Skip to main content

Parrhesia, Bad Faith and Accounting for Oneself

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Being a Teacher

Abstract

In this chapter, I aim to reconceptualise the basis for trusting accounts, proposing a move away from trust based on ‘absolute accuracy’ to a trust encapsulated in the practice of parrhesia. On the surface, parrhesia appears to be the opposite of Sartre’s concept of ‘bad faith’. Paradoxically, however, our attempts to be sincere in our accounts are inevitably tainted by bad faith. This tension is especially evident in autobiographical writing, as explored here through Sartre’s own autobiography, Words. The existence of these tensions does not mean that we should abandon trust in these accounts, however. Rather, parrhesiastic practices in autobiographical writing can offer a different understanding of how we account for ourselves and our practices, one that does not pertain to a narrow definition of truth as accuracy, but instead leads to a form of self-criticism where one situates oneself in relation to the ‘truth’ of their accounts in new ways. Towards the end of the chapter, I explore three ‘parrhesiastic techniques’ and their relationship to accounting for oneself as a teacher, to reimagine these techniques from technicist to existential ways of relating to our practices, a distinction more fully examined in the final chapter.

This chapter has also been published as: Brady, A. (2021). Accounting for Oneself in Teaching: Trust, Parrhesia and Bad Faith, Studies in Philosophy of Education, 41, pp. 273–286. CC-BY 4.0

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    These contrasting ideas of trust are explored widely in the epistemology of testimony which, due to space limitations, is not discussed here. For a start, see Lackey and Sosa (2006).

  2. 2.

    In Truth and Existence, Sartre (1995) clarifies his position against those who argue that his view makes a ‘common world’ impossible, given that, for him, my relation with others is always in conflict. In turn, this allows Sartre to accept an intersubjective understanding of truth and meaning. Catalano (2007) has attempted to summarise this position on truth, where he argues that, for Sartre, truth is (always) a relation between for-itself and all of human reality – it is ‘what happens to reality when it encounters human existence’ (Catalano, 2007, p. 49). Since all human reality is constituted by ‘social facts’, such facts are also truth, and not simply what we call ‘brute’ facts (See, for example: Sartre, 1973).

  3. 3.

    In fact, Foucault never quite denied this agency, but merely shifted his emphasis in his later years. Unlike Sartre, who later claimed that all power is ‘evil’, Foucault sees power as a given – neither good nor bad, existing across all relations and not simply in relations between individuals and institutions. For a more thorough examination of this, see Foucault (1987).

  4. 4.

    Some accuse the later Foucault of not recognising intersubjectivity in the formation of subjects, and since such self-indulgence is insufficient in dismantling power relations, it is also depoliticising. According to Wong (2013), however, such criticisms represent a misunderstanding of what Foucault means by ‘ontological priority’.

  5. 5.

    Although Wong (2013) disagrees with this assertion.

  6. 6.

    For Vlieghe and Zamojski (2019), this care for the ‘something’ in education is ontologically prior to the care for others in the educational context, a care that is equated with care for oneself as a teacher (where the ‘object’ of teaching is not distinct from the ‘teaching self’), something that they accuse certain thinkers of missing out on – e.g. Biesta (e.g. 2017) in his relational view of teaching. Bonnett (2010) also makes a similar argument.

  7. 7.

    Of course, truth can be understood in different ways – or, at least, it has different stakes depending on the context. The ‘medicalisation of madness’, for instance, purports a ‘truth’ in order to normalise behaviour. Truth in the field of mathematics arguably does not serve the same function, or at least is circumscribed by a very different truth-power relation. See Foucault (1987, 2006)

  8. 8.

    Rhetorical devices are also used by Socrates, as well as Beauvoir, Kierkegaard and Nietzsche, but with a different purpose in mind – they encourage rather than neutralise debate, forcing individuals to take up a relation to truth.

  9. 9.

    Foucault uses the example of a mathematics teacher teaching a theorem to children. The teacher knows that what he is teaching is the truth. There is no real risk in him teaching this concept to the children, and it is therefore not a parrhesiastic form of truth. Of course, there are examples that show that speaking certain (e.g. scientific) truths does require courage, where doing so involves a threat to one’s life. Hence, the separation of Cartesian truths and truth in a parrhesiastic sense is not absolute. If speaking scientific truths involves risk and courage, one is also practising a form of parrhesia, since this involves a form of commitment to the value of the truth where there is something at stake.

  10. 10.

    A discussion on this can be found in Hodgson (2010). For the purposes of this paper, I will focus primarily on the personal sense of parrhesia as a form of reflexive self-criticism rather than on the political sense – although, notably in the case of Socrates, these two are not wholly separate.

  11. 11.

    Rather than resolving these dichotomies, Sartre attempts to maintain an ambiguous tension between both, as indicated in one revealing section: ‘When I was in a good mood, everything came from myself… an obedient child, I would obey until I died, but I would obey myself. When I was depressed and aware of the sickening feebleness of my availability, I was able to soothe myself only by forcing it on predestination… I was merely the product of collective demand. Most of the time, I achieved peace of mind by taking care never to exclude altogether either the freedom which exalts or the necessity which justifies.’ (Sartre, 2000, p. 109)

References

  • Ball, S. J. (2003). The teacher’s soul and the terrors of performativity. Journal of Education Policy, 18(2), 215–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ball, S. J. (2016). Foucault as educator. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ball, S. J. (2019). A horizon of freedom: Using Foucault to think differently about education and learning. Power and Education, 11(2), 132–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biesta, G. J. J. (2014). The beautiful risk of education. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biesta, G. J. J. (2017). The rediscovery of teaching. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bonnett, M. (2010). Schools as places of unselving: An educational pathology? In G. Dall’Alba (Ed.), Exploring education through phenomenology. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borges, J. L. (2000). Fiction. Penguin Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brady, A. M. (2020). Response and responsibility: Rethinking accountability in education. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 55, 25–40. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9752.12501

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brady, A. (2021). Accounting for oneself in teaching: Trust, parrhesia and bad faith. Studies in Philosophy of Education, 41, 273–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (2005). Giving an account of oneself. Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camus, A. (2005). The myth of Sisyphus and other essays. Penguin Classics. Originally published in 1942.

