Skip to main content
Log in

The Badness of Death for Sociable Cattle

  • Published:
The Journal of Value Inquiry Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Correction to this article was published on 14 December 2023

This article has been updated

Abstract

I argue that death can be (and sometimes is) bad for cattle because it destroys relationships that are valuable for cattle for their own sake. The argument relies on an analogy between valuable human relationships and relationships cattle form with conspecifics. I suggest that the reasons we have for thinking that certain rich and meaningful human relationships are valuable for their own sake should also lead us to think that certain cattle relationships are valuable for their own sake. And just as death is bad for us when it destroys our valuable relationships, so death is bad for cattle when it destroys their valuable relationships. This argument is important because it pinpoints something that is bad about death for cattle that is overlooked by popular accounts of the badness of death for non-human animals that focus exclusively on the impact of death on lifetime well-being levels. Thus, the argument reveals an overlooked moral cost of some of our farming practices.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

Notes

  1. Some representative works in this vein include Nussbaum’s argument that social animals are entitled to, among other things, opportunities to form social relationships [3, pp. 325–407]; Monsó’s, Benz‑Schwarzburg’s and Bremhorst’s discussion of the moral capabilities of animals [4]; Delon’s examination of the ways in which captivity undermines the physical and social conditions constitutive of a good and meaningful life [5]; and Fitzpatrick’s and Andrews’s exploration of the significance of culture for animal well-being, both in and outside of captivity [6].

  2. I am here and elsewhere in this section indebted to Bennett Helm [7].

  3. Ideas of this kind can be found in Aristotle [8]. Contemporary writers who have discussed the benefits of friendship on self-understanding or self-esteem include John Cooper [9] and David Annis [10].

  4. This is another idea associated with Aristotle [8], discussed by Cooper [9].

  5. See Aristotle [8] and Shoeman [11]

  6. See Rorty [12] and Cocking and Kennett [13]. All the valuable aspects of relationships mentioned here are related, as these authors note.

  7. See Lem [14], especially pp. 154 ff.

  8. Here and elsewhere in this paper I implicitly draw upon something resembling an Aristotelian value theory, according to which what is valuable for a creature is at least partly determined by its functional organization or characteristic form of life. I have tried to avoid explicitly invoking the details of any particular value theory in order to make my argument as intuitive and ecumenical as possible, but it should be noted that much of what I say about value is inspired by the work of Christine Korsgaard. For discussion of the distinction I draw between intrinsic/extrinsic value on the one hand and final/instrumental value on the other, see Korsgaard [15]. For a schematic discussion of the way in which a creature’s functional organization determines what is valuable for it, see Korsgaard [16], [17].

  9. I owe this example to Dan Korman.

  10. It also shows that something that is for us valuable for its own sake may only have extrinsic value.

  11. Death also involves the destruction of the dier, and this raises an ancient philosophical puzzle about how anything can be bad for someone who does not exist (see [18]). I do not have the space to wade into this problem except to say that I think it is dissolved once we accept the correct metaphysical view of time, see Silverstein [19].

  12. For intriguing discussion of this issue, see Rorty [12], especially pp. 78–79.

  13. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me to address this objection.

  14. The preemption problem has been much discussed, in connection with both death and harm more generally (for representative examples of the former, see McMahan [22, pp. 42–49], Feldman [23, pp. 224–225], McMahan [24, pp. 12–127]; of the latter, see Feinberg [25, pp. 150–153]; Hanser [26, pp. 434–437]). Note that the preemption problem is sometimes called the ‘overdetermination problem.’

  15. The Addie example is also an example of preemption. I suspect that it fails to generate intuitions against the comparativism objection (if indeed it does) because Addie’s death is bad for many reasons unrelated to Addie’s career, whereas the preemption cases that tend to generate the strongest intuitions against the comparativism objection are cases where the comparativism condition forces us to say that the preempting event is not bad at all when intuitively it is.

  16. Note that I do not reject the idea that there is a sense in which death is bad for the dier because death deprives the dier of their relationships. After all, a dier is deprived of their relationships by virtue of the fact that those relationships are destroyed by death. Rather, I reject the more specific idea that this destruction (which constitutes (or at least results in) a deprivation) is not bad when it is inevitable, because I think the destruction (which constitutes (or at least results in) a deprivation) is bad in itself.

  17. Multiple discrete, closed herds will not form within a population of cattle if that population is not large enough or if there is not enough space. Many feral cattle populations studied are small and only support a single herd.

  18. It should be noted that the importance of amicable relationships varies across different cattle populations and contexts; see [39 p. 214]. Sometimes dominance-submission relationships are hard to distinguish from amicable relationships. This sort of ambiguity is familiar to human beings.

  19. Martha Nussbaum has advanced a similar argument for the conclusion that painless death can be bad for animals like cattle, but her argument focuses on the “termination of many and varied functioning,” including social functioning, rather than the destruction of valuable relationships per se [3 pp. 384–386].

  20. Those who reject this response and insist on a more restrictive theory of well-being (or value) than I am inclined to endorse cannot accept my argument as it stands. However, even someone with a rather restrictive value theory, such as hedonism or a desire theory (see [45]), can acknowledge the ethical relevance of the fact that cattle can form rich relationships with conspecifics since these relationships are very likely going to be associated with goods that are recognized from the perspective of these more restrictive theories. And since death curtails such goods, death can be bad for cattle. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing me to make this point.

  21. A categorical desire is a desire whose content is not conditioned on one’s being alive and thus can give one a reason to go on living (or to kill oneself). These contrast with desires whose content is conditioned on one’s continued existence and thus cannot give one reason to go on living (or to kill oneself). For example, my desire to visit space is a categorical desire whereas my desire to get my cavity filled is a conditional desire. If I were to discover that I will die tomorrow, the former desire would be a source of disappointment. But the latter desire would not, since the content of the desire is implicitly predicated upon a condition I would know is no longer satisfied, something like: I get my cavity filled (assuming that I will continue to live for a while). See Williams [51].

  22. I have a more general worry about attributing any non-categorical desires to cattle given Cigman’s and Belshaw’s assumptions. As I understand it, if a desire is not categorical, then by definition its content is conditioned on one’s continued existence, at least implicitly. Note that the difference between categorical and non-categorical desires must be a matter of conditional content, since the existence of all desires is trivially conditioned on the desirer’s continued existence. Yet it seems inconsistent to both affirm that cattle have desires with content containing conditionals concerning their continued life and deny that cattle understand themselves as creatures who persist through time. I am inclined to conclude that the categorical/non-categorical distinction is not as useful as it appears in this context. Then again, it may be that my understanding of this distinction is unorthodox or confused.

  23. A related issue which many ethicists have taken to be important is whether animals such as cattle form valuable relationships with humans in captivity. Many ethicists argue that it is possible for humans and animals like cattle to become friends and that these friendships, or the possibility of these friendships, generate special reasons against eating, mistreating, objectifying, or killing some animals (proponents of views in this vicinity include [54], [55], [56], [57], [58]; cf. Torres [59], who argues that Aristotle is committed to this view, and Carter and Charles [60], who tackle the topic from a sociological perspective). Suffice to say that if captive cattle form friendships with humans (and this may not happen very often, see Causey [61]), then the fact that death destroys these friendships is probably another thing that makes death bad for cattle.

  24. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out.

  25. Cf. Kolbe [63], who argues that because of how the meat and dairy industries are structured, consuming dairy is in some ways ethically worse than consuming meat.

  26. My thinking in this paragraph and elsewhere has been heavily influenced by Draper [67]. Draper argues that “a complete account of the evils in death must be pluralistic,” p. 396. Cf. Scheffler [20 pp. 21–22].

References

  1. Sanders, Bas. 2008. Global Cow Slaughter Statistics and Charts. Faunalytics. https://faunalytics.org/global-cow-slaughter-statistics-and-charts/. Accessed 16 Feb 2021.

