Skip to main content
Log in

Locke and “ad

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In IV, xvii, 19–22 of his Essay, Locke employs Latin labels for four kinds of argument, of which one (ad hominem) was already in circulation and one (ad judicium) has never had much currency. The present proposal seeks to locate and clarify what Locke was aiming to describe, and to contrast what he says with some subsequent uses that have been made of these labels as if they named fallacies. Though three of the four kinds of argument that Locke picks out are often less than decisive, he casts no aspersion on the legitimacy of their use in debate.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For instance, the only two references to Essay, IV, xvii in The Cambridge Companion to Locke (ed. Chappell 1994) are (on pp. 180 and 182) to the final, transitional §24, on questions of religious faith, with which we shall have nothing more to do. For all that it gave to the world a vocabulary that has a certain currency, the chapter is excised from some editions of the Essay (as cited by Hamblin in a note to his 1970, p. 159); nor is it included in the anthology The Locke Reader (ed. Yolton1977).

  2. Though the editors properly note that Locke himself does not use the word “fallacy” for these argument-types (p. 12) exactly the same passage of Locke that Hamblin quotes in full appears in Hansen and Pinto 1995, a very influential book collecting readings on fallacies (pp. 55–6).

  3. Aristotle’s Topics (I, 14, 105b19-29) comes to mind; but others might cite standard Stoic subdivisions as relayed by Diogenes Laertius (VII, 39–41). Even Kant allows in the first sentences of the “Preface” to the Grundlagen, that there is no need to improve on the scheme: Metaphysics-Ethics-Logic.

  4. As Aristotle puts it, “ouk syllogismos”, for instance at AnPr., I, iv, 26a8, 11–12, 32, and 37, 26b3, 10–11, and 17–18; v, 27a19, 27b3, 13, 23, and 36–7, vi, 28a32, 28b3-4, 22–3, 32, and 36–7, not to mention 29a9.

  5. Cf. van Eemeren (et al. 2002), on “the Validity rule” with a capital “v” (p. 132). In conversation with the author (December 2007), van Eemeren confirms that, by “validity”, he and his colleagues mean “deductive validity”.

  6. A curious sidelight: in the selection of Aubrey’s Brief Lives made by R. Barber for the Folio Society (1975), the life of Hooke is not included on the rather arbitrary grounds there is no extant portrait of him (and none can be found among the 55 illustrations in Bennett et al. 2003), a perhaps incidental social marker.

  7. They refer to the “ad verecundiam fallacy” only on p. 29 of their 2008, where it is understood as an improper blocking off of questions.

  8. Places where Locke does appear by name include (Watts 1725) pp. 112, 179 and 326.

  9. A little further on in the same passage, Watts contrasts “human Faith” with “divine Faith” (p. 312), each being a species of which faith is the genus.

  10. A certain folklore would have it that the book was published the very same day as the work by De Morgan’s friend George Boole on the Mathematical Analysis of Logic, one of the first logic books not to include any discussion of fallacies, perhaps because Boole believed that all valid arguments could be expressed with his formalism so that any that cannot are just beyond the pale.

  11. I withold reference to the source so as not to besmirch the memory of the author.

  12. This is a point brought to my attention by one of the readers for this journal for which I am particularly grateful.

References

  • Arnauld, A. and Nicole, P. (1683) La logique ou L’art de penser, 5th ed., presented by L. Marin, Paris, Flammarion 1970.

  • Augustus, De Morgan. (1847) Formal logic or the calculus of inference necessary and probable. London: Taylor and Walton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J., M. Cooper, M. Hunter, and L. Jardine. (2003) London’s Leonardo—the life and work of Robert Hooke. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boole, George. (1847) The mathematical analysis of logic, anastatic reprint Oxford, Basil Blackwell 1963.

