Skip to main content
Log in

Disability: An Embodied Reality (or Space) of Dasein

  • Theoretical / Philosophical Paper
  • Published:
Human Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The ‘body’ has remained the pivotal and essential mechanism for analysis within disability scholarship. Yet while historically conceptualized as an individual’s fundamental feature, the ‘disabled identity’ has been more recently explained as a function of ‘normalcy’ through social, cultural political, and legal discriminations against difference and deviancy. Disability studies’ established tradition of consultation with philosophical endeavour remains apparently unwilling to exploit or utilize Martin Heidegger’s understanding of ‘Being’ and interpretation of Dasein as a possible framework for unravelling the complexities of contemporary discrimination and oppression of those others. This paper in tracing Heidegger’s explanation of humankind, inspired by arguments proposed by Cerbone (Int J Philos Stud 2:209–230, 2000) and in consultation with Levin (The body: classic and contemporary readings, Blackwell, Malden, 1999), Aho (2009), Malpas (Heidegger’s topology: being place, world, MIT Press, Cambridge, 2008), and Rae (Hum Stud 33:23–39, 2010) among others, will interpret the ‘embodied’ reality of ‘Being,’ of being-disabled-in-the-world as primarily involved within the practical context and structured according to impersonal, normative social norms, rather than detached, theoretical contemplation or observance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Such Cartesian dualisms deeply embedded in both academic disciplines and everyday thinking crucially sustain oppression and discrimination of disabled people; see Corker and Shakespeare (2004), Snyder et al. (2002), Tremain (2005).

  2. Concentrating on the function, production, and influence of normalcy, abnormality, difference, and oppression.

  3. Campbell (personal communication 20 June 2010).

  4. Examples of other recent approaches to phenomenology and embodied notions of the body include: Hickey-Moody (2009), Scully (2009), Shildrick (2009, 2002), Shildrick and Mykitiuk (2005).

  5. Predominately through discussions in Heidegger (1962).

  6. Heidegger questioning the logic of binary oppositions affords a view of instigating a new non-binary logic (see Rae 2010: 30).

  7. Through the writings of Mairs (1996) and Longmore (2003).

  8. The negative, common failing of the ‘public self,’ of the anybody, in everyday activity. This mode of ‘Being’ allows for the ‘levelling’ of society as the desire for anonymity, need for uniformity, and imposition of conformity provides for only possibility of existence.

  9. While as Aho (2009) argues there is a linking or contact between the writings of Heidegger and Merleau Ponty in relation to space (Leiben) as both look beyond the traditional understanding of ‘container’ and the ‘body’ as a corporeal thing disengaged from its world (Körper), Ponty’s phenomenology remains connected to Cartesian subjectivity and thus less appropriate for the intent of this paper and direction of the new horizon of Disability Studies. As Turner (1984: 54) maintains, “the phenomenology … offered by Merleau-Ponty is an individualist account of embodiment from the point of view of the subject; it is consequently an account largely devoid of historical and sociological content”. Focussed on perceptual connection connecting the ‘now’ of bodily things and the world it privileges the present… “It is always in the present that we are created” (Merleau-Ponty 1962: 427). Yet for Heidegger, all perception is already pre-shaped in the past or thrownness (facticity) and the future possibilities (Möglichkeit). Other areas of departure from Heidegger include the fact that Merleau-Ponty:

    1. Is focussed on the pre-reflective bond between the body and world, described as being-towards-the world (perceptually bound to worldly objects) rather than Being-in-the-world. Dasein is the world … as a shared referential … is already there prior to bodily perception.

    2. Is an investigation into the conditions of possibility of meaning itself, explaining the how and why perceptions of the body-subject are intelligible or make sense. Indeed Ponty remains connected to a concept of subjectivity and questions whether meaning is constituted ‘in oneself’. For Heidegger there is no subject or “I” for Dasein is always Being-with-others.

    3. Argues the ‘primacy’ of perception in any meaningful experience thus cultural reality is a function of natural perception and contact with the world and history. Yet for Heidegger the clearing of intelligence is always existing and provides for the ‘hearing’ of worldly realities … perception remains determined by the ‘primacy’ of Dasein (Aho 2009).

