Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Can We Use Social Policy to Enhance Compliance with Moral Obligations to Animals?

  • Published:
Ethical Theory and Moral Practice Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Those who wish to abolish or restrict the use of non-human animals in so-called factory farming and/or experimentation often argue that these animal use practices are incommensurate with animals’ moral status. If sound, these arguments would establish that, as a matter of ethics or justice, we should voluntarily abstain from the immoral animal use practices in question. But these arguments can’t and shouldn’t be taken to establish a related conclusion: that the moral status of animals justifies political intervention to disallow or significantly diminish factory farming and animal experimentation. In this paper, we set out to do two things: First, we argue that while the arguments mentioned above may establish the moral impermissibility or injustice of the practices they condemn, they are not sufficient to justify political interventions or social policies to abolish or restrict such practices. It is one thing to argue that some moral imperative or imperative of justice exists, and quite another thing to call for the use of political power to induce compliance with that imperative. Our second task is to assess the prospects for developing an argument that is sufficient to justify political interventions to restrict or abolish the use of non-human animals in factory farming or experimentation. Beyond establishing the immorality or injustice of animal consumption or experimentation, one must show that the interventions in question constitute legitimate use of political power. Would prohibiting or discouraging animal use be legitimate? We attempt to answer this question within the context of fundamental liberal constraints on the legitimate use of coercive political power.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Those who appeal to animals’ moral status to criticize the treatment of non-human animals in various practices do not necessarily agree about what should be done in response to these arguments, i.e., there is not agreement about the implications of recognizing the moral status of animals. Those with Utilitarian commitments, like Singer (2009), are more inclined to accept that animal experimentation might be justified under some circumstances and that humane treatment of non-human animals in agriculture might make raising animals for food permissible. Those who advance moral status criticisms of these practices and have deontological normative commitments, such as Regan (1983), Gruen (2011), and Francione (2009), argue that any use of animals in these practices, no matter how humane, is inconsistent with animals’ moral status. Our concern is not about how practices should be revised in light of moral status concerns, but about whether moral status arguments suffice to justify political intervention to bring about those revisions. Much of the discussion is framed in terms of argument for the abolition of certain practices, but we take the concerns we raise to apply equally well to arguments for political policies that merely restrict animal use in certain ways: for example, to arguments that we should legally permit the use of non-human animals only when that use can be justified on Utilitarian grounds, or only when the interests of non-human animals aren’t discounted simply because they are the interests of non-humans.

  2. It is often hard to tell whether those who advance moral status criticisms of practices such as factory farming or animal experimentation take their arguments to justify political intervention. For example, calls to abolish animal experimentation might be taken as just another way of saying “this practice is always immoral”; they might be taken more strongly to claim that individuals should take action so as to stop animal experimentation on moral grounds; or, more strongly still, such calls might be construed as demands for political responses to animal experimentation, such as legal prohibition or tighter regulation. We think that at least some proponents of these moral status criticisms take their arguments to have legal implications. For example, Francione (2009) argues against the “property status” of non-human animals on grounds that treating animals as property is incommensurate with their moral status. Since the property status of animals is codified in law and Francione takes his arguments to undermine the property status of animals, it seems like we are supposed to see moral status arguments as having policy implications. It seems to us that, at least sometimes, proponents of moral status criticisms flirt with the idea that their arguments justify political interventions on behalf of animals. Our aim is to show that any such flirtations are to be avoided, or at least stand in need of further justification. Furthermore, even though it is often difficult to tell whether a philosopher who advances a moral status criticism of some animal practice intends to justify some political intervention, there are some relatively unambiguous cases, and animal advocates who expressly advocate for political intervention often do appeal to moral status considerations. See footnote 10 for further discussion.

  3. See, for example, (Donaldson and Kymlicka 2011; Smith 2012; Garner 2013)

  4. Again, the conclusions of such arguments vary widely depending on which normative theory the proponent of the argument endorses. For a Utilitarian, for example, “equal consideration of interests” means that like interests get equal weight in Utilitarian calculations independent of species membership. For a deontologist, “equal consideration of interests” will entail that if a human interest in not suffering grounds a right against experimentation, then a similar interest in a non-human will ground a similar right.

  5. Another example of this form of argument is Norcross’s (2004).

  6. For discussion of this trend see (Milligan 2015; Cochrrane et al. 2016).

  7. For more on the development of Rawls’s views on animals and justice, see (Garner 2012).

  8. Smith (2012) also argues that we have political relationships with animals and that they are therefore subjects of justice. On the political relevance of animals’ participation in civil society, see also O’Sullivan 2007.

