourse on human existence. In his exposition, Ricoeur relies upon what he himself characterizes as a phenomenology of memory. It is the aim of the present article to supplement the phenomenological account of memory discussed by Ricoeur with a hermeneutics of memory conscious of its own limitations. Such a hermeneutical supplement would not only be of complementary value but also provoke a rethinking of the relation between key concepts in the western discourse on memory, such as image, imprint, and trace. In this regard, the proposed hermeneutical reconfiguration of memory exceeds its own limitations and overflows into an investigation of the primordial passive and past ground, which motivates and allows the hermeneutical activity in the first place. Following the analyses of Emmanuel Lévinas, I will argue that this immemorial past must be conceived in terms of a responsibility that cannot be fulfilled.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Ricoeur (2004, p. xvi).

  2. Ricoeur (2004, pp. 21–44).

  3. Hannoum (2005, p. 124).

  4. Ricoeur (2004, p. 7).

  5. Ricoeur (2004, p. 12).

  6. Ricoeur (2004, pp. 17–21).

  7. Ricoeur (2004, p. 46).

  8. Ricoeur (2004, pp. 50–55).

  9. Ricoeur (2004, p. 52) and Bergson (1950, p. 171).

  10. Ricoeur (2004, p. 51).

  11. De memoria et reminiscentia 449b15, translated and commented in: Richard Sorabji, Aristotle on Memory, 2nd ed. ed. (London: Duckworth, 2004).

  12. De memoria et reminiscentia 453a13–14.

  13. Ricoeur (2004, p. 21).

  14. Ricoeur (2004, p. 52).

  15. Ricoeur (2004, p. 54).

  16. Ricoeur (2004, p. 24).

  17. Ricoeur (2004, p. 26).

  18. Ricoeur (2004, p. 27).

  19. Ricoeur (2004, p. 28).

  20. Ricoeur (2004, p. 24).

  21. Ricoeur (2004, p. 26).

  22. Ricoeur (2004, p. 25).

  23. Ricoeur (2004, pp. 37–38).

  24. Ricoeur (2004, p. 50).

  25. Ricoeur (2004, p. 36).

  26. Ricoeur (2004, p. 43).

  27. Ricoeur (2004, pp. 36–44).

  28. Ricoeur (2004, p. 36).

  29. See Casey (1987).

  30. Ricoeur (2004, p. 40).

  31. Ricoeur (2004, p. 40).

  32. I do not wish to suggest here that reading Husserl as relying on subjectivist idealism is in itself unproblematic. Indeed, Ricoeur admits that these tendencies in Husserl are somewhat remedied when Husserl in his later works introduces the concept of Lebenswelt (Ricoeur 2004, p. 36f.). My claim here is thus not the strong claim of dismissing Husserl as a subjectivist idealist, but rather to point to the fact that those elements which Ricoeur sees as problematic in Husserl to a certain extent is carried over into his own account of memory.

  33. Ricoeur (2004, p. 294).

  34. Heidegger (1996, pp. 151–154).

  35. Heidegger (1996, p. 153).

  36. Heidegger (1996, p. 148).

  37. Heidegger (1996, p. 148).

  38. Heidegger (1996, pp. 144–150).

  39. These considerations are not meant to define memory as strictly personal and exclude the idea of a collective memory as discussed in Ricoeur (2004, pp. 93–132). In this regard, the concepts of ‘world’ and ‘inhabiting’ are neutral concerning the ascription to a personal or collective subject.

  40. Ricoeur (2004, pp. 69–80).

  41. Lotz (2004) discusses the relation between Husserlian recollection and the concept of mourning and tries to show, from a different angle than the one presented here, how the phenomenological account of memory must necessarily push itself beyond its own boundaries towards an absolute, non-representable past.

  42. The process of internalization is discussed by Ricoeur (2004, pp. 58–68) and ranges all the way from simple learning to an ars memoria that combines mnemotecnics with the initiation into hermetic secrets.

  43. Heidegger (1996, p. 63ff.).

  44. Heidegger (1996, pp. 77–80).

  45. Heidegger (1996, pp. 77–80).

  46. Heidegger (1996, pp. 126–131).

  47. Heidegger (1996, p. 129): “The moodedness of attunement constitutes existentially the openness to world of Da-sein.”

  48. One may note the grammatical past tense involved in the concept of thrownness (Geworfenheit). This in itself implies that attunement, by being an openness or disclosure of a past thrownness, is intimately connected to some sort of memory.

  49. Heidegger (1996, p. 129).

  50. Heidegger (1996, p. 202f).

  51. Heidegger (1996, p. 126f).

  52. That is, the openness is determined through the twofold structure of “always-being-my-own-being” (Jemeinigkeit) and “to be” (Zu-sein) discussed in Heidegger (1996, p. 39ff).

  53. The following analysis of the trace and its connection to representation and memory is, admittedly, inspired by Emmanuel Lévinas’ treatment of the subject, especially Lévinas (1963) and (1965).

  54. Greisch (2004, p. 90).

  55. Blanchot (1982, p. 51).

  56. Cf. Edward Casey’s (1988, p. 249) illuminating study of the concept of trace in Lévinas.

  57. Lévinas (1998, p. 51ff).

  58. Lévinas (1998, p. 51).

  59. Lévinas (1987, p. 118).

References

  • Bergson, Henri-Louis. 1950. Matter and memory (trans: Nancy M. Paul and W. Scott Palmer). London: Allen and Unwin.

  • Blanchot, Maurice. 1982. The space of writing (trans: Ann Smock). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.

  • Casey, Edward. 1987. Remembering: A phenomenological study. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casey, Edward. 1988. Levinas on memory and the trace. In The Collegium Phaenomenologicum, ed. J.C. Sallis, G. Moneta, and J. Taminiaux. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greisch, Jean. 2004. Trace and forgetting: Between the threat of erasure and the persistance of the unerasable. Diogenes 51: 77–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hannoum, Abdelmajid. 2005. Paul Ricoeur on memory. Theory, Culture and Society 22(6): 123–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1996. Being and time (trans: Joan Stambaugh). New York: State University of New York Press.

  • Lévinas, Emmanuel. 1963. La trace de l’autre. Tijdskrift voor Filosofie 25(3): 605–623.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévinas, Emmanuel. 1965. Énigme et phénomène. Esprit 33: 1128–1142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévinas, Emmanuel. 1987. Time and the other (trans: Richard A. Cohen). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

  • Lévinas, Emmanuel. 1998. Otherwise than being or beyond essence (trans: Alphonso Lingis). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

  • Lotz, Christian. 2004. Recollection, mourning, and the absolute past: On Husserl, Freud, and Derrida. In The new yearbook for phenomenology and phenomenological philosophy (IV2004), ed. Hopkins, Burt. Seattle: Noesis Press.

  • Ricoeur, Paul. 2004. Memory, history, forgetting (trans: Kathleen Blamey and David Pellauer). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • Sorabji, Richard. 2004. Aristotle on memory, 2nd ed. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jon Utoft Nielsen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nielsen, J.U. A hermeneutical sketch of memory and the immemorial. Cont Philos Rev 44, 401–416 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-011-9198-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11007-011-9198-1

Keywords

Navigation