Skip to main content
Log in

The Impossibility of Mere Animal Knowledge for Reflective Subjects

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper we give reasons to think that reflective epistemic subjects cannot possess mere animal knowledge. To do so we bring together literature on defeat and higher-order evidence with literature on the distinction between animal knowledge and reflective knowledge. We then defend our argument from a series of possible objections.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Sosa (2017, p. 36).

  2. A distinction is sometimes made between partial and full defeaters, where partial defeaters reduce the extent of S’s justification for believing p even though S remains justified in believing p. Full defeaters render S’s belief unjustified. As we are using the term, defeaters are full defeaters. For more on this distinction, see Bergmann (2005).

  3. See Bonjour (1980) for the case of Norman, and Lehrer (1990) for the case of Truetemp.

  4. Such a response to the case of Norman the clairvoyant has been endorsed by Ghijsen (2016), Goldman (1986, p. 112, 2011), Nagel (2016), and Plantinga (1996, p. 333) among others.

  5. Here we use ‘rational’ as a stand-in for ‘reasonable’ or ‘justified’; nothing hangs on this variant vocabulary.

  6. This way of putting things may assume an implausible kind of doxastic voluntarism, but the voluntarism is not necessary for making the relevant point. Which doxastic attitudes a subject happens to have can’t be the whole story with respect to whether they have a defeater. In at least some cases, propositions that a subject is justified in believing/doubting (though she in fact fails to believe/doubt it) do defeating work.

  7. See Lasonen-Aarnio (2010, 2014), Coates (2012), Hazlett (2013), Williamson (2014), Titelbaum (2015), and Worsnip (2018). For replies, see Horowitz (2014).

  8. Higher-order evidence for p is evidence about one’s evidence for or against p or relevant to how one’s belief that p was produced.

  9. See also Sliwa and Horowitz (2015) and Smithies (2012) for more on this point.

    Relatedly, Huemer (2011) endorses a metacoherence requirement, that categorically believing that P commits one, on reflection, to the view that one knows that P.

  10. For additional motivation here, see Bergmann (2005), Christensen (2010), Feldman (2009), Moon (forthcoming), and [blinded].

  11. Since it can be denied that Norman’s belief enjoys even prima facie justification, it is not a consequence of endorsing rational epistemic akrasia that Norman’s belief is justified.

  12. See Sosa (2017, p. 81), though Sosa does acknowledge the intuitive pull to deny knowledge to these subjects (p. 78).

  13. Sosa’s own view, recall, is that they have animal knowledge but lack reflective knowledge (or, as he calls it, knowledge full well).

  14. It may be that the beliefs of Norman and Truetemp are rational in some sense. What is relevant to our argument here is that these beliefs are irrational in the sense of rationality required for knowledge (of any kind).

  15. Again see Lasonen-Aarnio (2010) and Williamson (2014).

  16. Moon (forthcoming) distinguishes the epistemic state of young Norman and adult Norman. On Moon’s account, young Norman has justified clairvoyant beliefs whereas adult Norman does not. The difference for Moon, is that young Norman should not be expected to have certain beliefs that would defeat his justification for this clairvoyant beliefs, whereas adult Norman should. Our account is friendly to those who share Moon’s intuitions about Norman, though it does not require endorsing them. In our terms, adult Norman has acquired an epistemic perspective on his belief-forming processes, and given this fact, he now has a defeater for any justification his clairvoyant beliefs would have possessed. On both accounts, there is adult Norman now possesses a defeater that he did not possess as a young child, and this is an important epistemic difference.

  17. That it can be irrational is what we argued above.

References

  • Bergmann, M. (2005). Defeaters and higher-level requirements. Philosophical Quarterly, 55(220), 419–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1980). Externalist theories of empirical knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 53–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2010). Higher-order evidence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(1), 185–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coates, A. (2012). Rational epistemic akrasia. American Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 113–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elga, A. (2005). On overrating oneself … and knowing it. Philosophical Studies, 123, 115–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2009). Evidentialism, higher-order evidence, and disagreement. Episteme: A Journal of Social Epistemology, 6(3), 294–312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghijsen, H. (2016). Norman and truetemp revisited reliabilistically: A proper functionalist account of clairvoyance. Episteme, 13, 89–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (2011). ‘Reliabilism’. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/reliabilism/.

  • Hazlett, A. (2013). A luxury of the understanding: On the value of true belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horowitz, S. (2014). Epistemic akrasia. Noûs, 48, 718–744.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, M. (2011). The puzzle of metacoherence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 82(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J. (1999). Testimonial knowledge and transmission. The Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 471–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2010). Unreasonable knowledge. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1990). Theory of knowledge. Boulder and London: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moon, A. Forthcoming. How to use cognitive faculties you never knew you had. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly.

  • Nagel, J. (2016). Knoweldge and reliability. In H. Kornblith & B. McLaughlin (Eds.), Alvin Goldman and his critics (pp. 237–256). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1996). Respondeo. In J. Kvanvig (Ed.), Warrant in contemporary epistemology. Rowman and Littlefield: Lanham, MD.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sliwa, P., & Horowitz, S. (2015). Respecting all the evidence. Philosophical Studies, 172(11), 2835–2858.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D. (2012). Moore’s paradox and accessibility of justification. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(2), 273–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). Reflective knowledge: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2009). Reflective knowledge: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2015). Judgment and agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2017). Epistemology. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Titelbaum, M. (2015). Rationality’s fixed point (or: in defense of right reason). In Gendler and Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology, Vol. 5.

  • Williamson, T. (2014). Very improbable knowing. Erkenntnis, 79(5), 971–999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Worsnip, A. (2018). The conflict of evidence and coherence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 96(1), 3–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sanford Goldberg.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Goldberg, S., Matheson, J. The Impossibility of Mere Animal Knowledge for Reflective Subjects. Erkenn 85, 829–840 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0052-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0052-2

Navigation