  10. Something ready-to-hand.

  11. Longmore: reference to Ten Broek and Matson (1966: 809–840).

  12. In my Doctoral Dissertation, The Consequence of Resistance. Interrogating Heidegger and Butler on the conundrums of ableism, I have examined and scrutinized specific legal judgements relating to disabled individuals using Heidegger’s concepts of disclosive freedom and Language to highlight the limits of formal equality and legal rhetoric respectively.

  13. The demand for certain body shapes, the passport to success through exercise, diet, and other indignities regulated through memberships to health clubs, spas, and aerobics once considered simply a hobby of the wealthy has become the obsession of the wider abled-bodied. The mass media’s relentless fascination on self-improvement ‘gadgets,’ slogans, the promotion of cosmetic surgery and the emulation of youth have provided distortion and ritual surrounding ‘bodily perfection’.

  14. Rae (2010: 24) comments, “to correct what Heidegger perceives as the fundamental misunderstanding of his thought [the later work turned from] providing an existential analytic of the human being to discern Being [… a discussion of the ek-sistence] of Being itself” (see Heidegger 1977a).

  15. Self-contained.

  16. Cavalier (1998) defines fallenness as being concerned with the present or everyday social commonality and thrownness as embodying all elements of existence, given, not chosen, revealed in moods, notions of the body, one’s finitude, past, present, and general situations. See Tuttle (2005) for further development of these terms.

  17. For an extended discussion on the inadequacies of ‘discourse on the body’ see Levin (1999).

  18. For Heidegger existence (its essence) is not the traditional oppositional position to essence. The definition of the human being is not representative of action but the privileging of Being; it does not exist by what it does but in relation to being that it, and it alone amongst beings, is able to disclose being (Rae 2010: 24).

  19. See Diprose (2003) for discussion on Nancy re-embodiment.

  20. See Heidegger (2001: 117) for similar commentary on Heidegger’s frustration in the relationship between the body and philosophy.

  21. “The philosophic-theoretical corpus of bodies is still supported by the spine of mimesis, of representation and of the sign” (Nancy 1994: 192).

  22. See Heidegger (1977b) for discussion on the chalice, the ‘chaliseness’ (causa formalis) of the chalice.

  23. “The world … a shared world with others[suggests that Dasein] far from being a solipsistic ego requiring an epistemological proof of existence of others … finds itself already always among others” (Caputo 1999: 226).

  24. Indeed “others are not those who are other than the I but those among whom the I is also, by whom Dasein is in fact dominated like an anonymous ‘They’ (das Man) and from which it must learn to differentiate itself into an authentic self” (Caputo 1999: 26).

  25. Between neutrality and its factical concretion.

  26. See Cerbone (2000: 216) for an extended discussion.

  27. This paper will not detail the distinction between the authentic individuated ‘I’ and inauthentic ‘Anyone’.

  28. “The entire protest and especially the burning of the book gave tangible form to the pain they felt … they too felt thwarted by a government that stymies their efforts to work and make a life. They too felt dehumanized by a society that devalues them” (Longmore 2003: 253).

  29. Object, thing, or substance; present-at-hand.

  30. Categories as mentioned in introduction: present-at-hand, ready-to-hand, and organisms dwelling within the world.

  31. See Askay (1999: 32) for useful discussion on a series of Heidegger’s interconnected assertions.

  32. As Dasein itself (for example).

  33. Heidegger fundamentally rejected Cartesian doctrines and idioms.

  34. For example, the raising of arms or a hand as a gesture of waving, calling, or retrieving.

  35. “The kind of concern which manipulates things and puts them to use … has its own kind of knowledge” (Heidegger 1962: 67).

  36. Cerbone (2000: 218) offered the following example: “[a]n arm is something with which I wave to a friend toward the act of extending a greeting in order to in fact greet the friend for the sake of being a friendly person”.

