Skip to main content
Log in

Śātarak\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}\)ita on the fallacies of personalistic vitalism

  • Published:
Journal of Indian Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Conclusions

What was the fate of personalistic vitalism in later Indian thought? That question is too large to be considered here, but it is certain that the doctrine did reemerge, and has remained influential. Nonetheless, there is some reason to believe that Śātarak\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}\)ita critique of personalistic vitalism did have an immediate impact on philosophers within the Nyāya tradition: Vācaspatimiśra, Uddyotakara's sub-commentator, whom we know to have been familiar with Śātarak\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}\)ita Tattvasa\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{m}\)graha simply passes over Uddyotakara's already equivocal argument without making any effort to defend it. Certainly, he had concluded that Uddyotakara's weak assertion of personalistic vitalism was either not important, or else a lost cause. Is it too much to suppose that he might have let himself be convinced, in this case, by a Buddhist?

The ancient debate between ātmavādin and anātmavādin was at the heart of a conflict between opposing systems of salvation. To construe this, however, in accordance with our contemporary categorical schemes involves a fundamental error, for “systems of salvation” in ancient India were concerned with human nature and the human world, in a rich and full sense. What I have tried to indicate here is that one strand of the debate in question can be isolated and shown to involve progressive developments in the conceptual analysis of a basic biological doctrine. Other strands that might similarly be analyzed bear upon the theories of agency and causation, and rational and empirical psychology. To study these and many other topics in classical Indian thought from the perspective here advocated does not require our losing sight of the essential religious interests which motivated and informed the Indian discussions with which we are concerned; what it does require is an involvement in the history of ideas quite broadly conceived. In this context we should recall that it is now possible to treat much of classical Indian thought from a truly historical, and not merely doxographical, vantage-point. By focusing less upon belief and doctrine within single systems, and more upon the dynamic tension that arose where competing systems came into conflict, we discover that there was indeed historical progress, and that it is characterized in part by the application of methodological refinements in the areas of logic and epistemology to problems that had been defined in antiquity. This sounds very much like the history of philosophy in other settings; what must be done is to fill in the details with respect to the splendid array of questions which Indian thinkers posed and the answers about which they argued.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Bibliography of Sanskrit texts cited

  • Ak\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}\)apāda (Gautama), Nyāyasūtra, in Nyāyadarśanam, 2 vols. (Kyoto: Rinsen Book Company, 1984).

  • Kamalaśīla, Tattvasa\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{m}\)grahapañjika, in Śātarak\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}\)ita, Tattvasa\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{m}\)graha, q.v.

  • Ka\( \underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{n}\)āda (Ulūka), Vaiśe\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}\)ikasūtra, in Śrī Nārāya\( \underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{n}\)a Miśra, ed., Vaiūe\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}\)ikasśtropaskāra\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{h}\), Kashi Sanskrit Series 195 (Varanasi: Chowkhamba, 1969).

  • Praśastapāda, 59–14, ed. Durgādhara Jhā (Varanasi: Sampurnanand Sanskrit Vishvavidyalaya, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  • Vasubandhu, Abhidharmakoūa, ed. Swami Dwarikadas Shastri, 2 vols. (Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati, 1982). Reprint of 1968 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Śrīdhara, Nyāyakandalīvyākhyā, in Praśastāpāda, Praśastāpādabhā\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}\)ya, q.v.

  • Uddyotakara, Nyāyavārttika, in Nyāyadarśanam, above (see Ak\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}\)apāda).

  • Vācaspatimiśra, Nyāyatātparya\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{t}\)ikā, in Nyāyadarśanam.

  • Vasubandhu, Abhidharmakośa, ed. Swami Dwarikadas Shastri, 2 vols. (Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati, 1981). Reprint of 1970–73 edition, which appeared in 4 vols.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kapstein, M. Śātarak\(\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle\cdot}$}}{s}\)ita on the fallacies of personalistic vitalism. J Indian Philos 17, 43–59 (1989). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00160138

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00160138

Keywords

Navigation