  2. Bradley, Ben. 2016. Is Death Bad for a Cow? In The Ethics of Killing Animals, ed. Tatjana Višak and Robert Garner, 51–64. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199396078.003.0004.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  3. Nussbaum, Martha. 2006. Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. https://doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1c7zftw.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  4. Monsó, Susana, Judith Benz-Schwarzburg, and Annika Bremhorst. 2018. Animal Morality: What It Means and Why It Matters. The Journal of Ethics 22: 283–310. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10892-018-9275-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Delon, Nicolas. 2018. Animal Agency, Captivity, and Meaning. The Harvard Review of Philosophy. 25: 127–146. https://doi.org/10.5840/harvardreview201892519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Fitzpatrick, Simon, and Kristin Andrews. 2022. Animal Culture and Animal Welfare. Philosophy of Science. 88 (5): 1104–1113. https://doi.org/10.1017/psa.2022.34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Helm, Bennett. 2021. Friendship. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/friendship/. Accessed 2 March, 2021.

  8. Aristotle. 2014. Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by C. D. C. Reeve. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

  9. Cooper, John. 1977. Friendship and the Good in Aristotle. The Philosophical Review. 86 (3): 290–315. https://doi.org/10.2307/2183784.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Annis, David. 1987. The Meaning, Value and Duties of Friendship. American Philosophical Quarterly. 24 (4): 349–356.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Schoeman, Ferdinand. 1985. Aristotle on the good of friendship. Australasian Journal of Philosophy. 69 (3): 269–282. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048408512341881.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Rorty, Amelie Oksenberg. 1986. The Historicity of Psychological Attitudes: Love Is Not Love Which Alters Not When It Alteration Finds. Midwest Studies in Philosophy. 10: 399–412. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4975.1987.tb00548.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Cocking, Dean, and Jeanette Kennett. 1998. Friendship and the Self. Ethics 108 (3): 502–527. https://doi.org/10.1086/233824.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Lem, Stanisław. 2014. Solaris. Translated by Bill Johnston. Krakow: Pro Auctore Wojciech Zemek.

  15. Korsgaard, Christine M. 1983. Two Distinctions in Goodness. The Philosophical Review. 92 (2): 169–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Korsgaard, Christine M. 2014. On Having a Good. Philosophy 89 (3): 405–429. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819114000102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Korsgaard, Christine M. 2018. Fellow Creatures: Our Obligations to the Other Animals. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198753858.001.0001.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  18. Epicurus. Letter to Menoeceus. Translated by Robert Drew Hicks. The Internet Classics Archive. http://classics.mit.edu/Epicurus/menoec.html. Accessed April 20, 2022.

  19. Silverstein, Harry S. 1980. The Evil of Death. The Journal of Philosophy. 77 (7): 401–424. https://doi.org/10.2307/2025537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Scheffler, Samuel. 2016. Death and the Afterlife. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199982509.001.0001.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  21. Shiffrin, Seana Valentine. 2016. Preserving the valued or preserving valuing? In Death and the Afterlife, ed. Niko Kolodny, 143–158. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199982509.003.0007.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  22. McMahan, Jeff. 1988. Death and the Value of Life. Ethics 99 (1): 32–61. https://doi.org/10.1086/293034.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Feldman, Fred. 1991. Some Puzzles about the evil of death. The Philosophical Review. 100 (2): 205–227. https://doi.org/10.2307/2185300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. McMahan, Jeff. 2002. The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/0195079981.001.0001.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  25. Feinberg, Joel. 1986. Wrongful Life and the Counterfactual Element in Harming. Social Philosophy & Policy. 4 (1): 145–178. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0265052500000467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. Hanser, Matthew. 2008. The Metaphysics of Harm. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 77 (2): 421–450. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2008.00197.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Wilson, Don E., and DeeAnn M. Reeder. 1993. Mammals Species of the World: A Taxonomic and Geographic Reference, 2nd ed. Washington: Smithsonian Institution Press.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Bouissou, Marie-France., Alain Boissy, Pierre Le Neindre, and Isabelle Veissier. 2001. The Social Behaviour of Cattle. In Social Behaviour in Farm Animals, ed. L.J. Keeling and H.W. Gonyou, 113–145. Wallingford: CABI Publishing. https://doi.org/10.1079/9780851993973.0113.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  29. Phillips, Clive J. C. 2002. Cattle Behaviour and Welfare. Oxford: Blackwell. https://doi.org/10.1002/9780470752418.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  30. Sato, S., S. Sako, and A. Maeda. 1991. Social licking patterns in cattle (Bos taurus): influence of environmental and social factors. Applied Animal Behaviour Science. 32 (1): 3–12. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0168-1591(05)80158-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Watts, Jon M., and Joseph M. Stookey. 2000. Vocal behaviour in cattle: the animal’s commentary on its biological processes and welfare. Applied Animal Behaviour Science. 67: 15–33. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0168-1591(99)00108-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Green, A.C., I.N. Johnston, and C.E.F. Clark. 2018. Invited review: The evolution of cattle bioacoustics and application for advanced dairy systems. Animal 12 (6): 1250–1259. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1751731117002646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Lazo, Alfonso. 1992. Facteurs déterminants du comportement grégaire de bovins retournés à l’état sauvage. Revue d’Ecologie. 47 (1): 51–66.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Lazo, Alfonso. 1994. Social segregation and the maintenance of social stability in a feral cattle population. Animal Behaviour. 48 (5): 1133–1141. https://doi.org/10.1006/anbe.1994.1346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Geven, Milou and Ellen de Graaf. 2014. A herd of Scottish Highland cattle (Bos taurus) in a semi-wild setting representing naturalness in behaviour: Extending knowledge beyond production systems. Van Hall Larenstein.

  36. Costa, J.H.C., M.A.G. von Keyserlingk, and D.M. Weary. 2016. Invited review: Effects of group housing of dairy calves on behavior, cognition, performance, and health. Journal of Dairy Science. 99 (4): 2453–2467. https://doi.org/10.3168/jds.2015-10144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Clutton-Brock, T.H., P.J. Greenwood, and R.P. Powell. 1976. Ranks and Relationships in Highland Ponies and Highland Cows. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie. 41 (2): 202–216. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1439-0310.1976.tb00477.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Reinhardt, V., and A. Reinhardt. 1975. Dynamics of Social Hierarchy in a Dairy Herd. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie. 38 (3): 315–323. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1439-0310.1975.tb02007.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Hall, Stephen J. G. 1986. Chillingham Cattle: Dominance and Affinities and Access to Supplementary Food. Ethology 71 (3): 201–215. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1439-0310.1986.tb00584.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  40. Reinhardt, Catherine, Annie Reinhardt, and Viktor Reinhardt. 1986. Social behaviour and reproductive performance in semi-wild Scottish Highland cattle. Applied Animal Behaviour Science. 15 (2): 125–136. https://doi.org/10.1016/0168-1591(86)90058-4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Reinhardt, Viktor, and Annie Reinhardt. 1981. Cohesive Relationships in a Cattle Herd (Bos indicus). Behaviour 77 (3): 121–150. https://doi.org/10.1163/156853981X00194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. Veissier, Isabelle, D. Lamy, and P. Le Neindre. 1990. Social behaviour in domestic beef cattle when yearling calves are left with the cows for the next calving. Applied Animal Behaviour Science. 27 (3): 193–200. https://doi.org/10.1016/0168-1591(90)90056-J.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Gutmann, Anke Kristina, Marek Spinka, and Christoph Winckler. 2015. Long-term familiarity creates preferred social partners in dairy cows. Applied Animal Behaviour Science. 169: 1–8. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.applanim.2015.05.007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  44. Vitale, A.F., M. Tenucci, M. Papini, and S. Lovari. 1986. Social behaviour of the calves of semi-wild Maremma cattle, Bos primigenius taurus. Applied Animal Behaviour Science. 16 (3): 217–231. https://doi.org/10.1016/0168-1591(86)90115-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Crisp, Roger. 2021. Well-Being. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/well-being/. Accessed 2 March, 2022.