  37. For extended discussion and analysis of the embodied nature of ‘Space’ see Malpas (2008).

  38. Longmore (2003: 240) in referencing Rasmussen (1991) quotes: “[t]he problems in the … welfare system stem not only from policy ideology that distorts the realities of disability, but … the tenacious exertions of an entrenched and bureaucratic institution to safeguard its prerogatives and powers, no matter what the cost in the lives of ordinary people with disabilities”.

  39. See Greaney (2007) for Heidegger’s discussion of a disabled potter for further explanation and clarification of potentiality and capacity.

  40. Hayles (1999) asserts: “Heidegger’s critique of metaphysical humanism laid the foundation for anti-humanism of structuralist, post-structuralit[,] and deconstructionist thought and more recent debates on posthuman”. See also Hefner (2009).

References

  • Abberley, P. (1998). Work, utopia and impairment. In L. Barton (Ed.), Disability and society: Emerging issues and insights (pp. 61–82). Harlow: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Agamben, G. (1998). Homo Sacer: Sovereign power and bare life (D. Heller-Roazen, Trans.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Aho, K. (2009). Heidegger’s neglect of the body. Ithaca: State University of New York.

  • Arisaka, Y. (1995). On Heidegger’s theory of space: A critique of Dreyfus. Inquiry, 38(4), 445–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arisaka, Y. (1996). Spatiality, temporality and the problem of foundation in ‘Being and Time’. Philosophy Today, 40, 36–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Askay, R. (1999). Heidegger, the body and the French philosophers. Continental Philosophy Review, 32, 29–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baiasu, R. (2007). Being and time and the problem of space. Research in Phenomenology, 379, 324–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brisenden, S. (1998). Independent living and the medical model of disability. In T. Shakespeare (Ed.), The disability reader: Social science perspective (pp. 20–27). London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (1993). Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of sex. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, F. K. (2005). Legislating disability: Negative ontologies and the government of legal identities. In S. Tremain (Ed.), Foucault and the government of disability (pp. 108–130). Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, F. K. (2009). Contours of ableism: The Production of disability and abledness. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Caputo, J. (1999). Heidegger. In S. Critchley & W. Schroeder (Eds.), A companion to continental philosophy (pp. 223–236). Massachusetts: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caputo, J. (2001). The absence of Monica: Heidegger Derrida and Augustine’s confessions. In N. Holland & P. Huntington (Eds.), Feminist interpretations of Martin Heidegger (pp. 149–164). University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casey, E. (1997). The fate of place: A philosophical history. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavalier, R. (1998). Lectures on Heidegger’s Being and time. http://caae.phil.cmu.edu/Cavalier/80254/Heidegger/SZHomePage. Accessed March 10, 2009.

  • Cerbone, D. (2000). Heidegger and Dasein’s bodily nature: What is the hidden problematic? International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 2, 209–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chanter, T. (2001). Time death and the feminine: Levinas with Heidegger. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, A., Shim, J., Mamo, L., Fosket, J., & Fishman, J. (2003). Biomedicalization: Technoscientific transformations of health, illness and U.S. biomedicine. American Sociological Review, 6, 161–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corker, M. (1998). Deaf and disabled or deafness disabled. Buckingham: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corker, M., & French, S. (Eds.). (1998). Disability discourse. Buckingham: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corker, M., & Shakespeare, T. (Eds.). (2004). Disability/postmodernity: Embodying disability theory. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crossley, N. (2001). The social body: Habit identity and desire. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Beistegui, M. (2003). Thinking with Heidegger: Displacements. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Beistegui, M. (2005). The new Heidegger. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1998). Discourse on method and meditations on first philosophy (D. Cress, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. (Originally published in 1637/1641).

  • Devlin, R., & Pothier, D. (2006). Toward a critical theory of dis-citizenship. In D. Pothier & R. Devlin (Eds.), Critical disability theory: Essays in philosophy, politics, policy and law (pp. 1–24). Vancouver: UBC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diprose, R. (2003). The hand that writes community in blood. Cultural Studies Review, 9, 44–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (1991). Being-in-the-world: A commentary on Heidegger’s Being and time. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elkholy, S. (2008). Heidegger and a metaphysics of feeling. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franck, D. (1991). Being and the living. In E. Cadava, P. Connor, & J. Nancy (Eds.), Who cares after the subject? London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fried, G. (2000). Heidegger’s polemos: From being to politics. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodley, D. (2011). Disability studies: Interdisciplinary introduction. Los Angeles: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greaney, P. (2007). Ultimately beggar: poverty and power from Baudelaire to Benjamin. Minneapolis: University of Minneapolis Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, E. (1986). What is feminist theory? In C. Paterson & E. Gross (Eds.), Feminist challenges: Social and political theory (pp. 190–204). Boston: Northeastern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haar, M. (1993). The song of the earth: Heidegger and the grounds of the history of being (R. Lilly, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Halyes, N. K. (1999). How we became posthuman: Virtual bodies in cybernetics, literature and Informatics. London: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hancock, P., Hughes, P., Jagger, E., Patterson, K., Russell, R., Tulle-Winton, E., & Tyler, M. (2000). The body, culture and society. Buckingham: Open University Press.

  • Hayman, R. (1998). The smart culture: Society, intelligence and law. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hefner, P. (2009). The animal that aspires to be an angel: The challenge of transhumanism. Dialog: A Journal of Theology, 48(2), 158–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarie, & E. Robinson, Trans.). New York: Harper & Row. (Originally published in 1927).

  • Heidegger, M. (1969). Identity and difference (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Originally published in 1957).

  • Heidegger, M. (1977a). Letter on humanism. In D. Krell (Ed.), Basic writings. New York: Harper & Row. (Originally published in 1947).

  • Heidegger, M. (1977b). The question concerning technology and other essays (W. Lovitt, Trans.) (pp. 1–35). New York; Harper & Row. (Originally published in 1953).

  • Heidegger, M. (1979). Nietzsche, vol. 1. The will to power as art. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1985). The history of the concept of time (T. Kisiel, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. (Originally published in 1979).

  • Heidegger, M. (1990). Kant and the problem with metaphysics (R. Taft, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. (Originally published in 1973).

  • Heidegger, M. (1995). Fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, finitude and solicitude (W. McNeill, & N. Walker, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. (Originally published in 1929).

  • Heidegger, M. (1998). Basic problems of phenomenology (A. Hofstadter, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press. (Originally published in 1975).

  • Heidegger, M. (2001). Zollikon seminars (F. Mayr, & R. Askay, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press. (Originally published in 1959–1969).

  • Heidegger, M. (2008). Building dwelling thinking. In D. Krell (Ed.), Basic writings (pp. 344–363). London: Harper Perennial. (Originally published in 1951).

  • Hickey-Moody, A. (2009). Unimaginable bodies: Intellectual disability, performance and becomings. Rotterdam: Sense.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, B. (2007). Being disabled: Towards a critical ontology for disability studies. Disability & Society, 22(7), 673–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, B. (2009). Wounded/monstrous/abject: A critique of the disabled body in the sociological imaginary. Disability & Society, 24(3), 399–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, B., & Patterson, K. (1997). The social model of disability and the disappearing body: Towards a sociology of impairment. Disability & Society, 12(3), 325–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huntington, P. (1998). Ecstatic subjects, utopia and recognition: Kristeva, Heidegger and Irigarary. Albany: State University Press of New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inahara, M. (2009). The body which is not one: The body, femininity and disability. Body and Society, 15(1), 47–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kenkmann, A. (2005). Circles of solitude and concern. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 13(4), 477–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krell, D. (1992). Daimon life: Heidegger and life philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krell, D. (1997). An Architecture: ecstasies of space, time and the human body. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. (1977). Ecrits: A selection (B. Fink, Trans.). London: Travistock Publications.

