Skip to main content
Log in

The proper treatment of variables in predicate logic

  • Published:
Linguistics and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In §93 of The Principles of Mathematics, Bertrand Russell (1903) observes that “the variable is a very complicated logical entity, by no means easy to analyze correctly”. This assessment is borne out by the fact that even now we have no fully satisfactory understanding of the role of variables in a compositional semantics for first-order logic. In standard Tarskian semantics, variables are treated as meaning-bearing entities; moreover, they serve as the basic building blocks of all meanings, which are constructed out of variable assignments. But this has disquieting consequences, including Fine’s antinomy of the variable and an undue dependence of meanings on language (representationalism). Here I develop an alternative, Fregean version of predicate logic that uses the traditional quantifier–variable apparatus for the expression of generality, possesses a fully compositional, non-representational semantics, and is not subject to the antinomy of the variable. The advantages of Fregean over Tarskian predicate logic are due to the former’s treating variables not as meaningful lexical items, but as mere marks of punctuation, similar to parentheses. I submit that this is indeed how the variables of predicate logic should be construed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Benacerraf, P. (1965). What numbers could not be. The Philosophical Review, 74, 47–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourbaki, N. (1954). Éléments de Mathématique: Théorie des Ensembles. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1982). Some concepts and consequences of the theory of government and binding. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1995). The minimalist program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Curry, H., & Feys, R. (1958). Combinatory logic (Vol. I). Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1973). Frege: Philosophy of language. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1977). Pronouns, quantifiers, and relative clauses (I). Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7(3), 467–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2000). Neutral relations. Philosophical Review, 109(1), 1–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2003). The role of variables. Journal of Philosophy, 100(12), 605–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2007). Semantic relationism. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1893). Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, Volume I, Jena: Hermann Pohle. English translation in P. Ebert and M. Rossberg (editors and translators), Gottlob Frege: Basic Laws of Arithmetic. Oxford: Oxford University Press (2013).

  • Geurts, B., Beaver, D., & Maier, E. (2016). Discourse representation theory. In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2016). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/discourse-representation-theory/.

  • Heim, I., & Kratzer, A. (1998). Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (1983). Logical form, binding, and nominals. Linguistic Inquiry, 14(3), 395–420.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D., & Ackermann, W. (1938). Grundzüge der theoretischen Logik. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D., & Bernays, P. (1934). Grundlagen der Mathematik I. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone, L. (2000). What \(Fa\) says about \(a\). Dialectica, 54(1), 3–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, P. (1999). Towards a variable-free semantics. Linguistics and Philosophy, 22, 117–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobson, P. (2003). Binding without pronouns (and pronouns without binding). In R. Oehrle & G.-J. Kruiff (Eds.), Resource-sensitivity, binding, and anaphora (pp. 57–96). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Janssen, T. (1997). Compositionality. In J. van Benthem & A. ter Meulen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and language (pp. 417–473). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Janssen, T. (2011). Compositionality. In J. van Benthem & A. ter Meulen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and language (2nd ed., pp. 495–554). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Janssen, T. (2012). Compositionality: Its historic context. In M. Werning, W. Hinzen, & E. Machery (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of compositionality (pp. 19–46). Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1986). Opacity. In L. E. Hahn & P. A. Schilpp (Eds.), The philosophy of W. V. Quine (pp. 229–289). La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, U., & Sternefeld, W. (2017). Same same but different: An alphabetically innocent compositional predicate logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 46(1), 65–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kracht, M. (2011). Lectures on interpreted languages and compositionality. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (1995). Stage-level and individual-level predicates as inherent generics. In G. N. Carlson & F. J. Pelletier (Eds.), The generic book (pp. 125–175). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemmon, E. J. (1965). Beginning logic. Princeton: Van Nostrand.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marsh, W., & Partee, B. (1987). How non-context free is variable binding? In W. Savitch, et al. (Eds.), The formal complexity of natural language (Studies in linguistics and philosophy 33) (pp. 369–386). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • May, R. (1977). The grammar of quantification. Doctoral dissertation, MIT.

  • May, R. (2006). The invariance of sense. Journal of Philosophy, 103(3), 111–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1973). The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In K. J. J. Hintikka, J. M. E. Moravcsik, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Approaches to natural language (pp. 221–242). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, P., & Westerstahl, D. (2010). Compositionality I: Definitions and variants. Philosophy Compass, 5(3), 250–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. (2013). The starring role of quantifiers in the history of formal semantics. In V. Punčochář & P. Švarný (Eds.), The logica yearbook 2012 (pp. 113–136). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickel, B. (2010). Syntax in basic laws §§29–32. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 51(2), 253–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickel, B., & Rabern, B. (2016). The antinomy of the variable: A Tarskian resolution. Journal of Philosophy, 113(3), 137–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potts, C. (2002). No vacuous quantification constraints in syntax. In M. Hirotani (Ed.), Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society (Vol. 32, pp. 451–470).

  • Quine, W. (1940). Mathematical logic. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1960). Variables explained away. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 104, 343–347.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1903). The principles of mathematics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schütte, K. (1977). Proof theory. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, P. (2003). An introduction to formal logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tennant, N. (1978). Natural logic. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Benthem, J. (1987). Logical syntax. Theoretical Linguistics, 14(2–3), 119–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1985). Converse relations. Philosophical Review, 94(2), 249–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1922). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmermann, T. E., & Sternefeld, W. (2013). Introduction to semantics. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kai F. Wehmeier.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Wehmeier, K.F. The proper treatment of variables in predicate logic. Linguist and Philos 41, 209–249 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-017-9224-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10988-017-9224-9

Keywords

Navigation