  • Bradley, F.H. (1897) Appearance and reality, 2nd ed. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavendish, Margaret. (1668) The description of a new world, called the blazing world. London: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chappell, Vere, ed. 1994. The Cambridge companion to Locke. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, E. (1995) There is no fallacy of arguing from authority. Informal Logic 17: 365–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, Franca. (2010) Verità avvelenata. Milan: Bollati Boringhieri.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, Richard. (2021) Le fonti dell’argomentazione. Rome: Dino Audino Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, Richard. (2020) ‘In defence of a fallacy’ Studia Semiotyczne (Warsaw) XXXIV, 2, pp. 25–42.

  • Descartes, René. (1637) Discours de la Méthode, in vol. VI of C. Adam, and P. Tannery, (eds) Œuvres de Descartes (12 vols) (originally Paris, Léopold Cerf, 1897 - 1913) with corrections and additions by J. Beaude and P. Costabel (et al.), Paris, Vrin, 1964–76.

  • Finocchiaro, Maurice. (1974) “The concept of Ad Hominem argument in Galileo and Locke, reprinted in his Arguments about Arguments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2005: 329–339.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei, Galileo (1890–1909) Opere (Edizione nazionale, 20 vols) eds. I Del Lungo and A. Favaro, Florence, Barbèra.

  • Goodwin, Jean. (1998) “Forms of authority and the real Argumentum ad Verecundiam” In OSSA conference archive, 41: 1-13

  • Gotti, Maurizio. (1996) Robert Boyle and the language of science. Milan: Guerini.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. (1975) The emergence of probability. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C.L. (1970) Fallacies. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, H., and R.C. Pinto, eds. (1995) Fallacies: classical and contemporary readings. Pennsylvania State University Press: University Park PA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansen, H. (2020) “Fallacies”, In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/fallacies/.

  • Hitchcock, David. (2006) “Why there is no argumentum ad hominem fallacy” at www.humanities.mcmaster.ca/~hitchkd/.

  • Krabbe, E.C.W. (1995) Appeal to Ignorance. In Fallacies: Classical and Contemporary Readings, ed. H. Hansen and R.C. Pinto, 251–264. Pennsylvania State University Press: University Park PA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. (1689) An Essay concerning human[e] understanding, ed. P.H. Nidditch, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1975.

  • Longaker, M.G. (2014) John Locke’s practice of argumentation. Informal Logic 34 (4): 364–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petrus Hispanus. (c.1230) Summule logicales, ed. L.M. de Rijk, under the title Tractatus van Gorcum, Assen 1972.

  • van Eemeren, F.H. and Grootendoorst, R. (2002), Argumentation: analysis, evaluation, presentation, Mahwah NJ, Lawrence Erlbaum.

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendoorst. (2015) The history of the argumentum ad hominem since the seventeenth century. In Reasonableness and effectiveness in argumentative discourse, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, 611–629. Cham (CH): Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., B. Garssen, E.C.W. Krabbe, A.F. Snoek Henkemans, B. Vehej, and J.M.H. Wagemans. (2014) Handbook of argumentation theory. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Varzi, Achille, et al. (1998) Theory and problems of logic, 2nd ed. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., C. Reed, and F. Macagno. (2008) Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Watts, Isaac. (1725) Logick: or the right use of reason in the inquiry after truth, references to the sixth edition. London: Ford and Hent, 1736.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whately, Richard. (1817) “Logic” In E. Smedley, H.J. Rose eds. Encyclopædia Metropolitana, London, B. Fellowes, Vol. I, pp. 193–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whately, Richard. (1826) Elements of logic. London: W. Clowes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (2007) Lightening up on the Ad Hominem. Informal Logic 27: 109–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yolton, J.W., ed. (1977) The Locke reader. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Richard Davies.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author did not receive support from any organization for the submitted work, and has no financial or non-financial interests to declare.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Davies, R. Locke and “ad”. Argumentation 37, 473–492 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-023-09594-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-023-09594-w

Keywords

Navigation