Skip to main content
Log in

Copies from "Standard Set Theory"? A Note on the Foundations of Minimalist Syntax in Reaction to Chomsky, Gallego and Ott (2019)

  • Published:
Journal of Logic, Language and Information Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Appeal to standard set theory in (mainstream) minimalist syntax is shown to be in conflict with the goal of analyzing dependency formation, a.k.a. movement, as involving genuine constituent copies. The underlying tension is due to (the axiom of) extensionality, which—other things being equal—favors a perspective on dependencies in terms of multidominance. The above argument is developed against the backdrop of a recent exposition of minimalist syntax (Chomsky et al. in Catal J Linguist (Special Issue):229–261, 2019), which can be seen as exemplary. The resulting critical assessment should be taken as removing obstacles on the way toward proper minimalist foundations for syntactic theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. I cite selected examplary work from the vast body of literature without in any way implying exhaustiveness.

  2. Scare quotes ("…")—not formally distinguished from direct quotes— are used throughout to flag terminology that would require critical discussion and thorough motivation, sidestepped here in the interest of conciseness.

  3. Langendoen (2003:309) proposes to distinguish the respective cases as Merge(γ122) and Merge(γ211). If in addition the "Extension Condition" (Chomsky 1993:23) or the "No Tampering Condition" (Chomsky 2007:8) holds, the root node of the containing constituent is a ("global") root in the technical sense of being undominated.

  4. The definition of "sp" is given in (i):

    1. (i) a

      sp(p) = {p} b sp(a) = \(\bigcup\)xa sp(x)

    This crucially presupposes the existence of "urelements" (Barwise 1975:1.1), a rather "natural" assumption in the context of syntactic structures "projected from" lexical formatives, "roots," or whatever else constitutes "terminals." Variable p ranges over urelements, a over sets, and x over the union of the sets of urelements and sets (Barwise 1975:10).

  5. People who like concrete examples could imagine that a is Artemis and that (1b) describes the current organizational structure of the scientific board for the preservation of Keynesianism in Greece (SBPKG). Imagine further that the statutes of the SBPKG stipulate that it consist of exactly one leader and a two person subcommittee, the advisory committee for the SBPKG, i.e., ACSBPKG. Then (1b) says that currently Artemis is leader of the SBPKG and happens, at the same time, to be member of the ACSBPKG, together with Basilius. At a meeting of the SBPKG, Artemis will be present only once. Noone would expect (or allow) any copy or double of Artemis to show up. Whether she has one or two votes is another matter.

  6. Guimarães (2000: section 4) relies on this fundamental set-theoretic property in his analysis of "Self-Merge," where, applied to example (1), Merge(γ11) = { a }.

  7. The definition by Troelstra (1992:2) reads: "A multiset over A is a mapping f: A → ℕ, where f(a) = n means that a occurs with multiplicity n. If f(a) = 0, a is not an element of f (that is to say, a occurs with multiplicity 0)." Thus, assuming A = { a, b, c }, the multiset in (4b) is given by:  f(4b) = { 〈a,2〉, 〈b,1〉, 〈c,0〉 }.

  8. CGO's discussion of phases, Spell-Out, Transfer, and (in)accessibility of constituents (pp. 240–242) is relevant for determining their perspective here.

  9. "Consider a syntactic object SO = { S1, { S1, S2 } }. We say that S1 occurs twice in SO. The position of an occurrence is given by a "path" from SO to the particular occurrence. A path is a sequence of syntactic objects 〈SO1, SO2, …, SOn〉 where for every adjacent pair SOi, SOi+1 of objects in the path, SOi+1 ∈ SOi (i.e., SOi+1 is immediately contained in SOi)." Collins and Stabler (l.c.) also discuss open questions about and shortcomings of alternative definitions.

  10. Elsewhere, Merge is explicitly characterized as either applying to two "syntactic objects" (Chomsky 1995:208; 2000:101; 2008:137), two "objects" (Chomsky 2005:11; Chomsky 2009:25; Chomsky 2013:40), two "elements" (Chomsky 2004:108), or two "structures" (Chomsky 2007:5).

  11. A perhaps less felicitously phrased passage on the obscureness of the relation between set theory and (structural aspects of) natural language syntax (Chomsky 2012:91) can be understood as conveying the same "warning." For a not so charitable interpretation, see Behme (2015).

  12. As, for example, the system of propositional logic is usually taken to form part of the system of predicate logic.

  13. The syntax of set theory (as relevant here) can be built from individual constants "a", "b", "c" etc., the two-place predicate constant "∈", and the "syncategorematic" expressions "{" (left bracket), "}" (right bracket), and "," (comma). And its (extensional) semantics (as relevant here) can be given in terms of a model ⟨D,I〉 with D the universe of things set theory is about and I an interpretation function such that, in particular, I(a), I(b), I(c) etc. are members of D, and I(∈)⊆D×D. Given that I is a function, any use of the name "a" refers to the same thing, I(a). This is another way of saying that "standard set theory" does not support interpretation of (1b) ({ a, { a, b } }) as involving two "copies" in the sense of two entities. To insist on the latter amounts to an appeal to a particular syntax of set theory with its subtle "excess of notation over subject matter" (Quine, 1995:5).

References

  • Bagaria, J. (2019). Set theory. In E. Zalta (Ed.) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy.

  • Barwise, J. (1975). Admissible sets and structures. An approach to definability theory. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behme, C. (2015). Is the ontology of biolinguistics coherent? Language Sciences, 15, 32–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bobaljik, J. (1995). In terms of merge. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics, 27, 41–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1993). A minimalist program for linguistic theory. In K. Hale & S. Keyser (Eds.), The view from building 20 (pp. 1–52). MIT Press.

  • Chomsky, N. (1995). Categories and transformations. In The minimalist program (pp. 219–394). MIT Press.

  • Chomsky, N. (2000). Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In R. Martin, D. Michaels, & J. Uriagereka (Eds.), Step by step (pp. 89–155). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2004). Beyond explanatory adequacy. In A. Belletti (Ed.), Structures and beyond (pp. 104–131). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2005). Three factors in language design. Linguistic Inquiry, 36, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2007). Approaching UG from below. In U. Sauerland & H.-M. Gärtner (Eds.), Interfaces + recursion = language? (pp. 1–29). Mouton de Gruyter.

  • Chomsky, N. (2008). On phases. In R. Freidin, C. Otero, & M. L. Zubizaretta (Eds.), Foundational issues in linguistic theory (pp. 133–166). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2009). Opening remarks. In M. Piattelli-Palmarini, J. Uriagereka, & P. Salaburu (Eds.), Of minds and language. A dialogue with Noam Chomsky in the Basque Country (pp. 13–43). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2012). The science of language. Interviews with James McGilvray. CUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (2013). Problems of projection. Lingua, 130, 33–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N., Gallego, A., & Ott, D. (2019). Generative grammar and the faculty of language: Insights, questions, and challenges. Catalan Journal of Linguistics (Special Issue), 229–261.

  • Citko, B. (2011). Multidominance. In C. Boeckx (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of linguistic minimalism (pp. 119–142). OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, C. (1994). Economy of derivation and the generalized proper binding condition. Linguistic Inquiry, 25, 45–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins, C., & Stabler, E. (2016). A formalization of minimalist syntax. Syntax, 19, 43–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corver, N., & Nunes, J. (2007). From trace theory to copy theory. In N. Corver & J. Nunes (Eds.), The copy theory of movement (pp. 1–9). John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ferreirós, J. (2007). Labyrinth of thought. A history of set theory and its role in modern mathematics. Birkhäuser.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärtner, H.-M. (2002). Generalized transformations and beyond. Akademie-Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guimarães, M. (2000). In defense of vacuous projections in bare phrase structure. University of Maryland Working Papers in Linguistics, 9, 90–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halmos, P. R. (1974). Naive set theory. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langendoen, T. (2003). Merge. In A. Carnie, H. Harley, & M. Willie (Eds.), Formal approaches to function in grammar (pp. 307–318). John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nunes, J. (2004). Linearization of chains and sideward movement. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, WVO. (1995). Whitehead and the rise of modern logic. In Selected logic papers (pp. 1–36). Harvard University Press.

  • Suppes, P. (1972). Axiomatic set theory. Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, S. (2010a). Traces or copies, or both—Part I: Characterizing movement properties. Language and Linguistics Compass, 4, 1091–1103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, S. (2010b). Traces or copies, or both—Part II: Introducing further considerations. Language and Linguistics Compass, 4, 1104–1115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thiersch, C. (2017). Remnant movement. In M. Everaert & H. van Riemsdijk (Eds.), The Wiley Blackwell companion to syntax. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Troelstra, A. S. (1992). Lectures on linear logic. CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For reactions to an earlier draft I am grateful to David Adger, Norbert Hornstein, and Thomas Ede Zimmermann. Likewise, I am grateful to the anonymous reviewer. Remaining shortcomings are my own responsibility.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hans-Martin Gärtner.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gärtner, HM. Copies from "Standard Set Theory"? A Note on the Foundations of Minimalist Syntax in Reaction to Chomsky, Gallego and Ott (2019). J of Log Lang and Inf 31, 129–135 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-021-09342-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10849-021-09342-x

Keywords

Navigation