    Google Scholar 

  • Catalano, J. S. (1996). Good faith and other essays: Perspectives on a Sartrean ethics. Rowman and Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Catalano, J. S. (2007). The meaning and truth of history: A note on Sartre’s critique of dialectical reasoning. Sartre Studies International, 13(2), 47–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fell, J. (1968). Sartre’s words: An existential self-analysis. The Psychoanalytic Review, 55(3), 426–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flynn, T. R. (2004). Sartre and Foucault: A cross-generational exchange. Sartre Studies International, 10(2), 47–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1987). The ethic of care for the self as a practice of freedom: An interview with Michel Foucault on January 20th, 1984. Conducted by R. Fornet-Betancourt, H. Becker & A. Gomez-Müller; S. J. J. D. Gauthier, Trans. SAGE Publishing Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1990a). The history of sexuality: Vol 1: An introduction. Penguin Books. Originally published in 1976a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1990b). The history of sexuality: Vol 2: The use of pleasure. Vintage Books. Originally published in 1976b.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1991). Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison. Penguin Books. Originally published in 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (2001). Fearless speech (J. Pearson, Ed.). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (2005). The hermeneutics of the subject (lectures at the Collège de France 1981–1982). Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (2006). Madness and civilisation. Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillam, C. (2013). Sartre in dialogue with Foucault: Towards a post-existentialism. Political Studies Association conference, Cardiff [online]. Available at: https://www.psa.ac.uk/sites/default/files/965_486.pdf. Accessed 14 May 2020.

  • Hattam, R., & Baker, B. (2016). Technologies of self and the cultivation of virtues. In O. Ergas & S. Todd (Eds.), Philosophy east/west: Exploring intersections between educational and contemplative practices. Wiley Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, N. (2010). Voicing the self: Foucault, Cavell, and an ethics of citizenship. In Happiness and personal growth: Dialogue between philosophy, psychology, and comparative education. Kyoto University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hogan, P. (2009). The new significance of learning: imagination’s heartwork. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lackey, J., & Sosa, E. (Eds.). (2006). The epistemology of testimony. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leask, I. (2011). Beyond subjection: Notes on the later Foucault and education. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 44(1), 57–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mooney Simmie, G., & Moles, J. (2020). Teachers’ changing subjectivities: Putting the soul at work for the principles of the market or for facilitating risk? Studies in Philosophy and Education, 39, 383–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paolantonio, M. D. (2019). The malaise of the soul at work: The drive for creativity, self-actualization, and curiosity in education. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 38, 601–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papadimos, T. J., Manos, J. E., & Murray, S. J. (2013). An extrapolation of Foucault’s technologies of the self to effect positive transformation in the intensivist as teacher and mentor. Philosophy, Ethics and Humanities in Medicine, 8(7), 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perryman, J., Maguire, M., Braun, A., & Ball, S. (2018). Surveillance, governmentality and moving the goalposts: The influence of Ofsted on the work of schools in a post-panoptic era. British Journal of Educational Studies, 66(2), 145–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Santoni, R. E. (1995). Bad faith, good faith, and authenticity in Sartre’s early philosophy. Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (1973). Search for a method. Random House Inc. Originally published in 1957

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (1995). Truth and existence. University of Chicago Press. Originally published in 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (2000) Les mots, or “words” (I. Clephane, Trans.). Penguin Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (2004). Critique of dialectical reasoning: Volume 1. Verso Books. Originally published in 1960a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (2006). Critique of dialectical reasoning: Volume 2. Verso Books. Originally published in 1960b.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (2008). Between existentialism and Marxism. Verso Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J. P. (2018). Being and nothingness: An essay on phenomenological ontology (S. Richmond, Trans.). Blackwell Publishers Ltd. Originally published in 1943.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seitz, B. (2004). Sartre, Foucault and the subject of philosophy’s situation. Sartre Studies International, 10(2), 92–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, S. (2016). Facing uncertainty in education: Beyond the harmonies of Eurovision education. European Educational Research Journal, 15(6), 619–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vlieghe, J., & Zamojski, P. (2019). Towards an ontology of teaching: Thing-centred pedagogy, affirmation and love for the world. Wiley.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • White, R. (2014). Foucault on the care of the self as an ethical project and a spiritual goal. Human Studies, 37, 489–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitmore, J. J. (2006). The double-writing of “les mots”: Sartre’s “words” as performative philosophy. Sartre Studies International, 12(2), 61–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wong, J. (2013). Self and others: The work of ‘care’ in Foucault’s care of the self. Philosophy Faculty Publications, 6, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Singapore Pte Ltd.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Brady, A.M. (2022). Parrhesia, Bad Faith and Accounting for Oneself. In: Being a Teacher. Contemporary Philosophies and Theories in Education, vol 19. Springer, Singapore. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-19-7323-9_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-19-7323-9_8

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Singapore

  • Print ISBN: 978-981-19-7322-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-981-19-7323-9

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics