Skip to main content
Log in

What Does a Phenomenological Theory of Social Objects Mean?

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

What are social objects and what makes them different from other realms of scientifically studied reality? How can sociology theoretically account for the relationship between objects of social reality such as norms and social structures, and their existence as objects of experience for living human actors? Contemporary sociology is characterized by a fundamental dissensus with regard to this question. Ironically, this is the very problem Alfred Schutz tackled in his phenomenological critique of Max Weber’s sociological theory. As Schutz demonstrated nearly a century ago, phenomenology’s egological method is indispensable to a non-reductionist theory of intersubjectivity, namely, one that does full justice to embodied conscious life while demonstrating the relative independence of the intersubjective (social) sphere. In the process, Schutz’s mundane phenomenology results not only in a thorough rejection of all kinds of philosophical solipsism but also warns of the dangers, one that Husserl himself succumbed to, of granting collective structures transcendental status. Through a critical reading of Schutz’s early theory in the Phenomenology of the Social World, alongside key texts by Husserl, this paper shows the continued relevance of Schutz’s phenomenological theory of intersubjectivity to serve both as ontological grounding of “the social” and a method for investigating and describing concrete social objects in their transformation into theoretico-analytical objects amenable to empirical observation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I speak here of sociology for the sake of convention and convenience, but the remarks apply to social science more generally.

  2. The capitalized “Ego” here refers, as in Schutz, to the ego of Husserl’s egology, rather than any psychological meaning of the term.

  3. Section 3 offers a more sustained discussion of Husserl’s concept of intentionality.

  4. Schutz refers to this theoretical formulation as the “general thesis of the alter ego” (1967[1932]: 97–102).

  5. As Scheler writes, “only a part of our total mental and cognitive existence is capable of becoming an object for us, and only a very small proportion of that part can itself be observed and repeated” (2008: 223). While Scheler’s criticism was directed against experimental psychology, it is consistent with Schutz’s view of the limits of introspection and the possibility of fully explicating inner lived experience. Such a view speaks against criticisms which suggest that phenomenology rests on the Cartesian belief of the full transparency of one’s subjective mental life to oneself.

  6. Because existence is personal, that does not mean that it is therefore “private” in the traditional Western metaphysical sense of Descartes and Locke, which constitute the tradition behind the psychologism which Husserl turns against. For a classic statement on the personal self in philosophy and its ethical implications, see Taylor (1989). Taylor however draws from the Heideggerian rather than Husserlian phenomenological tradition in his study. In sociology, Smith (2010) has more recently argued for the need for a “thick notion of persons,” as has Archer through her notion of the “internal conversation” (2012). Ethically and methodologically, social phenomenology has much to contribute to the dialogue between realist social science and philosophical and moral understandings of the person.

  7. One might notice parallels here with the Freudian unconscious. Though there are similarities between the phenomenological and the Freudian theory of the structure of consciousness, phenomenologists do not necessarily subscribe to the Freudian interpretation of the constitution of the unconscious, especially the latter’s determinative function in conscious life. Moreover, in the psychoanalytic understanding, the unconscious can, in principle, in the course of psychoanalytic treatment, be brought into consciousness, since it reflects sedimented, but at one time sensibly experienced moments of the subject’s past psychic life (as in Freud’s Oedipal drama). By contrast, for many phenomenologists, moments of the pre-phenomenal flux are forever foreclosed to the possibility of proper meaning and thus do not perform the same function as the Freudian unconscious (thus only finding “poetic” expression in modern artistic forms).

  8. This highlights problems with critiques (e.g., Pendergrast 1986) that Schutz followed Austrian economics’ recipe of “methodological individualism”. Schutz’s method is instead better described as “methodological egologism”.

  9. In the same passage, Schutz adds, “Of course, within this total coherence of experience, contradictory experiences can occur without impairing the over-all unity”. In other discussions Schutz describes the possibility of an experience referencing incongruent schemes. An experience may also “explode” a scheme when its anticipations become unfulfilled.

References

  • Adorno, T. W. (1940). Husserl and the problem of idealism. Journal of Philosophy, 37(1), 5–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, T. W. (2019). Ontology and dialectics. Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archer, M. S. (2003). Structure, agency, and the internal conversation. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Archer, M. S. (2012). The reflexive imperative in late modernity. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Benzecry, C. E., & Winchester, D. (2017). Varieties of microsociology. In C. E. Benzecry, M. Krause, & I. A. Reed (Eds.), Social Theory now (pp. 42–74). University of Chicago Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, P. L., & Luckmann, T. (1966). The social construction of reality. Anchor Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (1979). The possibility of naturalism. Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blumer, H. (1966). Sociological implications of the thought of George Herbert Mead. American Journal of Sociology, 71(1), 535–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P. (1990). The logic of practice. Stanford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bourdieu, P., & Wacquant, L. (1992). An invitation to reflexive sociology. University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donati, P. (2011). Relational sociology: a new paradigm for the social sciences. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. (1982). The rules of sociological method. Free Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1992). Postmetaphysical thinking: philosophical essays. Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., & Gillett, G. (1994). The discursive mind. Sage Publications.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian meditations: an introduction to phenomenology. Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology. Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001). Analyses concerning passive and active synthesis: Lectures on transcendental logic. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (2001[1970]) Logical Investigations (Vol. 2). Routledge.

  • Ihde, D. (1993). Postphenomenology: Essays in the Postmodern Context. Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (2016). Husserl’s missing technologies. Fordham University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (2021). Material hermeneutics: Reversing the linguistic turn. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Knoblauch, H. (2019). The communicative construction of reality. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knorr Cetina, K. (1997). Sociality with objects: Social relations in postsocial knowledge societies. Theory, Culture & Society, 14(4), 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kockelmans, J. J. (1994). Edmund Husserl’s phenomenology. Purdue University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krais, B. (1991). ‘Meanwhile, I have come to know all the diseases of sociological understanding’: An Interview with Pierre Bourdieu. In P. Bourdieu, J.-C. Chamboredon, & J.-C. Passeron (Eds.), The craft of sociology: Epistemological preliminaries (pp. 247–260). Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1993). We have never been modern. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1996). On interobjectivity. Mind, Culture, and Activity, 3(4), 228–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (2005). Reassembling the social: An introduction to Actor-Network Theory. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lizardo, O. (2014). Beyond the Comtean Schema: The sociology of culture and cognition versus cognitive social science. Sociological Forum, 29(4), 983–989.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luckmann, T. (1978). Philosophy, social sciences and everyday life. In T. Luckmann (Ed.), Phenomenology and sociology (pp. 217–256). Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luckmann, T. (1983) Remarks on personal identity: Inner, social and historical time. In: Jacobson-Widding A (ed) Identity: Personal and socio-cultural. Almqvist & Wiksell International.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of perception. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pula, B. (2021) Does phenomenology (Still) matter? Three phenomenological traditions and sociological theory. International Journal of Politics, Culture and Society Pre-publication online: 1–21.

  • Russell, M. (2006). Husserl: A guide for the perplexed. Continuum International Publishing Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. (2008). The nature of sympathy. Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz, A. (1967[1932]) The phenomenology of the social world. Heinemann Educational Books.

  • Schutz, A. (1975a). Phenomenology and the foundations of the social sciences. In I. Schutz (Ed.), Collected papers III (pp. 40–50). Martinus Nijhoff.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schutz, A. (1975b). The problem of transcendental intersubjectivity in Husserl. In I. Schutz (Ed.), Collected papers III (pp. 51–84). Martinus Nijhoff.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, C. (2010). What is a person? Rethinking humanity, social life, and the moral good from the person up. University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1989). Sources of the self: The making of modern identity. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, S. (2007). Social theory as a cognitive neuroscience. European Journal of Social Theory, 10(3), 357–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaisey, S. (2009). Motivation and justification: A dual-process model of culture in action. American Journal of Sociology, 114(6), 1675–1715.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, H. R. (1973). The scope of phenomenological sociology: Considerations and suggestions. In G. Psathas (Ed.), Phenomenological sociology: Issues and applications (pp. 61–90). John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, A. (1998). On constitution and causation in international relations. Review of International Studies, 24(5), 101–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, H. (1992). Identity and control: A structural theory of social action. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, T. P. (1970). Normative and interpretive paradigms in sociology. In J. D. Douglas (Ed.), Understanding everyday life: Toward the reconstruction of sociological knowledge (pp. 57–79). Aldine Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2017). Husserl’s legacy: Phenomenology, metaphysics, and transcendental philosophy. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prendergast, C. (1986) Alfred Schutz and the Austrian School of Economics. American Journal of Sociology 92(1): 1-26.

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank Mathieu Desan and the participants of the Sociological Theory panel at the 2021 ASA (virtual) Annual Conference for their valuable feedback on the original draft of this paper. The author would also like to thank the journal’s two anonymous reviewers for critical suggestions that have greatly improved the quality of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Besnik Pula.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Pula, B. What Does a Phenomenological Theory of Social Objects Mean?. Hum Stud 45, 509–528 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-022-09636-4

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-022-09636-4

Keywords

Navigation