Skip to main content
Log in

Naive Realism for Unconscious Perceptions

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Unconscious perceptions (i.e., person-level perceptions that lack phenomenal character) have recently become a focal point in the debate for and against naive realism. In this paper I defend the naive realist side. More specifically, I use an idea of Martin’s to develop a new version of naive realism—neuro-computational naive realism. I argue that neuro-computational naive realism offers a uniform treatment of both conscious and unconscious perceptions. I also argue that it accommodates the possibility of phenomenally different conscious perceptions of the same items, and that it can answer a further challenge to naive realism raised by Berger and Nanay.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Block (in Phillips and Block 2017, p. 169) also argues for this.

  2. As will become clear later, neuro-computational naive realism extends and develops upon an idea of Martin’s (1998). I am indebted to his work.

  3. See Brewer (2011, p. 93), Campbell (2002, p. 117), Snowdon (1990, p. 124), and Martin (2006, p. 354; 2004, p. 39; 2002b, pp. 392–393).

  4. See Brewer (2011, p. 55), Campbell (2002, pp. 117–118), French (2014, p. 395) and Martin (2004, p. 39).

  5. As far as I know, Travis (2013, p. 31) comes closest to accepting the stronger thesis, as he holds that perceptions do not represent things as being thus and so to the subject. But even Travis allows perceptions to involve certain alternative kinds of representational properties.

  6. See fn. 4.

  7. The term “standpoint” is from Campbell (2009).

  8. On the extra-dermal conditions, see Campbell (2009, pp. 657–658) and Brewer (2011). On the conditions of the perceiver’s psychological apparatus, see Brewer (2011, chp. 5; 2013), Campbell (2002, pp. 118–119) and Fish (2009, chp. 3).

  9. The example is adapted from Logue (2012, p. 211).

  10. See, e.g., Weiskrantz (2009), Kouider and Dehaene (2007) or Lin and He (2009). For a general introduction, see Prinz (2015). For a review of experimental methods, see Breitmeyer (2015).

  11. Some may believe that selectionism can successfully resist Block (2007, 2010) and Pautz’s (2014, 2017) arguments. For a long argument that selectionism cannot do so, see my (2019).

  12. By “S is being appeared to in a greenish way” I roughly mean that S is appeared to in the way that I would be appeared to were I to now be confronted by a green thing under ideal conditions.

  13. My use of “appearance properties” is different from Genone (2014), Antony (2011), Kalderon (2011), Shoemaker (1994, 2000, 2006) and others’ use of “appearance properties”. On their use of the term, appearance properties are not properties that subjects can have, but properties that objects or scenes can have. More specifically, appearance properties are ways that objects or scenes appear simpliciter (as opposed to ways that they appear to a specific subject). This use of “appearance properties” should be carefully distinguished from my own.

  14. Martin discusses and defends this conception of phenomenology in his (1998, 2002a, b). Also see Campbell (2002) and Gomes and French (2016).

  15. To say that one set of properties is determined completely in virtue of another set of properties does not entail that each of the properties in the first set is identical to some property in the second set. One alternative possibility is that the properties in the second set ground the properties in the first. Therefore, my proposal is compatible with multiple views about the nature of appearance properties themselves.

  16. External events may, of course, cause you to have the neuro-computational properties that you have. In this way, external events may also play a causal role in the instantiation of appearance properties. This is perfectly consistent with the claim that you have the appearance properties that you do completely in virtue of your neuro-computational properties.

  17. My use of “neuro-computational properties” follows Pautz’s (2010, 2013, 2017). Like Pautz, I will not try to decide here between the various causal, semantic, syntactic or mechanistic accounts of what it takes to implement a computation or an algorithm. For a review of the different positions, see Piccinini (2017). Note that although the set of neuro-computational properties is broad enough so as not to pre-judge matters currently under empirical inquiry and dispute, it will also prove to be narrow enough to advance the purposes of the present paper.