  9. Engel Jr., for example, takes his commonsense moral principles, their corollaries, and some additional facts about the efficacy of certain forms of animal experimentation to entail that various experiments “are wrong and ought to be abolished” (Engel Jr. 2012, 219). The “abolitionist approach” with which many prominent animal rights theorists are associated seeks “a prohibition on the use of animals by humans” (Garner 2013). See the “Animal Rights: The Abolitionist Approach” website: http://www.abolitionistapproach.com/.

  10. A lively debate continues about the possibility and nature of individual citizens’ obligations to promote justice. See (G. A. Cohen 1997; Murphy 1998; Williams 1998; Wolff 1998; Estlund 1998; Pogge 2000; J. Cohen 2001; Tan 2004; Scheffler 2006; Neufeld 2009; Schouten 2013).

  11. If justice does not generate obligations for individuals, then obligations that the state cannot legitimately discharge would cease to be obligations of justice at all, though they would remain cases wherein individuals’ actions—which they are not obligated to take—could promote the cause of justice. In this case, duties of justice to animals would be, if they are duties of justice at all, prima facie duties of justice which become actual duties only if they can be discharged by political institutions. We remain neutral on this issue. Though we use the language of “duties of justice” throughout this paper, these may in fact be only prima facie duties of justice.

  12. Presumably, we also face the burden of showing that the proposed interventions meet various standards of efficiency: that they are cost-effective public expenditures, and that they do not generate negative consequences whose disvalue outweighs the value of enhanced compliance with moral norms. For example, legal prohibitions on abortion might be unwarranted if the consequences of prohibition would be sufficiently bad to outweigh the good of reducing (ex hypothesi) immoral activity. We assume for the sake of argument that some version of animal protection interventions can meet these standards of efficiency.

  13. Clearly, the two mechanisms for establishing the legitimacy of political interventions are inter-related. For example, the majoritarian processes of the first mechanism can justify intervention only within the parameters set by the absolute protections of the second. To ensure that our conclusion is robust across various ways in which the two mechanisms might interact, we argue that the consensus approach cannot currently justify intervention even assuming those protections are otherwise consistent with applicable constraints on democratic decision-making.

  14. A direct majoritarian consensus is not the only democratic process by way of which to legitimately enact laws or policy. For example, it might be legitimate for the state to allow an agency, like the NSF, to make autonomous decisions. See (Brighouse 1995) for an example of this sort of autonomy and whether it is justified in the context of decisions about state funding of the arts.

  15. The Animal Welfare Act (AWA) of 1966 was in large part motivated by public outcry over the use of dogs in animal experimentation. See (Adams and Larson 2015)

  16. It is worth noting a distinction between two senses in which a majoritarian consensus might be relevant to questions of political intervention on behalf of animals. One way it may be important is that a majoritarian consensus will be practically necessary in order to effect change. Many of those who advance the claim that non-human animals are not currently treated in a way that is commensurate with their moral status claim that we are unlikely to realize commensurate treatment without broad public support. Along these lines, Francione claims that “on the social and legal level, there needs to be a paradigm shift as a social matter before the legal system will respond in a meaningful way” (Francione 2009 p. 109). This claim about the practical necessity of consensus is consistent with the view that political intervention on behalf of animals might be legitimate absent such consensus.

  17. As Donaldson and Kymlicka note: “Far more animals are being harmed today to serve human interests than 40 years ago, and every projection is that even more animals will be harmed and killed to serve humans 20 or 40 years from now. As a society, we remain addicted as ever to the exploitation of animals for human benefit” (Donaldson and Kymlicka 2012, 7).

  18. See O’Sullivan (2007) for a strategic proposal for building consensus in favor of new animal protections by drawing attention to internal inconsistency in our current animal treatment practices: that is, by drawing attention to cases wherein different sets of standards regulate our treatment of animals in morally relevantly similar circumstances.

  19. We follow the Rawlsian articulation of political liberalism most closely. See Rawls 2005. Other defenses and elaborations of political liberalism can be found in (B. A. Ackerman 1980; B. Ackerman 1994; Larmore 1987; Larmore 1996; Moon 2012; Quong 2011).

  20. We think that something like the mistake identified in this paragraph leads Garner prematurely to reject liberalism’s commitment to respecting pluralism (Garner 2003).