  • Leder, D. (1998). A tale of two bodies: The Cartesian corpse and the lived body. In D. Welton (Ed.), Body and the flesh: A philosophical reader (pp. 117–129). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, D. (1999). The ontological dimension of embodiment: Heidegger’s thinking in being. In D. Welton (Ed.), The body: Classic and contemporary readings (pp. 122–149). Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. (1978). Existence and existents (A. Lingis, Trans.). The Hahue: Nijhoff.

  • Linton, S. (1998). Claiming disability: Knowledge and identity. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longmore, P. (2003). Why I burned my book and other essays on Disability. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

  • Mairs, N. (1996). Waist-high in the world: A life among the nondisabled. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malpas, J. (2008). Heidegger’s topology: Being place, world. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans.). New York: Routledge Press.

  • Michalko, R. (2002). The difference disability makes. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Minda, G. (1995). Postmodern legal movements: Law and jurisprudence at century’s end. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, R. (1995). Encounters: The body silent in America. In B. Ingstad & S. Reynolds Whyte (Eds.), Disability and culture (pp. 140–158). London: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nancy, J. L. (1994). Corpus. In W. Hamacher & D. Welbery (Eds.), The birth to presence (B. Holmes, & others, Trans.) (pp. 189–211). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Nancy, J. L. (2000). Being singular plural (R. Richardson, & A. O’Byrne, Trans.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Overboe, J. (2007). Vitalism: Subjectivity exceeding racism sexism and (psychiatric) ableism. Wagadu, 4 (Summer), 23–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Overboe, J. (2009). Affirming an impersonal life: A different register for disability studies. Journal of Literary and Cultural Disability Studies, 3(3), 241–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rae, G. (2010). Re-thinking the human: Heidegger, fundamental ontology and humanism. Human Studies, 33, 23–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rasmussen, K. (1991). Overview of the history of disability policy: An historian’s and insider’s perspective. In Proceedings of the fourth annual meeting, society for disability studies (pp. 28–31), Oakland CA.

  • Sartre, J. P. (1957). Being and nothingness: An essay on phenomenological ontology (H. Barnes, Trans.). London: Methuem.

  • Scully, J. (2009). Disability and the thinking body. In K. Kristiansen, S. Vehmas, & T. Shakespeare (Eds.), Arguing about disability: Philosophical perspectives (pp. 57–74). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shildrick, M. (2002). Embodying the monster: Encounters with the vulnerable self. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shildrick, M. (2009). Disability discourses of disability, subjectivity and sexuality. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillam.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shildrick, M., & Mykitiuk, R. (Eds.). (2005). Ethics of the body: Postconventional challenges. Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Snyder, S., Brueggeman, B., & Garland Thomson, R. (Eds.). (2002). Disability studies: Enabling the humanities. New York: The Modern Language Association of America.

  • Sorial, S. (2004). Heidegger Jean-Luc Nancy and the question of Dasein’s embodiment. Philosophy Today, 48(2), 216–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ten Broek, J., & Matson, F. (1966). The disabled and the law of welfare. California Law Review, 5, 811–812.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tremain, S. (2000). Foucault, governmentality and critical disability theory. In S. Tremain (Ed.), Foucault and the government of disability (pp. 1–26). USA: Michigan University Press.

  • Tremain, S. (2002). On the subject of impairment. In M. Corker & T. Shakespeare (Eds.), Disability/postmodernity: Embodying disability theory (pp. 32–47). London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tremain, S. (Ed.). (2005). Foucault and the government of disability. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, B. (1984). The body and society: Exploration in social theory. New York: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuttle, H. (1996). The crowd is untruth. New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuttle, H. (2005). Human life is radical reality. New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vallega, A. (2003). Heidegger and the issue of space: Thinking on exilic grounds. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vehmas, S. (2009). Arguing about disability: Philosophical perspectives. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wild, J. (1963). The philosophy of Martin Heidegger. Journal of Philosophy, 32(4), 664–677.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wrathall, M. (2006). How to read Heidegger. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, I. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Josephine A. Seguna.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Seguna, J.A. Disability: An Embodied Reality (or Space) of Dasein . Hum Stud 37, 31–56 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-013-9289-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10746-013-9289-6

Keywords

Navigation