Encyclopedia of Educational Philosophy and Theory

2017 Edition
| Editors: Michael A. Peters

Cavell and Philosophy of Education

  • Michael A. Peters
Reference work entry
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-981-287-588-4_297

Introduction

Stanley Cavell is an American philosopher who, following Wittgenstein, teaches us how to read Wittgenstein and practice philosophy in post-analytic philosophy (Mulhall 1994). He speaks directly to philosophers of education through his treatment of the figure of the child and “the scene of instruction” in Wittgenstein’s (1972) Philosophical Investigations, addressing “the education of grown ups” (Saito and Standish 2012) and in works like Themes Out of School (Cavell 1988).

Stanley Cavell is an American philosopher, who with others like Richard Rorty – though in very different ways – has deliberately attempted to heal the epistemological rupture in the tradition of American public thought caused by a Viennese analytic strain of philosophy. Cavell has done so by returning to the origins of American philosophy represented in Emerson’s transcendentalism and Thoreau’s “Walden” (see Cavell 1981a, 1981b, 1989, 1990, 1994). On this reading the American intellectual tradition was...

This is a preview of subscription content, log in to check access.

References

  1. Borradori, G. (1994). The American philosopher (trans: Crocitto, R.). Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  2. Cavell, S. (1969). Must we mean what we say? A book of essays. New York: Scribner.Google Scholar
  3. Cavell, S. (1977). The world viewed: Reflections on the ontology of film. New York: Peguin.Google Scholar
  4. Cavell, S. (1979). The claim of reason: Wittgenstein, skepticism, morality and tragedy. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  5. Cavell, S. (1981a). Pursuits of happiness: The Hollywood comedy of remarriage. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Cavell, S. (1981b). Senses of Walden. San Francisco: North Point Press.Google Scholar
  7. Cavell, S. (1987a). Disowning knowledge: In six plays of Shakespeare. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Cavell, S. (1987b). Change work. In J. H. Smith & W. Kerrigan (Eds.), Images in our souls: Cavell, psychoanalysis, and cinema. Baltimore: John Hopkins Press.Google Scholar
  9. Cavell, S. (1988a). In quest of the ordinary: Lines of skepticism and Romanticism. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Cavell, S. (1988b). Out of school: Effects and causes. Chicago: Chicago University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Cavell, S. (1989). This new yet unapproachable America: Lectures after Emerson, after Wittgenstein. Albuquerque: Living Batch Press.Google Scholar
  12. Cavell, S. (1990). Conditions handsome and unhandsome: The constitution of Emersonian perfectionism. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Cavell, S. (1994). Pitch of philosophy: Autobiographical exercises. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Cavell, S. (1995a). Philosophical passages: Wittgenstein, Emerson, Austin, Derrida. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  15. Cavell, S. (1995b). Notes and afterthoughts on the opening of Wittgenstein’s investigations. In Philosophical passages: Wittgenstein, Emerson, Austin, Derrida (pp. 124–186). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  16. Cavell, S. (1996a). Psychoanalysis and cinema: moments of letter from an unknown woman (pp. 81–113).Google Scholar
  17. Cavell, S. (1996b). In S. Mulhall (Ed.), The Cavell reader. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  18. Cavell, S. (1996c). Epilogue: The investigations’ everyday aesthetics of itself. In S. Mulhall (Ed.), The Cavell reader (pp. 369–389). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  19. Fischer, M. (1989). Stanley Cavell and literary criticism. Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  20. Mulhall, S. (1994). Stanley Cavell: Philosophy’s recounting of the ordinary. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  21. Payne, M. (1995). Introduction. In S. Cavell’s (Ed.), Philosophical passages: Wittgenstein, Emerson, Austin, Derrida (pp. 1–11). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  22. Peters, M. (1999, March). Deranging the investigations: Cavell on the figure of the child. Paper presented to a symposium on the work of Stanley Cavell, Philosophy of Education (PES), Annual Conference, New Orleans.Google Scholar
  23. Peters, M., & Marshall, J. (1999). Wittgenstein: Philosophy, postmodernism, pedagogy. Westport/London: Bergin and Garvey.Google Scholar
  24. Rorty, R. (1991). Philosophy as a kind of writing. In Essays on Heidegger and others. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Saito, N. & Standish, P. (2012). Stanley Cavell and the Education of Grown Ups. NY: Fordham University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Sluga, H. (1998). What has history to do with me? Wittgenstein and analytic philosophy. Inquiry, 41, 99–121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Wittgenstein, L. (1972). Philosophical investigations (trans: Anscombe, G. E. M.). Oxford: Blackwell, (Reprint of English Text with index). [First Edition 1953].Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Singapore 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of WaikatoHamiltonNew Zealand