  18. For correlations regarding taste, see e.g. Di Lorenzo et al. (2009). For those regarding smell, see e.g. Howard et al. (2009). For those regarding loudness, see e.g. Röhl et al. (2011). Finally, for those regarding color, see Brouwer and Heeger (2013).

  19. Although, cf. Logue (2017).

  20. See my (2019).

  21. It is noteworthy that naive realists can deny that neuro-computational properties are identical to, or ground, the S perceives x relation and still assert that neuro-computational properties are part of the supervenience base for the S perceives x relation.

  22. See, e.g., Brewer (2011, p. 55) and Campbell (2002, pp. 117–118).

  23. A related, though very different, concern is that (NR2) might be in tension with the possibility that neuro-computational properties are themselves being represented—e.g., by the subject, by some of the subject’s properties or states, or by some of the properties or states of the subject’s body. But this concern can also be put aside: That something or other represents neuro-computational properties implies nothing about the nature of the S perceives x relation. For example, nothing follows about the nature of the S perceives x relation from the possibility that a thought in the subject’s head, or a sentence the subject writes down on a piece of paper, represent (inter alia) neuro-computational properties.

  24. I follow Antony (2011), Brewer (2011), Campbell and Cassam (2014, chp. 4), Fish (2009), Genone (2014), Kalderon (2011), and Travis (2013) in taking illusions to be perceptions of some sort. So I accept that naive realists should account for illusions.

References

  • Allen, K. (2016). A Naive realist theory of colour. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anaya, A., & Clarke, S. (2017). Naïve realism and unconscious perception: A reply to Berger and Nanay. Analysis, 77, 267–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Antony, L. (2011). The openness of illusions. Philosophical Issues, 21, 25–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beck, O. (2019). Rethinking naive realism. Philosophical Studies, 176, 607–633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger, J., & Nanay, B. (2016). Relationalism and unconscious perception. Analysis, 76, 426–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2007). Sexism, racism, ageism, and the nature of consciousness. In N. Block (Ed.), Consciousness, function, and representation, Vol. 1 Chapter 25 (pp. 571–601). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2010). Attention and mental paint. Philosophical Issues, 20, 23–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2016). The Anna Karenina principle and skepticism about unconscious perception. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93, 452–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breitmeyer, B. G. (2015). Psychophysical “blinding” methods reveal a functional hierarchy of unconscious visual processing. Consciousness and Cognition, 35, 234–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (2011). Perception and its objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brewer, B. (2013). Attention and direct realism. Analytic Philosophy, 54, 421–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, G. J., & Heeger, D. J. (2013). Categorical clustering of the neural representation of color. The Journal of Neuroscience, 33(39), 15454–15465.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2009). Consciousness and reference. In B. McLaughlin, A. Beckermann, & S. Walter (Eds.), Oxford handbook of philosophy of mind (pp. 648–662). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J., & Cassam, Q. (2014). Berkeley’s puzzle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Di Lorenzo, P. M., Chen, J.-Y., & Victor, J. D. (2009). Quality time: Representation of a multidimensional sensory domain through temporal coding. The Journal of Neuroscience, 29(29), 9227–9238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fish, W. (2009). Perception, hallucination, and illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • French, C. (2014). Naive realist perspectives on seeing blurrily. Ratio, 27, 393–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Genone, J. (2014). Appearance and illusion. Mind, 123, 339–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gomes, A., & French, C. (2016). On the particularity of experience. Philosophical Studies, 173, 451–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodale, M., & Milner, D. (2013). Sight unseen (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Howard, J. D., Plailly, J., Grueschow, M., Haynes, J.-D., & Gottfried, J. A. (2009). Odor quality coding and categorization in human posterior piriform cortex. Nature Neuroscience, 12, 932–938.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (2006). Better than mere knowledge? The function of sensory awareness. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 260–290). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kalderon, M. E. (2011). Color illusion. Noûs, 45, 751–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kouider, S., & Dehaene, S. (2007). Levels of processing during non-conscious perception: A critical review of visual masking. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 362(1481), 857–875.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lin, Z., & He, S. (2009). Seeing the invisible: The scope and limits of unconscious processing in binocular rivalry. Progress in Neurobiology, 87(4), 195–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Logue, H. (2012). Why naive realism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 112, 211–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Logue, H. (2017). Are perceptual experiences just representations? In B. Nanay (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of perception Chapter 3 (pp. 43–56). New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (1998). Setting things before the mind. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 43, 157–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2002a). Particular thoughts and singular thought. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Logic, thought and language, volume 51 of Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement (pp. 173–214). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2002b). The transparency of experience. Mind and Language, 17, 376–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2004). The limits of self-awareness. Philosophical Studies, 120, 37–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. G. F. (2006). On being alienated. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 354–410). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2008). The disjunctive conception of experience as material for a transcendental argument. In A. Haddock & F. Macpherson (Eds.), Disjunctivism: Perception, action, knowledge Chapter 16 (pp. 376–389). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pautz, A. (2010). Do theories of consciousness rest on a mistake? Philosophical Issues, 20, 333–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pautz, A. (2013). Does phenomenology ground mental content? In U. Kriegel (Ed.), Phenomenal Intentionality, his “Experiences are representations: An empirical argument”. In B. Nanay (ed.) Current controversies in philosophy of perception, 2017 (pp. 23–42) Chapter 11 (pp. 194–234). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Pautz, A. (2014). The real trouble with phenomenal externalism: New empirical evidence for a brain-based theory of consciousness. In R. Brown (Ed.), Consciousness inside and out: Phenomenology, neuroscience, and the nature of experience Chapter 18 (pp. 237–298). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pautz, A. (2017). Experiences are representations: An empirical argument. In B. Nanay (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of perception Chapter 2 (pp. 23–42). New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Peters, M. A. K., Kentridge, R. W., Phillips, I., & Block, N. (2017). Does unconscious perception really exist? Continuing the assc20 debate. Neuroscience of Consciousness, 3, 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I. (2016). Consciousness and criterion: On Block’s case for unconscious seeing. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 93, 413–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I., & Block, N. (2017). Debate on unconscious perception. In B. Nanay (Ed.), Current controversies in philosophy of perception Chapter 11 (pp. 165–192). New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2017). Computation in physical systems. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Summer 2017 edition. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/computation-physicalsystems/.

  • Prinz, J. J. (2015). Unconscious perception. In M. Matthen (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of perception Chapter 19 (pp. 371–389). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1994). Sense, nonsense, and the senses: An inquiry into the powers of the human mind. The Journal of Philosophy, 91, 445–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Röhl, M., Kollmeier, B., & Uppenkamp, S. (2011). Spectral loudness summation takes place in the primary auditory cortex. Human Brain Mapping, 32(9), 1483–1496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (1994). Phenomenal character. Noûs, 28(1), 21–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2000). Phenomenal character revisited. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 60(2), 465–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2006). On the ways things appear. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Perceptual experience (pp. 461–480). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon, P. (1990). The objects of perceptual experience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 64, 121–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, C. (2013). The silences of the senses. In C. Travis (Ed.), Perception: Essays after Frege Chapter 1 (pp. 23–58). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weiskrantz, L. (2009). Blindsight—A case study spanning 35 years and new developments (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am indebted Jacob Berger, Bence Nanay, Adam Pautz, Henry Taylor, and to the participants of the European Society for Philosophy and Psychology, Central APA, and The Science of Consciousness conferences for criticisms and good advice that helped in the writing of this paper. I am especially grateful to David Widerker and to two anonymous reviewers for their invaluable suggestions. My writing was aided by the generous support of the Department of Philosophy and Kreitman School of Advanced Studies at Ben-Gurion University of the Negev.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ori Beck.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Beck, O. Naive Realism for Unconscious Perceptions. Erkenn 87, 1175–1190 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00236-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00236-1

Navigation