Skip to main content

Types, Meanings and Co-composition in Lexical Semantics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Modern Perspectives in Type-Theoretical Semantics

Part of the book series: Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy ((SLAP,volume 98))

  • 389 Accesses

Abstract

This paper investigates co-composition, the composition of a predicate and its arguments in which either the predicate, the arguments, or both shift their meaning. We study the implications of this phenomenon for type-theoretic approaches to semantics. We adduce evidence from distributional methods in lexical semantics that co-composition is widespread and then argue that a proper treatment leads to a reconsideration of the basics of type theory for natural language semantics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 89.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Asher (2011) and many other approaches—e.g.,  (Kamp et al. 1995; Partee 2010)—adopt this view for adjectives and modifiers.

  2. 2.

    E.g., using the cosine measure, which computes the angle between two vectors.

  3. 3.

    One of the syntactic features of the word apple might e.g. be eat \(_{\mathrm {dobj}}\), since apple appears as a direct object of the verb eat. Note that these syntactic contexts – also called dependency features – are generally automatically extracted using a dependency-based grammatical parser.

  4. 4.

    Asher (2011) argues for this thesis in detail.

  5. 5.

    Some cases are much less obvious, however. Consider capital vs. cultural capital. Cultural does not seem to be subsective, but it gives some sort of modal frame—within the cultural worlds of that frame, X is the capital of the country or...

  6. 6.

    Partee (2010) also advocates something like this view, though the details are quite different from those of the approach developed here.

  7. 7.

    For more discussion see Bride et al. (2014, 2015).

  8. 8.

    For a fuller discussion of MTTs view of common nouns as types, see (Chatzikyriakidis and Luo 2016).

  9. 9.

    Chatzikyriakidis and Luo (2016) use polymorphic types to fix this problem, in contrast to earlier work in MTT, to which we refer here.

  10. 10.

    This is a term that linguists use for “at issue” content in contrast to presupposed content which is backgrounded and functions differently in composition.

  11. 11.

    We used singular value decomposition because of its guarantee to provide the best possible fit for the original data given a limited number of dimensions. The top dimensions are thus guaranteed to explain the most variance present in the original data.

  12. 12.

    There’s another dimension of variation as well. Change the corpus and you get a different set of types, or a different type for each word.

  13. 13.

    For details on this idea, see Asher et al. (2016).

References

  • Asher, N. (2011). Lexical meaning in context: A web of words. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N. (2015). Types, meanings and coercions in lexical semantics. Lingua, 157, 66–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., & Luo, Z. (2012). Formalization of coecions in lexical semantics. In E. Chemla (Ed.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Asher, N., Van de Cruys, T., Bride, A., & Abrusán, M. Integrating type theory and distributional semantics: A case study on adjective-noun compositions. Computational Linguistics, in press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baroni, M., & Zamparelli, R. (2010). Nouns are vectors, adjectives are matrices: Representing adjective-noun constructions in semantic space. In Proceedings of the 2010 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing, October 2010 (pp. 1183–1193). Cambridge: Association for Computational Linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1998). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bride, A., van de Cruys, T., & Asher, N. (2014). Une évaluation approfondie de différentes méthodes de compositionalité sémantique. In Proceedings of TALN 2014 (pp. 36–44), Marseille.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bride, A., van de Cruys, T., & Asher, N. (2015). A generalisation of lexical functions for composition in distributional semantics. In Proceedings of the 53rd Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics and the 7th International Joint Conference on Natural Language Processing, July 2015, (Vol.1: Long Papers) (pp. 281–291), Beijing, China: Association for Computational Linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chatzikyriakidis, S., & Luo, Z. (2016). On the interpretation of common nouns: Types versus predicates. In this volume.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coecke, B., Sadrzadeh, M., & Clark, S. (2011). Mathematical foundations for a compositional distributional model of meaning. Linguistic Analysis: A Festschrift for Joachim Lambek, 36(1–4), 345–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dinu, G., & Lapata, M. (2010). Measuring distributional similarity in context. In Proceedings of the 2010 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing (pp. 1162–1172). Association for Computational Linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1993). The seas of language. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egg, M. (2003). Beginning novels and finishing hamburgers: Remarks on the semantics of to begin. Journal of Semantics, 20, 163–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1988). Revisions of knowledge systems using epistemic entrenchment. In Moshe Y. Vardi, (Ed.), Proceedings of the Second Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning about Knowledge (pp. 83–95), San Francisco: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geffet, M., & Dagan, I. (2005). The distributional inclusion hypotheses and lexical entailment. In Proceedings of the 43rd Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics (ACL’05), June 2005 (pp. 107–114), Ann Arbor, Michigan: Association for Computational Linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johannes, D. (2003). Flexibility in adverbal modification: Reinterpretation as contextual enrichment. In E. Lang, C. Maienborn, & C. Fabricius-Hansen (Eds.), Modifying Adjuncts (pp. 511–552). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H., & Partee, B. (1995). Prototype theory and compositionality. Cognition, 57, 129–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (2010). Type-theoretical semantics with coercive subtyping. SALT20, Vancouver.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (2011). Contextual analysis of word meanings in type-theoretical semantics. LACL’11, LNAI. Vol. 6736.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luo, Z. (2012). Formal semantics in modern type theories with coercive subtyping. Linguistics and Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magidor, O. (2013). Category Mistakes. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, J., & Lapata, M. (2008). Vector-based models of semantic composition. In Proceedings of ACL-08: HLT, Ohio, June 2008, (pp. 236–244), Columbus: Association for Computational Linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, J. (1983). Coercion and type inference. In Proceedings of Tenth Annual Symposium on Principles of Programming Languages (POPL).

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. (2010). Privative adjectives: Subsective plus coercion. In R. Bäuerle, & T. Zimmerman (Eds.), Presuppositions and Discourse: Essays Offered to Hans Kamp (pp. 273–285). Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B., & Rooth, M. (1983). Generalised conjunction and type ambiguity. In R. Bauerle, C. Schwarze, & V. Stechow (Eds.), Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pulman, S. (1997). Aspectual shift as type coercion. Transactions of the Philological Society, 52(2).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1995). The Generative Lexicon. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turney, P., & Pantel, P. (2010). From frequency to meaning: Vector space models of semantics. Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research, 37(1), 141–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van de Cruys, T., Poibeau, T., & Korhonen, A. (2011). Latent vector weighting for word meaning in context. In Proceedings of the 2011 Conference on Empirical Methods in Natural Language Processing, July 2011 (pp. 1012–1022), Edinburgh, Scotland, UK: Association for Computational Linguistics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell’s.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicholas Asher .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Asher, N., Abrusan, M., Van de Cruys, T. (2017). Types, Meanings and Co-composition in Lexical Semantics. In: Chatzikyriakidis, S., Luo, Z. (eds) Modern Perspectives in Type-Theoretical Semantics. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol 98. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50422-3_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50422-3_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-50420-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-50422-3

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics