Skip to main content
Log in

Evaluating Scientific Research Projects: The Units of Science in the Making

  • Published:
Foundations of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Original research is of course what scientists are expected to do. Therefore the research project is in many ways the unit of science in the making: it is the center of the professional life of the individual scientist and his coworkers. It is also the means towards the culmination of their specific activities: the original publication they hope to contribute to the scientific literature. The scientific project should therefore be of central interest to all the students of science, particularly the philosophers and sociologists of science. We shall focus on the preliminary evaluation of research projects—the specific task of referees—and will emphasize the problem of their scientificity—the chief concern of scientific gatekeepers. In the past such an examination aimed only at protecting the taxpayer from swindlers and incompetent amateurs, such as the inventors of continuous motion artifacts. In recent times a similar issue has resurfaced with regard to some of the most prestigious and most handsomely funded projects, namely work on string theory and many-worlds cosmology. Indeed, some of their faithful have claimed that these theories are so elegant, and so full of high-grade mathematics, that they should be exempted from empirical tests. This claim provoked the spirited rebuttal of the well-known cosmologists Ellis and Silk (Nature 516:321–323, 2014), which the present paper is intended to reinforce. Indeed, we shall try to show why empirical testability is necessary though insufficient for a piece of work to qualify as scientific. Finally, the present paper may also be regarded as an indirect contribution to the current debate over the reliability of quantitative indicators of scientific worth, such as the h-index of scientific productivity (e.g., Wilsdon in Nature 523:129, 2015). But we shall touch only tangentially on the sociological, political, and economics of research teams: our focus will be the acquisition of new scientific knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Barber, B. (1952). Science and the social order. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1955). The philosophy of the space-time approach to the quantum theory. Methodos, 7, 295–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1967a). Foundations of physics. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1967b). Scientific research, 2 vols. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1973a). Philosophy of physics. Dordrecht, NL: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1973b). Method, model and matter. Dordrecht, NL: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1999). The sociology-philosophy connection. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2003). Philosophical dictionary. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2006). Chasing reality: The Strife over realism. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2012). The correspondence theory of truth. Semiotica, 188, 65–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1908). ΣΩΖΕIΝ ΤΑ ΦΑΙΝΟΜΕΝΑ: Essai sur la théorie physique de Platon à Galilée. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G., & Silk, J. (2014). Defend the integrity of physics. Nature, 516, 321–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hebb, D. (1951). The role of neurological ideas in psychology. Journal of Personality, 20, 39–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koepsell, D. (2009). Who owns you? Malden, MA: Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, Bruno. (1987). Science in action: How to follow scientists and engineers through society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1979). Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. K. (1973). Sociology of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mirowski, P. (2011). Science-mart: Privatizing American science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raynaud, D. (2015). Scientific controversies. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romero, G. E., & Vila G. S. (2013). Introduction to black hole astrophysics. In Lecture Notes in Physics (Vol. 876).

  • Sokal, A., & Bricmont, J. (1998). Fashionable nonsense. New York: Picador.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takahashi, D. Y., et al. (2015). The developmental dynamics of marmoset monkey vocal production. Science, 349, 734–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilsdon, J. (2015). We need a measured approach to metrics. Nature, 523, 129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. New York: Penguin.

  • Zuckerman, H. (1977). Scientific elite: Nobel laureates in the United States. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mario Bunge.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bunge, M. Evaluating Scientific Research Projects: The Units of Science in the Making. Found Sci 22, 455–469 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-015-9474-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-015-9474-3

Keywords

Navigation