Skip to main content
Log in

Infinities as Natural Places

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is shown that a notion of natural place is possible within modern physics. For Aristotle, the elements—the primary components of the world—follow to their natural places in the absence of forces. On the other hand, in general relativity, the so-called Carter–Penrose diagrams offer a notion of end for objects along the geodesics. Then, the notion of natural place in Aristotelian physics has an analog in the notion of conformal infinities in general relativity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Schummer (2008) presents a brief introduction to the main points of Aristotle’s physics.

  2. However “the religious Newton” assumed God’s final causes: “We know him only by his most wise and excellent contrivances of things, and final causes” (Newton 1846, Book III, p. 506).

  3. Apparently, because there are vestiges of teleology in the principle of least action, for example. See Stöltzner (1994).

  4. See Physics III.

  5. Nietzsche (2002, §22).

  6. Argumentation developed in Neves (2013, 2016) by using Nietzschean tools.

  7. See, for example, Jammer (1954, chapter 1).

  8. One may consider Einstein’s attempts of adopting Mach’s principle in general relativity as a modern form of an integrated cosmos.

  9. Aristotle says that the center of the universe and the planet earth’s place coincide accidentally. “It happens, however, that the centre of the earth and of the whole is the same. Thus they [the elements earth] do move to the centre of the earth, but accidentally, in virtue of the fact that the earth’s centre lies at the centre of the whole” (Aristotle 1922a, 296b15).

  10. At least for test particles. In this case, the tiny mass of that particles will not modify the metric, or spacetime geometry. On the other hand, massive bodies in motion modify the spacetime geometry. In this case, it is necessary to use backreaction effects to evaluate the body trajectory.

  11. In this article, one adopts geometric unities. Then the speed of light in vacuum is set equal to 1.

  12. Einstein static universe (Einstein 1917) is a special cosmological solution of Einstein’s field equations. It describes a non-expanding universe with dust, or pressureless matter. Moreover, Einstein adopted the cosmological constant to achieve such a solution of his field equations. It is well-known that Einstein static universe is unstable.

  13. A diffeomorphism is special type of map between two manifolds, which may be represented by sets. In general relativity, a spacetime is a manifold \({\mathcal {M}}\) endowed with a metric \(g_{\mu \nu }\). It is also indicated by \(({\mathcal {M}}, g_{\mu \nu })\). A spacetime is a set of events. Two manifolds are diffeomorphic if there exists a differentiable and invertible map between them. See (Wald 1984, Appendix C).

  14. In cosmology, matter means a pressureless perfect fluid.

  15. Today it is possible to construct cosmological models without the initial singularity in the general relativity context. Such regular models are the so-called bouncing cosmologies (Novello 2008; Neves 2017a). Contrary to Minkowski spacetime, the cosmological metric in the standard model is not geodesically complete. In the past, the initial singularity is the end of trajectories. In Minkowski spacetime, as we have already seen, we have a structure of past infinities. This is the reason why Minkowski spactime is geodesically complete and the Friedmann–Lemaître–Robertson–Walker metric is not.

References

  • Abbott, B. P., et al., & LIGO Scientific Collaboration and Virgo Collaboration. (2016). Observation of gravitational waves from a binary black hole merger. Physical Review Letters, 116, 061102.

  • Ade, P. A. R., et al., & Planck Collaboration. (2016). Planck 2015 results XIII. Cosmological parameters. Astron Astrophys, 594, A13.

  • Aristotle. (1922a). On the generation and corruption, translated by H. H. Joachim. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Aristotle. (1922b). On the generation and corruption, translated by H. H. Joachim. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Aristotle. (1983). Physics III and IV, translated by E. Hussey. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, B. (1966). Complete analytic extension of the symmetry axis of Kerr’s solution of Einstein’s equations. Physical Review, 141(4), 1242–1247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1916). Die Grundlage der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie. Annalen der Physik, 354(7), 769–822.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1917). Kosmologische Betrachtungen zur allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie. Sitzungsberichte der Königlich Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 142–152.

  • Hawking, S. W., & Ellis, G. F. R. (1973). The large scale structure of space–time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jammer, M. (1954). Concepts of space. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P. K. (1978). Aristotle on natural place and natural motion. ISIS, 69(3), 377–387.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M., & Hankinson, R. J. (1993). Aristotle’s universe: Its form and matter. Synthese, 96, 417–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neves, J. (2013). O eterno retorno hoje. Cadernos Nietzsche, 32, 283–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neves, J. C. S. (2016). Nietzsche for physicists. arXiv:1611.08193.

  • Neves, J. C. S. (2017a). Bouncing cosmology inspired by regular black holes. General Relativity and Gravitation, 49, 124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neves, J. C. S. (2017b). Einstein contra Aristotle: The sound from the heavens. Physics Essays, 30, 279–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1846). Mathematical principles of natural philosophy, translated by Andrew Motte. New York: Daniel Adee.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (2002). Beyond good and evil, translated by J. Norman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (2007). On the genealogy of morality, translated by Carol Diethe. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Novello, M., & Perez, B. S. E. (2008). Bouncing cosmologies. Physics Reports, 463, 127–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1964). Conformal treatment of infinity. In: de Witt B., & de Witt C. (Eds.), Relativity, groups and topology (pp. 565–584). New York-London: Gordon and Breach. Reprinted in 2011 in General Relativity and Gravitation, 43, 901–922.

  • Plato. (1931). Timaeus, translated by B. Jowett. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schummer, J. (2008). Aristotelian physics. In K. L. Lerner & B. W. Lerner (Eds.), Scientific thought in context (Vol. 2, pp. 759–768). Detroit: Gale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stöltzner, M. (1994). Action principles and teleology. In H. Atmanspacher & G. J. Dalenoort (Eds.), Inside versus outside (pp. 33–62). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wald, R. M. (1984). General relativity. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank IMECC-UNICAMP for the kind hospitality and referees for comments and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Juliano C. S. Neves.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Neves, J.C.S. Infinities as Natural Places. Found Sci 24, 39–49 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-018-9556-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-018-9556-0

Keywords

Navigation