  46. Kasperbauer, T.J., and Peter Sandøe. 2016. Killing as a Welfare Issue. In The Ethics of Killing Animals, ed. Tatjana Višak and Robert Garner, 17–31. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199396078.003.0002.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  47. Broom, Donald M. 2011. A History of Animal Welfare Science. Acta Biotheoretica. 59: 121–137. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-011-9123-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  48. Singer, Peter. 1975. Animal Liberation. New York: HarperCollins Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Cigman, Ruth. 1981. Death, Misfortune and Species Inequality. Philosophy & Public Affairs. 10 (1): 47–64.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Belshaw, Christopher. 2016. Death, Pain, and Animal Life. In The Ethics of Killing Animals, ed. Tatjana Višak and Robert Garner, 32–50. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199396078.003.0003.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  51. Williams, Bernard. 1973. The Makropulos Case: Reflections on the Tedium of Immortality. In Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers 1956-1972, 82-100. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511621253.008

  52. Bower, Matt, and Bob Fischer. 2018. Categorical Desires and the Badness of Animal Death. Journal of Value Inquiry. 52: 97–111. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-017-9604-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  53. McMahan, Jeff. 2016. The Comparative Badness for Animals of Suffering and Death. In The Ethics of Killing Animals, ed. Tatjana Višak and Robert Garner, 65–85. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199396078.003.0005.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  54. Jordan, Jeff. 2001. Why Friends Shouldn’t Let Friends Be Eaten: An Argument for Vegetarianism. Social Theory and Practice. 27 (2): 309–322. https://doi.org/10.5840/soctheorpract200127214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Townley, Cynthia. 2011. Animals as Friends. Between the Species. 13 (10): 45–59. https://doi.org/10.15368/bts.2010v13n10.3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Frööding, Barbro, and Martin Peterson. 2011. Animal Ethics Based on Friendship. Journal of Animal Ethics. 1 (1): 58–69. https://doi.org/10.5406/janimalethics.1.1.0058.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Rowlands, Mark. 2011. Friendship and Animals: A Reply to Frööding and Peterson. Journal of Animal Ethics. 1 (1): 70–79. https://doi.org/10.5406/janimalethics.1.1.0070.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Gheaus, Anca. 2012. The Role of Love in Animal Ethics. Hypatia 27 (3): 583–600. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1527-2001.2012.01284.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Torres, Jorge. 2022. Animal Ethics Based on Friendship: An Aristotelian Perspective. Journal of Animal Ethics. 12 (1): 76–88. https://doi.org/10.5406/21601267.12.1.08.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Carter, Bob, and Nickie Charles. 2013. Animals, Agency and Resistance. Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour. 43 (3): 322–340. https://doi.org/10.1111/jtsb.12019.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Causey, Mark. 2019. Animal Ethics Based on Friendship: A Reply. Journal of Animal Ethics. 9 (1): 1–5. https://doi.org/10.5406/janimalethics.9.1.0001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  62. Damron, W. Stephen. 2013. Introduction to Animal Science: Global, Biological, Social, and Industry Perspectives, 5th ed. New York: Pearson.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Kolbe, Karin. 2018. Why Milk Consumption is the Bigger Problem: Ethical Implications and Deaths per Calorie Created of Milk Compared to Meat Production. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. 31: 467–481. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-018-9740-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  64. DeGrazia, David. 2016. Sentient Nonpersons and the Disvalue of Death. Bioethics 30 (7): 511–519. https://doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  65. Bradley, Ben. 2009. Well-Being and Death. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199557967.001.1.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  66. Nagel, Thomas. 1970. Death. Noûs 4 (1): 73–80. https://doi.org/10.2307/2214297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  67. Draper, K. 1999. Disappointment, sadness, and death. The Philosophical Review. 108 (3): 387–414. https://doi.org/10.2307/2998466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. Solis, Coleman. 2021. How Much Does Slaughter Harm Humanely Raised Animals? Journal of Applied Philosophy. 38 (2): 258–272. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The idea for this paper originated out of several conversations I had with Julie Huzzey, an animal scientist at Cal Poly, SLO, who generously taught me about cattle, gave me a tour of Cal Poly’s dairy farm, and introduced me to some lovely cows and calves. I thank her for her time and attention. Thanks are also due to my intimates (especially Catelynn Kenner) who over the last few years repeatedly and generously indulged my screeds about cattle. Finally, thanks to three anonymous reviewers who provided me with incisive comments, which greatly strengthened the paper.

Statements and Declarations

The author has no relevant financial or non-financial interests to disclose.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Story.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

The original online version of this article was revised: In the original publication of the article, formatting of numbered citations were corrected throughout the article.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Story, D. The Badness of Death for Sociable Cattle. J Value Inquiry (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-023-09945-6

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-023-09945-6

Keywords

Navigation