  21. Notice also that the justification for citizenship encompassing certain capacities is why the account of citizenship is not “speciesist.” Appeals to agency or moral capacity to ground the moral status of humans is problematic because agency is not a morally relevant difference between humans and non-humans; no justification can be given, according to moral status arguments, for why the interests of non-agents should not be accommodated. On the other hand, such a reason has been given for the political idealization of citizenship to include these capacities.

  22. Similarly, protections of bodily integrity are called for by the importance of physical security to having even the most rudimentary capacity to pursue our chosen conception of the good; certain curricular requirements for children’s education might be justified on the grounds that they are necessary to ensure that all children can develop a capacity for a sense of justice; and redistributive social policies and other social services might be justified on the grounds that they ensure the material preconditions for the effective exercise of our basic liberties.

  23. Given the causal relationship between factory farming and global climate change, there may in fact be citizenship interests at stake that would justify actions that political intervention to significantly limit factory farming, for example. See (Flanders 2013) for a public reasons argument in favor of animal protections that’s based largely on appeal to human benefits that would be derived from such protections.

  24. Or what has traditionally been called the problem of “marginal cases” This alternative phrasing, due to Mylan Engel Jr., identifies the problem without suggesting that the individuals under consideration are in any way marginal. DeGrazia offers another alternative, “non-paradigm humans,” in (DeGrazia 2014)

  25. For an assessment of the (lack of) attention to disability among philosophers generally, see (Tremain 2013).

  26. Nussbaum’s approach appears less controversial when we examine the actual animal policies she thinks it licenses, including guidelines for the ethical treatment of the animals we use or consume, including those in circuses and zoos, and those consumed for food. She argues that, over the long term, we should work toward a consensus against eating sentient animals, but she does not argue that her capabilities approach can justify outlawing or even seriously restricting any of these practices. These policy recommendations may well be less controversial than the capabilities approach that Nussbaum uses to support them, but they fall far short of what would be required to seriously reduce immoral use and consumption of animals. Indeed, as the policy implications claimed for the capabilities approach become stronger, the claim that the approach can maintain the support of an overlapping consensus becomes correspondingly less plausible.

  27. Besides Nussbaum’s capabilities approach and the other alternatives examined in this paper, see Abbey (2016) and (2017) for discussion of liberalisms that might have more permissive implications for the legitimacy of animal protections absent majoritarian approval.

References

  • Abbey R (2007) Rawlsian resources for animal ethics. Ethics Environ 12(1):1–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abbey R (2016) Putting cruelty first: exploring Judith Shklar’s liberalism of fear for animal ethics. Politics and Animals 2:25–36

  • Abbey R (2017) Closer kinships: Rortyan resources for animal rights. Contemporary Political Theory 16:1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ackerman B (1980) Social justice in the liberal state. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Ackerman B (1994) Political liberalisms. J Philos 91(7):364–386

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams B, Larson J (2015) Legislative history of the animal welfare act: National Agricultural Library. https://www.nal.usda.gov/awic/legislative-history-animal-welfare-act-introduction. Accessed 13 Mar 2018

  • Barry BM (1995) Justice as impartiality. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Brighouse H (1995) Neutrality, publicity, and state funding of the arts. Philos Public Aff 24(1):35–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cochrrane A, Garner R, O'Sullivan S (2016) Animal ethics and the political. Crit Rev Int Soc Pol Phil 21:261–277

  • Coeckelbergh M (2009) Distributive justice and co-operation in a world of humans and non-humans: a contractarian argument for drawing non-humans into the sphere of justice. Res Publica 15(1):67–84

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen GA (1997) Where the action is: on the site of distributive justice. Philos Public Aff 26:3–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen J (2001) Taking people as they are? Philos Public Aff 30(4):363–386

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeGrazia D (2014) On the moral status of infants and the cognitively disabled: a reply to Jaworska and Tannenbaum. Ethics 124:543–556

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson S, Kymlicka W (2011) Zoopolis: a political theory of animal rights. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Donaldson S, Kymlicka W (2012) Do we need a political theory of animal rights? In: Minding animals international conference. Utrecht, Netherlands

  • Engel M Jr (2012) The commonsense case against animal experimentation. In: Garret J (ed) The ethics of animal research: exploring the controversy, 1st edn. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp 215–236

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Estlund D (1998) Debate: Liberalism, equality, and fraternity in Cohen’s critique of Rawls. J Polit Philos 6:99–112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flanders C (2013) Public reason and animal rights. In: Wissenburg M, Schlosberg D (eds) Political animals and animal politics. Palgrave Macmillan, London, pp 44–57

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Francione GL (2009) Animals as persons: essays on the abolition of animal exploitation. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallup. 2015. “In U.S., More Say Animals Should Have Same Rights as People.” Gallup.com . http://www.gallup.com/poll/183275/say-animals-rights-people.aspx

  • Garner R (2003) Animals, politics and justice: Rawlsian liberalism and the plight of non-humans. Environmental Politics 12:3–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garner R (2012) Rawls, animals and justice: new literature, same response. Res Publica 18:159–172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garner R (2013) A theory of justice for animals: animal rights in a nonideal world. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Gruen L (2011) Ethics and animals: an introduction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Horrigan L, Lawrence RS, Walker P (2002) How sustainable agriculture can address the environmental and human health harms of industrial agriculture. Environ Health Perspect 110:445–456

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larmore CE (1987) Patterns of moral complexity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Larmore CE (1996) The morals of modernity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Milligan T (2015) The political turn in animal rights. Politics and Animals 1:6–15

  • Moon JD (2012) Constructing community: moral pluralism and tragic conflicts. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

  • Murphy LB (1998) Institutions and the demands of justice. Philos Public Aff 27:251–291

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neufeld B (2009) Coercion, the basic structure, and the family. J Soc Philos 40:37–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norcross A (2004) Puppies, pigs, and people: eating meat and marginal cases. Philos Perspect 18:229–245

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Sullivan S (2007) Advocating for animals equally from within a liberal paradigm. Environmental Politics 16:1–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pippin JJ (2005) The failure of animal tests of COX-2 inhibitors. http://www.physiciansforresponsiblemedicine.org/pdfs/research/testing/exp/COX2Report.pdf

  • Pogge TW (2000) On the site of distributive justice: reflections on Cohen and Murphy. Philos Public Aff 29:137–169

  • Quong J (2011) Liberalism without perfection. Oxford University Press, Oxford, New York

  • Rawls J(1999) A theory of justice. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

  • Rawls J (2005) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York

  • Regan T (1983) The case for animal rights. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands M (2002) Animals like us. Verso Press, London

  • Rowlands M (2009) Animal rights: moral theory and practice. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler S (2006) Is the basic structure basic? In: Sypnowich C (ed) The egalitarian conscience: essays in honour of G. A. Cohen. Oxford University Press, pp 102–129

  • Schouten G (2013) Restricting justice: political interventions in the home and in the market. Philos Public Aff 41:357–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer P (2009) Animal liberation: the definitive classic of the animal movement. Harper Collins, New York

  • Smith KK (2012) Governing animals: animal welfare and the liberal state. Oxford University Press, New York

  • Steinfeld H, Gerber P, Wassenaar TD, et al (2006) Livestock’s long shadow: environmental issues and options. United Nations Food and Agriculture Organization (FAO) http://www.fao.org/docrep/010/a0701e/a0701e00.HTM

  • Streiffer R, Basl J (2011) Ethical issues in the application of biotechnology to animals in agriculture. In: Beauchamp TL, Frey RG (eds) The oxford handbook of animal ethics. OUP USA, pp 826–854

  • Tan K-C (2004) Justice and personal pursuits. J Philos 101:331–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tremain S (2013) Introducing feminist philosophy of disability. In: Disability studies quarterly

  • VanDeVeer D (1979) Of beasts, persons, and the original position. The Monist 62:368–377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams A (1998) Incentives, inequality, and publicity. Philos Public Aff 27:225–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolff J (1998) Fairness, respect, and the egalitarian ethos. Philos Public Aff 27:97–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to the following people for feedback at various stages of this paper: Jeff Behrends, Brian Berkey, Eric Blumenson, Michael Bukoski, Candice Delmas, Mylan Engel Jr., David Faraci, Bo Kim Kopek, Matt Kopec, Katie McShane, Stephen Nathanson, Ronald Sandler, Eric Stencil, Daniel Wodak. We also received exceptional feedback after presenting these materials at the Rocky Mountain Ethics (RoME) Congress in 2015. We are especially grateful for Katie McShane’s comments on this work. We apologize for not being able to list all the attendees that offered feedback. Finally, we are thankful to anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful, helpful comments that much improved this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Basl.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Basl, J., Schouten, G. Can We Use Social Policy to Enhance Compliance with Moral Obligations to Animals?. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 21, 629–647 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-018-9895-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-018-9895-5

Keywords

Navigation