Skip to main content
Log in

Resentment, Parenting, and Strawson’s Compatibilism

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Is moral responsibility compatible with determinism? Peter Strawson’s first answer is: I do not know what the thesis of determinism is. His second answer seems to be: Yes, it is, and we can see this by looking to relevant pockets of our ordinary practices and attitudes, especially our responses (resentment, anger, love, forgiveness) to quality of will. His second answer has shaped subsequent discussions of moral responsibility. But what exactly is Strawson’s compatibilism? And is it a plausible view? By attending to Strawson’s account of parenting and the development of moral agents from children to adults, I’ll clarify and defend the following account: For Strawson, the appropriateness conditions for holding responsible change by degrees, over time, based on an agent’s susceptibility to empathy and quality of will, and this shows us that determinism is irrelevant to responsibility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. But in Sect. 5 I’ll have some more remarks about why (6) is not as radical as it might seem.

  2. See Beglin’s (2018) concern-based construal of the Strawsonian reversal, a careful elaboration of (3).

  3. Manual Vargas (2007: 148) is similarly puzzled by the suggestion or implication that there is some specific age at which children go from determined to do what they do to no longer determined to do what they do, that is, a specific age at which the indeterminism unique to human decision-making kicks in.

  4. For Fischer and Ravizza, taking responsibility is a distinctively human process that begins its development in early childhood, long before we are capable of contemplating the subtleties of abstract metaphysical principles (1998: 242).

  5. Note that nothing in what I say here undermines Strawson’s claim that objectivity of attitude and the normal reactive attitudes are incompatible. That claim is still true when understood as a claim about the full weight and range of the reactive attitudes and a total objectivity of attitude.

  6. Perhaps we can also make better sense of why (6), “There is no fact of the matter as to whether an agent is morally responsible” (Bennett (2008)), might seem like an attractive reading (though I do not wish to endorse (6)): responsibility facts become so context-sensitive, on the picture I suggest here, that one might well think that even if there is some fact of the matter as to whether or not S is responsible for A, we often cannot realistically determine whether or not S is responsible for A. Additionally, we might say that (1) it is unimportant whether or not S is responsible for A—what matters is how responsible S is for A, (2) determinations about the degree of responsibility of S for A hinge on the progressive development of S as a moral agent, and (3) given (1) and (2), it is misleading to characterize responsibility ascriptions as ‘facts’.

References

  • Beglin, D. (2018). Responsibility, Libertarians, and the ‘Facts as We Know Them’: A concern-based construal of Strawson’s reversal. Ethics, 128, 612–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. 2008. Accountability (II). In McKenna and Russell: 47–68.

  • Bluestein, J. (1982). Parents and children: The ethics of the family. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bluestein, J. (1993). The family in medical decision making. Hastings Center Report, 23, 6–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandenburg, D. (2018). The nurturing stance: Making sense of responsibility without blame. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 99, 5–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coren, D. (2019). Freedom, gratitude, and resentment: Olivi and Strawson. Res Philosophica, 96, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1984). Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, S. (2003). Moral development and moral responsibility. Monist, 86, 181–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, D. (2008). Anne of Green Gables turns 100. The Toronto Star. Retrieved from https://www.thestar.com/entertainment/2008/01/26/anne_of_green_gables_turns_100.html

  • Hoffman, M. L. (1991). Empathy, social cognition, and moral action. In W. M. Kurtines & J. L. Gewirtz (Eds.), Handbook of moral behavior and development: vol. 1. theory (pp. 275–305). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyun, I. (2000). When adolescents “mismanage” their chronic medical conditions: An ethical exploration. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 10, 147–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hyun, I. (2003). Conceptions of family-centered medical decision making and their difficulties. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 12, 196–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, K. (1996). Trust as an affective attitude. Ethics, 107, 4–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGeer, V. (2019). Scaffolding agency: A proleptic account of the reactive attitudes. European Journal of Philosophy, 27, 301–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (1998). The limits of evil and the role of moral address: A defense of Strawsonian compatibilism. The Journal of Ethics, 2, 123–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2011). Conversation and responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2005). Where Frankfurt and Strawson Meet. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 29, 163–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2012). Conversation and responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Montgomery, L. M. (1908). Anne of Green gables. L.C. Page & Company.

  • Montgomery, L. M. (1909). Anne of Anovlea. L.C. Page & Company.

  • Nelkin, D. (2016). Difficulty and degrees of moral praiseworthiness and blameworthiness. Nous, 50, 356–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L. F. (1998). Children, families, and health care decision making. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, T. (1999). What is a child? Ethics, 109, 715–738.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, D. (2017). Response-dependent responsibility; or, a funny thing happened on the way to blame. Philosophical Review, 126, 481–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and Resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tierney, H. (2019). Quality of reasons and degrees of responsibility. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 97, 661–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P. (2016). Strawson, moral responsibility, and the ‘order of explanation’: An intervention. Ethics, 127, 208–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tognazzini, N. (2013). Blameworthiness and the affective account of blame. Philosophia, 41, 1299–1312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2007). Revisionism. In Four views on free will (pp 126–165).

  • Vargas, M., Fischer, J. M., Kane, R., & Pereboom, D. (2007). Four views on free will. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. J. (1994). Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. (1987). Responsibility and the limits of evil: Variations on a Strawsonian theme. In F. Schoeman (Ed.), Responsibility, character, and the emotions: New essays in moral psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. (2014). Peter Strawson on responsibility and sociality. In D. Shoemaker & N. Tognazzini (Eds.), Oxford studies in agency and responsibility (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1981). The importance of free will. Mind, 90, 366–378.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For helpful suggestions, I am grateful to Michael McKenna, Alastair Norcoss, Robert Pasnau, Gagan Sapkota, and Susan Wolf. In addition, I am grateful to thoughtful suggestions from two anonymous reviewers for Erkenntnis.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Coren.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Publisher's Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Coren, D. Resentment, Parenting, and Strawson’s Compatibilism. Erkenn 88, 43–65 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00339-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00339-9

Navigation