Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Should Democracies Ban Hate Speech? Hate Speech Laws and Counterspeech

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper’s main goal is to compare laws banning hate speech with counterspeech as an effective method of curtailing hate speech. In the first part, the paper discussed three normative justifications for hate speech bans. Firstly, the line of argument developed by critical race theorists that assumes that hate speech leads to the direct harm and violation of individuals’ rights. Secondly, paper examines the Weimar model that rests on the assumption that hate speech can lead to indirect harm to members of vulnerable minorities by creating a toxic environment, which opens the door to discrimination and even violence. Thirdly, the justification which is derived from the idea that such forms of extreme public speech violate the basic values and principles – such as inclusiveness, equality and mutual respect - on which constitutional democracies are built. This approach extends its argument from general values to the status of citizens by arguing that hate speech violates the equal standing of citizens by attempting to exclude certain members of society from the process of democratic deliberation based on their ascriptive characteristics. The second part of the paper looks at counterspeech as an efficient approach to limit harms that arise from hate speech. The author argues that legal bans should be reserved only for the most extreme forms of hateful rhetoric, while counterspeech is a valid option for tackling all other forms of hate speech.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Both defendants were convicted of genocide, not of public incitement to commit genocide. For criticism of this ruling, see: Baker 2012, pp. 155–156.

  2. It is worth noting, that only racial laws targeting Jewish people in Germany are a clear example of depriving a minority of their legal rights, in the other three cases cited by Tsesis – slaves in Mauritia, slaves in the antebellum South and Native Americans – the targets of discrimination never had equal rights to begin with. Of course, Tsesis could be referring here to the deprivation of natural or human rights of these minorities.

  3. This, for examples, is a position defended by Julie C. Suk when she points out that in France in most cases of Holocaust denial, offenders face criminal fines, not prison sentences and all of Holocaust denial literature is still available in libraries, which “supports the conclusion that the main function of criminalizing Holocaust denial is to strongly express the state’s moral outrage rather than to silence an unpopular viewpoint” (2012, p. 151).

  4. Although not explicitly arguing for the two-tier model, elements of this approach can be found in Parekh 2012 and Bader 2014. Parekh argues that stable democratic societies “have several mechanisms to cope with hate speech and its consequences, such as an open and competitive economy, a vibrant civil society, a reasonably cohesive and integrated society, a varied media representing a wide spectrum of views, and a plural and self-limiting public culture. They can, therefore, afford to assign law a relatively limited role” (2012, p. 55). Similarly, Bader advocates for legal sanctions when facing extreme cases of “incitement to violence and […] incitement to discrimination”, but that “we should try to fight the root causes of racist, ethno-centrist and religious violence and discrimination by the whole set of alternative non-legal responses” (2014, p. 335).

  5. There are two important differences worth noting between Brettschneider’s position and the position I am defending. First, Brettschneider argues that no speech should be banned of the basis of its content, while I maintain that speech that invokes violence and discrimination against members of certain groups should be legally prohibited. Second, for Brettschneider the main purpose of the state’s counterspeech against hateful utterances is to try and “change the minds of those who reject the values of free and equal citizenship” (2010: 1012), while I argue for the use of counterspeech by the state’s actors as a way to diminish the harmful effects of hate speech. On this second point see, Lepoutre: “I am concerned less with state-based counterspeech’s ability to persuade hate speakers and others, and more with its ability to block hate speech’s attempted assault on the dignity of its targets […] In decrying detestable speech, the state is reassuring its targets“ (2017:10).

  6. For additional arguments against putting the burden of counterspeech on the victims themselves, see: Nielsen 2012; Maitra and McGowan 2012.

  7. This approach of ranking different types of hate speech and proscribing different levels of legal and policy regulation to them depending on the severity of their impact is advocated in both the UN’s Rabat Plan of Action for 2012 and the European Commission against Racism and Intolerance (ECRI) General Policy Recommendation No. 15 from 2016 (ECRI, 2016).

  8. The political culture of counterspeech I am advocating here is much less restrictive than the culture of political correctness which entails not only the policy of speaking back, but also more penalizing measures such as loss of one’s job, cancellations of public speaking or book publishing deals, hindrance of person’ career advancement, etc.

  9. This explanation is, given the brevity of an article, inevitably somewhat simplified. First, a society where the culture of counterspeech reigns supreme and a society where the culture of intolerance prevails are two opposite extremes, but in the real world, it is reasonable to assume that most democratic societies would fall somewhere in between these two extremes. Second, even in a society where the culture of counterspeech has become the norm, we can assume that there might be areas where the demands of such a culture are ignored. This danger would be most pertinent in deeply polarized societies. I would like to thank a reviewer for pointing this out.

