Skip to main content
Log in

Deliberative Democracy and Corporate Constitutionalism: Considering Corporate Constitutional Courts

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Committees multiply in firms, whether stakeholder boards or committees, multi-stakeholder initiatives, ethics committees, or oversight boards. These arrangements aim to organise and legitimise the social and political activities of corporations. This article raises the question of the appropriate form of such governance structures. The examples above illustrate three possible ways of legitimising corporate quasi-public social and political activities: deliberation within the company, deliberation outside, and an approach we label corporate constitutionalism. While the first two models have been tested in practice and assessed in theory, the third one is comparatively more recent, both in practice and in theory. This article focuses on the latter model and asks whether corporate constitutionalism offers a suitable addition, or alternative, to deliberation (with or within firms) for legitimising corporate quasi-public social and political activities. It examines the respective merits of the three models and argues that a corporate constitutional court may mitigate some of the limits of deliberative practices alone. It argues the court is needed in weak regulatory environments, whether they are failing or inherently limited.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See https://bangladeshaccord.org/. Accessed on May 27th, 2021.

  2. For a presentation of different understandings of organisational legitimacy, pragmatic, epistemic, and moral, see Palazzo and Scherer (2006, pp. 72–73). This paper focuses on the third, normative, conception of legitimacy.

  3. The power to determine others’ rights and duties is not only that of states; it is that of private parties in the state of nature, and perhaps also in a post-Westphalian world order. This is what “corporate sovereigns” do absent state supervision (Cordelli, 2020, pp. 72–74). This is an account of political legitimacy in the Kantian tradition: it is when private parties coerce one another, that is, interfere with each other’s external freedom that the question of political legitimacy arises. “Legitimate authority starts from the question of how private parties may treat each other.” (Ripstein, 2004, p. 6).

  4. For a useful discussion of what counts normatively as a “public function”, see Cordelli (2020, pp. 25–29).

  5. The idea that real institutions should mirror an ideal situation of deliberation has been criticised as too idealistic. For example, deliberation might not be a second best under non-ideal conditions including power asymmetries (see Vandamme, 2021, pp. 121–124, for a discussion). Today Habermasians rather understand the related notion of the ideal speech situation as what is logically presupposed in deliberative exchanges aiming to reach mutual understanding; it is the “counterfactual presuppositions assumed by participants in argumentation” (Habermas, 1996, p. 323).

  6. The three expressions are used interchangeably in the remainder of the paper.

  7. Scherer et al. (2013) hint at the idea of additional seats on boards, a possibility that is discussed by Sabadoz and Singer (2018, p. 203). Chiara Cordelli offers the more developed idea of a “deliberative polyarchy” locating the democratic decision-making in “deliberative bodies” and/or a “board of directors”, and one additional citizen jury, in the spirit of this proposal (2020, p. 274–275).

  8. For a discussion of constitutionalism in the context of discussing workers’ rights, see Nien-he Hsieh (2005).

References

  • Bohman, J. (1998). Survey Article: The coming of age of deliberative democracy. Journal of Political Philosophy, 6, 400–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, J. (1999). Theories, practices, and pluralism a pragmatic interpretation of critical social science. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 29(4), 459–480.

  • Cordelli, C. (2012). The Institutional Division of Labor and the Egalitarian Obligations of Nonprofits. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20(2), 131–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordelli, C. (2020). The privatized state. Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Felicetti, A. (2018). A deliberative case for democracy in firms. Journal of Business Ethics, 150, 803–814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerlsbeck, F., & Herzog, L. (2020). The epistemic potentials of workplace democracy. Review of Social Economy, 78(3), 307–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghosh, E. (2010). Deliberative democracy and the countermajoritarian difficulty: Considering constitutional juries. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 30(2), 327–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. (2007). Enfranchising all affected interests, and its alternatives. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 35(1), 40–68.

  • Gutmann, A., & Thompson, D. (1996). Democracy and disagreement. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1996). Between facts and norms: Contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hsieh, N. (2005). Rawlsian justice and workplace republicanism. Social Theory and Practice, 31(1), 115–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hussain, W., & Moriarty, J. (2018). Accountable to whom? Rethinking the role of corporations in political CSR. Journal of Business Ethics, 149(3), 519–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, H. (2012). Why the many are smarter than the few and why it matters. Journal of Public Deliberation, 8(1). https://doi.org/10.16997/jdd.129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mansbridge, J., Bohman, J., Chambers, S., Christiano, T., Fung, A., Parkinson, J., …. Warren, M. (2012). A systemic approach to deliberative democracy. In: J. Parkinson & J. Mansbridge (Eds.), Deliberative systems: Deliberative democracy at the large scale (pp. 1–26). Cambridge University Press.

  • Matten, D., & Crane, A. (2005). Corporate citizenship: Toward an extended theoretical conceptualization. The Academy of Management Review, 30(1), 166–179.

  • Mena, S., & Palazzo, G. (2012). Input and Output Legitimacy of Multi-Stakeholder Initiatives. Business Ethics Quarterly, 22(3), 527–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moriarty, J. (2010). Participation in the Workplace: Are Employees Special?. Journal of Business Ethics, 92, 373–384.

  • Norman, W. (2011). Business ethics as self-regulation: Why principles that ground regulations should be used to ground beyond-compliance norms as well. Journal of Business Ethics, 102, 43–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oliver, C. (1996). The institutional embeddedness of economic activity. Advances in Strategic Management, 13, 163–186.

  • Palazzo, G., & Scherer, A. (2006). Corporate legitimacy as deliberation: A communicative framework. Journal of Business Ethics, 66, 71–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peter, F. (2017). Political Legitimacy. In: The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. E. N. Zalta (Ed.). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/legitimacy/

  • Ripstein, A. (2004). Authority and coercion. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 32(1), 2–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosanvallon, P. (2015). Le bon gouvernement. Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sabadoz, C., & Singer, A. (2017). Talk ain’t cheap: Political CSR and the challenges of corporate deliberation. Business Ethics Quarterly, 27(2), 183–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A., Baumann-Pauly, D., & Schneider, A. (2013). Democratizing corporate governance: Compensating for the democratic deficit of corporate political activity and corporate citizenship. Business & Society, 52(3), 473–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A., & Palazzo, G. (2007). Toward a political conception of corporate responsibility: Business and society seen from a Habermasian perspective. Academy of Management Review, 32(4), 1096–1120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, A., Palazzo, G., & Baumann, D. (2006). Global rules and private actors: Toward a new role of the transnational corporation in global governance. Business Ethics Quarterly, 16(4), 505–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, A. (2018). Justice failure: Efficiency and equality in business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 149(1), 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spector, H. (2003). Judicial review, rights, and democracy. Law and Philosophy, 22, 285–334.

  • Vandamme P.-E. (2016). La valeur épistémique de la démocratie, entre faits et normes. Revue philosophique de Louvain, 114(1), 125–126.

  • Vandamme, P. -É. (2020). What’s wrong with an epistocratic council? Politics, 40(1), 90–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vandamme, P. -É. (2021). Démocratie et justice sociale. Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waluchow, W. (2018). Constitutionalism. In: The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Zalta E. N. (Ed.). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/legitimacy/

  • Zurn, C. (2002). Deliberative democracy and constitutional review. Law and Philosophy, 21, 467–542.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zurn, C. (2011). Judicial review, constitutional juries and civic constitutional fora: Rights, democracy and law. Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory, 58(127), 63–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to the following people for comments and discussions offered on the arguments presented herein: Rutger Claassen, Chiara Cordelli, Auriane Lamine, Nicholas Vrousalis, Pierre-Etienne Vandamme, and especially my late colleague and friend Waheed Hussain who generously gave of his time to talk through the early arguments of this paper. I also wish to thank the participants of the Economic Ethics Network; the “Political theory of the corporation” MANCEPT Workshop; the EBEN France research seminar; the Mardis Intimes de la Chaire Hoover, Université Catholique de Louvain; the Society for Business Ethics Annual Meeting; and the members of the ANR project OSMosis. I am also grateful to the two anonymous referees of this journal for their very constructive comments and suggestions.

Funding

This work was supported by the French ANR project, “OSMOSIS” (project n°ANR-21-CE26-0024).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sandrine Blanc.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors have no relevant financial or non-financial interest to disclose.

Informed Consent

Not applicable.

Research Involving Human and/or Animal Participants

This research does not involve human participants nor animals.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Blanc, S. Deliberative Democracy and Corporate Constitutionalism: Considering Corporate Constitutional Courts. J Bus Ethics 188, 1–15 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-022-05206-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-022-05206-x

Keywords

Navigation