Skip to main content
Log in

Ontic Structuralism and the Symmetries of Particle Physics

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to structural realism, in mature science there is structural continuity along theoretical change. A major counterexample to this thesis is the transition from the Eightfold Way to the Standard Model in particle physics. Nevertheless, the notion of structure is significantly important in comprehending the theoretical picture of particle physics, where particles change and undergo transmutations, while the only thing which remains unchanged is the basic structure, i.e. the symmetry group which controls the transmutations. This kind of view agrees with the paradigmatic case where the structure is an internal symmetry and the instantiations are the elementary particles. The metaphysical view which reflects this situation is a version of ontic structuralism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Private communication with Yuval Ne’eman.

  2. “Unitary symmetry” and “unitaty spin” were employed as alternative names to the Eightfold Way.

  3. By the term “rotations” I mean transformations of the group in internal space, e.g. one which carries every proton to a neutron and vice versa; it has nothing to do with rotations in ordinary space-time and with ordinary observers in relativity theory.

  4. SU(2) has one Casimir operator so that each of it representations is characterized by one number, whereas SU(3) has two such operators so that each of its representations is characterized by two numbers.

  5. After the failure in detecting the proton decay, SU(5) has been somewhat discredited, but since there are many alternatives to it, none of which is considered to be perfect, I still use this group as an illustration.

  6. WOS differs considerably from “moderate structural realism” advocated by Esfeld and Lam. According to the latter view “objects and relations (structure) are on the same ontological footing, with the objects being characterized only by the relations in which they stand” (Esfeld and Lam 2008).

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1983). What is a law of nature?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1993). The identification problem and the inference problem. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 53, 421–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. R. (1994). Smoke and mirrors: How science reflects reality. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Busch, J. (2003). What structures could not be. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 17, 211–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cao, T. (2003). Structural realism and the interpretation of quantum field theory. Synthese, 136, 3–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44, 248–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. (2002). Laws, symmetry, and symmetry breaking; invariance, conservation principles, and objectivity. 18 Biennial Mtg, PSA 2002 Symposia.

  • Esfeld, M., & Lam, V. (2008). Moderate structural realism about space-time. Synthese, 160, 27–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (1999). Models and mathematics in physics: The role of group theory. In J. Butterfield & C. Pagonis (Eds.), From physics to philosophy (pp. 187–207). Cambridge: Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • French, S., & Ladyman, J. (2003). Remodelling structural realism: Quantum physics and the metaphysics of structure. Synthese, 136, 31–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kantorovich, A. (1993). Scientific discovery: Logic and tinkering. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kantorovich, A. (2003). The priority of internal symmetries in particle physics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 34, 651–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosso, P. (2000). Fundamental and accidental symmetries. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 14, 109–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (1998). What is structural realism? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 409–424.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2007). “Structural realism” entry in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (SEP). Internet.

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalised. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lyre, H. (2004). Holism and structuralism in U(1) gauge theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 35, 643–670.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, B. (2009). Group structural realism. Blog: SoulPhysics.org.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stachel, J. (2005). Structures, individuality and quantum gravity. In D. P. Rickles, et al. (Eds.), Structural foundations of quantum gravity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1977). The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7, 667–698.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43, 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aharon Kantorovich.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kantorovich, A. Ontic Structuralism and the Symmetries of Particle Physics. J Gen Philos Sci 40, 73–84 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-009-9084-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-009-9084-2

Keywords

Navigation