References

  • Bader V (2014) Free Speech or Non-discrimination as Trump? Reflections on Contextualised Reasonable Balancing and Its Limits. J Ethnic Migration Stud 40(2):320–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker EC (2012) Hate Speech. In: Herz M, Molnar P (eds) The Content and Context of Hate Speech. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 57–80

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barendt E (2005) Freedom of Speech. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bollinger L (1986) The Tolerant Society. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Brettschneider C (2012) When the State Speaks, What Should It Say? How Democracies Can Protect Expression and Promote Equality. Princeton, Princeton University Press, NJ

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brettschneider C (2010) When the State Speaks, What Should It Say? The Dilemmas of Freedom of Expression and Democratic Persuasion. Perspective on Politics 8(4):1005–1019

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown A (2015) Hate Speech Law: A Philosophical Examination. Routledge, Abingdon

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Delgado R (1982) Words That Wound: A Tort Action for Racial Insults, Epithets, and Name-Calling. Harv Civil Rights-Civil Liberties Law Rev 17:133–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Delgado R (2018) Words That Wound: A Tort Action for Racial Insults. In: Matsuda M et al (eds) Words That Wound: Critical Race Theory, Assaultive Speech, and the First Amendment. Routledge, New York, pp 89–110

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Delgado R, Stefancic J (2004) Understanding Words that Wound. Westview, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1996) Freedom’s Law. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (2009) Foreword. In: Hare I, Weinstein J (eds) Extreme Speech and Democracy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp v–ix

    Google Scholar 

  • ECRI (2016) ECRI General Policy Recommendation No.15 on Combating Hate Speech. Council of Europe, Strasbourg

    Google Scholar 

  • Foxman A, Wolf C (2013) Viral Hate. Palgrave MacMillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelber K (2002) Speaking Back: The Free Speech versus Hate Speech Debate. John Benjamins Publishing, Amsterdam

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gelber K (2012) Reconceptualizing Counterspeech in Hate Speech Policy (with a Focus on Australia). In: Herz M, Molnar P (eds) The Content and Context of Hate Speech. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 198–216

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gelber K, McNamara L (2015) The Effects of Civil Hate Speech Laws: Lessons from Australia. Law & Society Review 49:631–664

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heinze E (2016) Hate Speech and Democratic Citizenship. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hare I (2009) Extreme Speech under International and Regional Human Rights Standards. In: Hare I, Weinstein J (eds) Extreme Speech and Democracy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 62–80

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Howard JW (2019) Free Speech and Hate Speech. Annu Rev Polit Sci 22:93–109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacKinnon C (1996) Only Words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maitra I, McGowan MK (eds) (2012) Speech and Harm. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mchangama J (2012) /2013 The Harm in Hate Speech Law. Policy Review, pp. 95–102

  • Langton R (2014) Hate Speech and the Epistemology of Justice. Law and Philosophy, pp. 1–9

  • Lepoutre M (2017) Hate speech in public discourse: a pessimistic defense of counterspeech. Soc Theory Pract 43(4):851–883

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence C et al (1993) Introduction. In Matsuda, M (eds) (2018) Words That Wound: Critical Race Theory, Assaultive Speech, and the First Amendment. Routledge, New York, pp. 1–15

  • Malik K (2012) Interview with Kenan Malik. In: Herz M, Molnar P (eds) The Content and Context of Hate Speech. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 81–91

    Google Scholar 

  • Matsuda M (1989) Public Responses to Racist Speech. Mich Law Rev 87:2320–2381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matsuda M et al (eds) (2018) Words That Wound: Critical Race Theory, Assaultive Speech, and the First Amendment. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Matsuda M (2018) Public Response to Racist Speech: Considering the Victim’s Story. In: Matsuda, M (eds) (2018) Words That Wound: Critical Race Theory, Assaultive Speech, and the First Amendment. Routledge, New York, pp. 17–51

  • Nielsen LB (2012) Power in Public: Reactions, Responses, and Resistance to Offensive Public Speech. In: Maitra I, McGowan MK (eds) Speech & Harm: Controversies Over Free Speech. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 148–173

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Parekh B (2012) Is There Case for Banning Hate Speech? Hate Speech. In: Herz M, Molnar P (eds) The Content and Context of Hate Speech. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 37–56

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rabat Plan of Action on the prohibition of advocacy of national, racial or religious hatred that constitutes incitement to discrimination, hostility or violence (2012) http://www.ohchr.org/Documents/Issues/Opinion/SeminarRabat/Rabat_draft_outcome.pdf. Accessed 13 May 2021

  • Richards DAJ (1999) Free Speech and the Politics of Identity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley J (2015) How Propaganda Works. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strossen N (2012) Interview with Nadine Strossen. In: Herz M, Molnar P (eds) The Content and Context of Hate Speech. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 378–398

    Google Scholar 

  • Strossen N (2018) HATE: Why We Should Resist It with Free Speech, Not Censorship. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Suk JC (2012) Holocaust Denial and the Free Speech Theory of the State. In: Herz M, Molnar P (eds) The Content and Context of Hate Speech. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 144–163

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tsesis A (2002) Destructive Messages: How Hate Speech Paves the Way for Harmful Social Movements. New York University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Tirrell L (2012) Genocidal Language Games. In: Maitra I, McGowan MK (eds) Speech & Harm: Controversies Over Free Speech. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 174–221

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2012) The Harm in Hate Speech. Harvard University Press, Boston

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weinstein J (2009) Extreme Speech, Public Order and Democracy. In: Hare I, Weinstein J (eds) Extreme Speech and Democracy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 23–61

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

An early draft of this paper was presented at the ECPR Joint Session Freedom of Speech: How Much Is Too Much? in April 2020 in Toulouse, France. I would like to thank all the participant for their comments, especially Teresa Bejan, Corrado Fumagalli and Maxime Lepoutre. I would also like to thank anonymous reviewers for their suggestions and remarks.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Enes Kulenović.

Ethics declarations

The research leading to these results received funding from the University of Zagreb (research project “Hate Speech in Croatia”).

The author has no financial or proprietary interests in any material discussed in this article.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kulenović, E. Should Democracies Ban Hate Speech? Hate Speech Laws and Counterspeech. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 26, 511–532 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-022-10336-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-022-10336-2

Keywords

Navigation