Skip to main content

Philosophy of Religion in Australasia

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
History of Philosophy in Australia and New Zealand

Abstract

The first section surveys Australian philosophy of religion, putting greater emphasis on the more distinctively Australian contributions, without any implication that it is good for there to be distinctively Australian contributions. It also exhibits connections between the philosophy of religion and Australian contributions to other areas of philosophy. The second section surveys philosophy of religion in New Zealand.

Peter Forrest is the author of the section ‘Philosophy of Religion in Australia’ and John Bishop and Ken Perszyk are the authors of the section ‘Philosophy of Religion in New Zealand’.

Many thanks to Nick Trakakis for his helpful editorial comments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 549.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For an alternative account of Australian philosophy of religion before about 1980, see Grave (1984).

  2. 2.

    See, for instance, Lamb and Barnes (2003). I also note Australian process theology. In addition, it should be recalled that there is a strong tradition of teaching philosophy in seminaries, especially Catholic ones (see Franklin 2006).

  3. 3.

    Yet again, there is work of a somewhat poetic kind such as that of Anthony Palma (1986, 1988).

  4. 4.

    For some further remarks on Platonist and other interpretations of the Dreaming, see Charlesworth’s introduction to Charlesworth et al. (2005).

  5. 5.

    ‘Concupiscence’ is the tendency to satisfy your appetites even when it is contrary to reason to do so, as it might be to eat the whole cake. ‘Concupittance’, coined in honour of the theologian Don Cupitt, is the desire, contrary to reason, to eat the whole cake and still have a slice or two.

  6. 6.

    See, however, Duff-Forbes (1961) for some criticisms of various defences of religious language from the charge of unfalsifiability.

  7. 7.

    Evils X and Y are incommensurable if it is neither the case that X is worse than Y nor that Y is worse than X nor that X and Y are equal. While equality is transitive, incommensurability is not. Here is an example of incommensurable evils adapted from Bernard Williams’ story of Jim and the Indians. The police chief first offers Jim a choice between killing two Indians or himself shooting all ten. When Jim hesitates, the police chief ‘generously’ offers him the choice between killing just one Indian or himself shooting all ten. When Jim still hesitates, the police chief berates him for irrationality on the grounds that if his dislike of killing two Indians is roughly equal to his dislike of allowing ten to be killed, then, surely, his dislike of killing just one must be significantly less than his dislike of allowing ten to be killed. I judge, and invite readers to judge, that Jim is not irrational and that this is an example of incommensurable evils.

  8. 8.

    Types of act should be characterised in a language without proper names, and a type of act performed by an agent x should have x and only x as a free variable.

  9. 9.

    See, for instance, Grim (1983, 1985, 2000).

  10. 10.

    Further discussion of whether God would create the best of all possible worlds is to be found in Levine (1996) and Nagasawa and Brown (2005b c).

  11. 11.

    Although a defender of pantheism, Levine resists the thesis that standard theism collapses into pantheism (Levine 1984).

  12. 12.

    Worth noting is the Intelligent Design conference, held at the Australian Catholic University in 2006.

  13. 13.

    A further contribution: Nagasawa (2007a) has defended the ontological argument against Millikan’s criticism that existence is not a perfection.

  14. 14.

    Although Oppy’s (1995b) work on the ontological argument makes (accurate) claims about its comprehensiveness, he explicitly notes in his Arguing about Gods (Oppy 2007) the difficulty of a similarly exhaustive survey of cosmological and teleological arguments.

  15. 15.

    These conferences arose out of an occasional series that dates back to a ‘Christianity and Platonism’ conference in Melbourne in 1977.

  16. 16.

    Andrew Dole and Andrew Chignell have recently identified Flew and MacIntyre’s edited collection (1955) as a ‘transitional document’ beginning a movement towards ‘lines of inquiry that had been blocked by the positivists’ (2005: 7–8). For an account of why the resurgence of interest in philosophy of religion in recent decades occurred within the analytical—and not Continental—tradition, see Wolterstorff (2009).

  17. 17.

    For the explanation of their choice of the term ‘Philosophical Theology’, see Flew and MacIntyre’s (1955) preface, viii.

  18. 18.

    For an influential defence of the right of Christian philosophers to philosophise from Christian presuppositions, see Alvin Plantinga’s 1983 inaugural lecture ‘Advice to Christian Philosophers’ in Plantinga (1984).

  19. 19.

    Mary Prior reports (personal communication to Max Cresswell) that the problem of free will and divine omniscience was ‘in the air’ in their discussions, and it may be that Prior’s initial interest in the logic of time was motivated by an interest in formalising theological arguments on this topic. That Prior had deep theological interests is, anyway, clear from his earlier published writings. Mike Grimshaw remarks that ‘if Prior the man is to be understood, then we need to look at his early published work which locates him as potentially one of New Zealand’s greatest theologians – if he had chosen that route of study’ (2002: 480).

  20. 20.

    Findlay’s paper was originally published after he went to King’s College, London; Hughes’ reply was originally published before he arrived in Wellington.

  21. 21.

    Mackie’s (1955) article and Flew’s (1955) article set a framework for contemporary discussion of the Argument from Evil in the philosophy of religion.

  22. 22.

    For an account of Geering’s work and career, see Paul Morris’ introduction to The Lloyd Geering Reader (2008).

  23. 23.

    Note, however, John Owens’ (2004) critique of a common interpretation of the Wittgensteinianism of D. Z. Phillips.

  24. 24.

    This kind of response to Richard Dawkins (2006) is exemplified by Terry Eagleton (2009).

  25. 25.

    Perszyk’s (2011) edited collection on Molinism grew out of this workshop.

  26. 26.

    In Bradley’s own words: ‘God himself drowned the whole human race except Noah and his family [Gen. 7:23]; he punished King David for carrying out a census that he himself had ordered and then complied with David’s request that others be punished instead of him by sending a plague to kill 70,000 people [II Sam. 24:1–15]; and he commanded Joshua to kill old and young, little children, maidens and women (the inhabitants of some 31 kingdoms) while pursuing his genocidal practices of ethnic cleansing in the lands that orthodox Jews still regard as part of Greater Israel [see Josh., chapter 10 in particular]’. See also Michael Tooley’s remarks on revealed religions and the argument from evil (in Plantinga and Tooley 2008: 73–76) and Lewis (2007).

  27. 27.

    Describing itself as ‘an association of people who have a common interest in exploring religious thought and expression from a non-dogmatic and human-oriented standpoint’, the Sea of Faith Network was founded in the wake of Don Cupitt’s 1984 BBC television documentary series and book with that title, taken from Matthew Arnold’s poem ‘Dover Beach’.

  28. 28.

    The Open Society 78.1 (2005).

References

Philosophy of Religion in Australia

  • Ahern, M. (1963). An approach to the problems of evil. Sophia, 2, 18–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahern, M. (1965). A note on the nature of evil. Sophia, 4, 17–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahern, M. (1966). The nature of evil. Sophia, 5, 35–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahern, M. (1967). God and evil—A note. Sophia, 6, 23–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahern, M. (1971). The problem of evil. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Almond, P. (1979). On the varieties of mystical experience. Sophia, 18, 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Almond, P. (1988). Mysticism and its contexts. Sophia, 27, 40–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1978). A theory of universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. (1983). What is a law of nature? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J., Ellis, B., & Lierse, C. (1992). The world as one of a kind. British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 43, 371–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bilimoria, P. (1990). The self and its destiny in Hinduism. Geelong: Deakin University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bilimoria, P. (1995). Duhkha and Karma: The problem of evil and God’s omnipotence. Sophia, 34, 92–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bilimoria, P. (1997). On Sankara’s attempted reconciliation of ‘You’ and ‘I’. In B. Matilal, J. Mohanty, & P. Bilimoria (Eds.), Relativism, suffering and beyond (pp. 252–77). Delhi: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bilimoria, P. (2001). Hindu doubts about God: Towards a Mimamsa deconstruction. In R. Perrett (Ed.), Philosophy of religion (pp. 87–105). New York: Garland Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyce Gibson, W. (1906). Rudolf Eucken’s philosophy of life. London: Adam & Charles Black.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brien, A. (1989). Can God forgive us our trespasses? Sophia, 28, 35–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R. (1976). From belief to understanding: A study of Anselm's Proslogion argument on the existence of God. Canberra: Australian National University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R. (1981). Transcendence and the scope of philosophical reflection. In R. Mortley & D. Dockrill (Eds.), Via Negativa Prudentia (Supp. Vol. 1). Auckland University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R. (1982). Philosophical reflection and the impulse towards transcendence. In E. Dowdy (Ed.), Ways of transcendence: Insights from major religions and modern thought (pp. 148–69). Bedford Park: Australian Association for the Study of Religion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, R. (1995). Anselm’s three stage argument—Twenty years on. Sophia, 34, 32–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chadha, M., & Trakakis, N. (2007). Karma and the problem of evil: A response to Kaufman. Philosophy East and West, 57, 533–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2006). The character of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charlesworth, M. (1962). St Anselm’s argument. Sophia, 1, 25–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charlesworth, M. (1965). St Anselm’s Proslogion. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charlesworth, M. (1987). Australian aboriginal religion in a comparative context. Sophia, 26, 50–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charlesworth, M., Dussart, F., & Morphy, H. (2005). Aboriginal religions in Australia: An anthology of recent work. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chipman, L. (1970). Faith, reason and truth. The Australian Rationalist, 1, 111–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coady, C. (1992). Testimony. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coghlan, P., & Trakakis, N. (2006). Confronting the horror of natural evil: An exchange between Peter Coghlan and Nick Trakakis. Sophia, 45, 5–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M., Priest, G., & Garfield, J. (2005). Problems with the argument from fine tuning. Synthese, 145, 325–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craig, W. (1979). The Kalam cosmological argument. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglass, J. (2004). Logic and God: A thesis claiming that there is a link between God and mathematics (PhD Thesis). University of New England.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44, 248–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drum, P. (1996). An implausible theodicy. Sophia, 35, 79–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drum, P. (2003). Supernatural religion and the problem of providence. Sophia, 42, 27–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff-Forbes, D. (1961). Theology and falsification again. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 39, 143–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. (1965). The elementary forms of the religious life (trans: Swain, J). New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliot, R. (1976). Resurrection and retrocognition. Sophia, 15, 28–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Englebretsen, G. (1979). The powers and capacities of God. Sophia, 18, 29–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2007). Reasonable religious disagreements. In L. Antony (Ed.), Philosophers without God: Meditations on atheism and the secular life (pp. 194–214). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, A., & Ramsay, H. (Eds.). (2004). Faith and reason. Adelaide: ATF Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (1981). The problem of evil: Two neglected defences. Sophia, 20, 49–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (1989). An argument for the divine command theory of right action. Sophia, 28, 2–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (1996). God without the supernatural. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (1998). Divine fission: A new way of moderating social trinitarianism. Religious Studies, 34, 281–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (2000). The incarnation: A philosophical case for kenosis. Religious Studies, 36, 127–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (2007a). Developmental theism: From pure will to unbounded love. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (2007b). The tree of life: Agency and immortality in a metaphysics inspired by quantum theory. In D. Zimmerman & P. van Inwagen (Eds.), Persons, human and divine (pp. 301–18). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, R. (1964). Some sorts of necessity. Sophia, 3, 15–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, J. (1980). More on Part IX of Hume’s dialogues. The Philosophical Quarterly, 30, 69–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, R. (1996). Interpretations of mysticism. Sophia, 35, 47–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, J. (1998). Two caricatures, I: Pascal’s wager. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 44, 109–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, J. (2002). Two caricatures, II: Leibniz’s best world. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 52, 45–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, J. (2006). Traditional catholic philosophy: Baby and bathwater. In M. Whelan (Ed.), Issues for church and society (pp. 15–32). Strathfield: St Pauls Publications Australia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaita, R. (1991). Good and evil: An absolute conception. Basingstoke: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfied, J., & Priest, G. (2003). Nagarjuna on the limits of thought. Philosophy East and West, 53, 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, J. (1977). Miracles with method. Sophia, 16, 19–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gleason, G. (2004). Speaking of persons, human and divine. Sophia, 43, 45–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grave, S. (1952). The ontological argument of St. Anselm. Philosophy, 27, 30–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grave, S. (1984). A history of philosophy in Australia. St. Lucia: Queensland University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grim, P. (1983). Some neglected problems of omniscience. American Philosophical Quarterly, 20, 265–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grim, P. (1985). Against omniscience: The case from essential indexicals. Noûs, 19, 151–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grim, P. (2000). The being that knew too much. International Journal of Philosophy of Religion, 47, 141–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2003). Waging war on Pascal’s wager. Philosophical Review, 113, 27–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, P. (1996). God and animal minds: A response to Lynch. Sophia, 35, 67–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hick, J. (1989). An interpretation of religion. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchings, P. (1995). The old and the new sublimes: Do they signify? God? Sophia, 34, 49–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1986). What Mary didn’t know. Journal of Philosophy, 83, 291–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kesarcodi-Watson, I. (1976). Is Hinduism pantheistic? Sophia, 15, 26–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kesarcodi-Watson, I. (1984). Approaches to personhood in Indian thought: Essays in descriptive metaphysics. Delhi: Satgara.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khamara, E. (1995). Mackie’s Paradox and the free will defence. Sophia, 34, 42–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamb, W. (1996). Beyond tolerance: On describing the fundamentalist. St. Mark’s Review, 164, 10–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamb, W. (1998). ‘Facts that stay put’: Protestant fundamentalism, epistemology and orthodoxy. Sophia, 37, 88–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamb, W. (2004). Living truth—Truthful living: Christian faith and the scalpel of suspicion. Hindmarsh: ATF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamb, W., & Barnes, I. (Eds.). (2003). God down under: Theology in the antipodes. Adelaide: ATF Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamont, J. (2004). Divine faith. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langtry, B. (1972). Hume on testimony to the miraculous. Sophia, 11, 20–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langtry, B. (1975a). Hume on miracles and contrary religions. Sophia, 14, 29–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langtry, B. (1975b). Similarity, continuity, and survival. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 53, 3–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langtry, B. (1982). In defence of a resurrection doctrine. Sophia, 21, 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langtry, B. (1985). Miracles and rival systems of religion. Sophia, 24, 21–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langtry, B. (1989). God, evil and probability. Sophia, 28, 32–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langtry, B. (1995). Reply to Chrzan’s comments. Sophia, 34, 74–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langtry, B. (1998). Structures of greater good theodicies: The objection from alternative goods. Sophia, 37, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langtry, B. (2008). God, the best and evil. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, M. (1984). Why traditional theism does not entail pantheism. Sophia, 23, 13–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, M. (1994a). Adams’s modified divine command theory of ethics. Sophia, 33, 63–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, M. (1994b). Pantheism: A non-theistic concept of the divine. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, M. (1996). Must God create the best? Sophia, 35, 28–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Londey, D. (1963a). God is the (a) necessary being. Sophia, 2, 15–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Londey, D. (1963b). Necessary being again. Sophia, 2, 30–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Londey, D. (1978). Concepts and God’s possibility. Sophia, 17, 15–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Londey, D. (1986). Can God forgive us our trespasses? Sophia, 25, 4–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Londey, D. (1992). God and forgiveness. Sophia, 31, 101–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Londey, D., Miller, B., & King-Farlow, J. (1971). God and the stone paradox: Three comments. Sophia, 10, 23–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luck, M. (2005). Against the possibility of historical evidence for a miracle. Sophia, 44, 7–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. (1955). Evil and omnipotence. Mind, 64, 200–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. (1982). The miracle of theism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCloskey, H. (1974). God and evil. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCullagh, C. (1988). Theology of atonement. Theology, 91, 392–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCullagh, C. (1992). Evil and the love of God. Sophia, 31, 48–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCullagh, C. (2007). Can religious beliefs be justified pragmatically? Sophia, 46, 21–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, B. (1992). From existence to God: A contemporary philosophical argument. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, B. (1996). A most unlikely God: A philosophical exploration of the nature of God. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, B. (2002). The fullness of being: A new paradigm for existence. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, T. (1987). Anselmian explorations: Essays in philosophical theology. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mortley, R. (1986a). From word to silence (Vol. 1, The Rise and Fall of Logos). Bonn: Hanstein.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mortley, R. (1986b). From word to silence (Vol. 2, The Way of Negation, Christian and Greek). Bonn: Hanstein.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, A. (2005). Talking about God: Analogy revisited. The Australasian Catholic Record, 82, 29–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y. (2003a). Divine omniscience and experience: A reply to Alter. Ars Disputandi, 3. http://www.arsdisputandi.org/publish/articles/000098/index.html

  • Nagasawa, Y. (2003b). Divine omniscience and knowledge de se. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 53, 73–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y. (2003c). God’s point of view: A reply to Mander. The Heythrop Journal, 44, 60–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y. (2005). Omniscience and physicalism: A reply to Beyer. Sophia, 44, 55–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y. (2007a). Millican on the ontological argument. Mind, 116, 1027–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y. (2007b). A further reply to Beyer on omniscience. Sophia, 46, 65–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y. (2008a). God and phenomenal consciousness: A novel approach to knowledge arguments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y. (2008b). A New defence of Anselmian theism. Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 577–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y., & Bayne, T. (2006). Grounds of worship. Religious Studies, 42, 299–313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y., & Bayne, T. (2007). The grounds of worship again: A reply to Crowe. Religious Studies, 43, 475–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y., & Brown, C. (2005a). I can’t make you worship me. Ratio, 18, 138–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y., & Brown, C. (2005b). Anything you can do, God can do better. American Philosophical Quarterly, 42, 221–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y., & Brown, C. (2005c). The best of all possible worlds. Synthese, 143, 309–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagasawa, Y., & Trakakis, N. (2004). Skeptical theism and moral skepticism: A reply to Almeida and Oppy. Ars Disputandi, 4. http://www.arsdisputandi.org/publish/articles/000178/article.pdf

  • Nagasawa, Y., Oppy, G., & Trakakis, N. (2004). Salvation in heaven? Philosophical Papers, 33, 95–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naulty, R. (1992). J. L. Mackie’s disposal of religious experience. Sophia, 31, 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olding, A. (1970). Flew on souls. Sophia, 9, 11–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olding, A. (1991). Modern biology and natural theology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (1990). On rescher on Pascal’s wager. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 30, 159–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (1991). Craig, Mackie, and the Kalam cosmological argument. Religious Studies, 27, 189–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (1995a). Inverse operations with transfinite numbers and the Kalam cosmological argument. International Philosophical Quarterly, 35, 219–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (1995b). Ontological arguments and belief in God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (1996a). Gödelian ontological arguments. Analysis, 56, 226–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (1996b). Pascal’s wager is a possible bet (but not a very good one): Reply to Harmon Holcomb III. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 40, 101–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (1999). Koons’ cosmological argument. Faith and Philosophy, 16, 378–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (2000). On ‘a new cosmological argument’. Religious Studies, 36, 345–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (2001). Time, successive addition, and the Kalam cosmological argument. Philosophia Christi, 3, 181–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (2002). Arguing about the Kalam cosmological argument. Philo, 5, 34–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G. (2007). Arguing about Gods. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G., & Almeida, M. (2003). Sceptical theism and the evidential argument from evil. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 81, 496–516.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppy, G., & Almeida, M. (2005). Evidential arguments from evil and sceptical theist responses. Philo, 8, 84–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palma, A. (1986). Notes towards a God. Sophia, 25, 4–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palma, A. (1988). Religious icons, prayers and practices. Sophia, 27, 26–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pargetter, R. (1982). Evil as evidence. Sophia, 21, 11–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1967). God and other minds: A study of the rational justification of belief in God. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1974). The nature of necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (1996). Time’s arrow and Archimedes’ point: New directions in the physics of time. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2002). Beyond the limits of thought. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Restall, G., & Bayne, T. (2009). A participatory theory of the atonement. In Y. Nagasawa & E. Wielenberg (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of religion (pp. 150–66). Palgrave Macmillan: Basingstoke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Routley, R. (1969). A simple natural deduction system. Logique et Analyse, 46, 129–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarlett, B. (2003). God and animal pain. Sophia, 42, 61–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schesinger, G. (1977). Religion and scientific method. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1993). Practical ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, B., & Gillen, F. (1899). The native tribes of central Australia. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, B., & Gillen, F. (1904). The northern tribes of central Australia. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stove, D. (1978). Part IX of Hume’s dialogues. Philosophical Quarterly, 28, 300–09.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stove, D. (1991). Idealism: A Victorian horror story. In The Plato cult and other philosophical follies (pp. 83–179). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1977). The nature of laws. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 7, 667–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1983). Abortion and infanticide. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1989). Plantinga and the argument from evil. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 58, 360–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trakakis, N. (2003a). What no eye has seen: The skeptical theist response to Rowe’s evidential argument from evil. Philo, 6, 250–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trakakis, N. (2003b). On the alleged failure of free will theodicies: A reply to Tierno. Sophia, 42, 99–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trakakis, N. (2003c). God, gratuitous evil, and van Inwagen’s attempt to reconcile the two. Ars Disputandi, 3. http://www.arsdisputandi.org/publish/articles/000124/article.pdf

  • Trakakis, N. (2004). Second thoughts on the alleged failure of free will theodicies. Sophia, 43, 87–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trakakis, N. (2005). Is theism capable of accounting for any natural evil at all? International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 57, 35–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trakakis, N. (2006). The God beyond belief: In defence of William Rowe’s evidential argument from evil. Dordrecht: Springer Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, F. (1973). The contingency argument again. Sophia, 12, 29–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wykstra, S. (1984). The Humean obstacle to evidential arguments from suffering: On avoiding the evils of appearance. International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 16, 73–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynn, M. (1999). God and goodness: A natural theological perspective. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, R. (1970). The resurrection of the body. Sophia, 9, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

Philosophy of Religion in New Zealand

  • Aijaz, I. (2008). Belief, providence and eschatology: Some philosophical problems in Islamic theism. Philosophy Compass, 3, 231–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aijaz, I., & Weidler, M. (2007). Some critical reflections on the hiddenness argument. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 61, 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. (1991). Perceiving God: The epistemology of religious experience. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ardley, G. (1950). Aquinas and Kant: The foundations of the modern sciences. London: Longmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ardley, G. (1982). Sixty years of philosophy: A short history of the Auckland University Philosophy Department, 1921–1983. Auckland: Department of Philosophy, The University of Auckland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (1983). The reasons of the gods: A reply to Robert Nola. Prudentia, 15, 13–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (1985). Theism, morality and the ‘Why should I be moral?’ question. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 17, 3–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (1993a). Evil and the concept of God. Philosophical Papers, 22, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (1993b). Compatibilism and the free will defence. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 71, 104–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (1998). Can there be alternative concepts of God? Noûs, 32, 174–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (2002). Faith as doxastic venture. Religious Studies, 38, 471–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (2006). The philosophy of religion: A programmatic overview. Philosophy Compass, 1, 506–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (2007a). Believing by faith: An essay in the epistemology and ethics of religious belief. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (2007b). How a modest fideism may constrain concepts of God: A Christian alternative to classical theism. Philosophia, 35, 387–402.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J. (2009). Towards a religiously adequate alternative to omniGod theism. Sophia, 48, 419–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J., & Aijaz, I. (2004). How to answer the de jure question about Christian belief. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 56, 109–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, J., & Perszyk, K. (2011). The normatively relativised logical argument from evil. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 70, 109–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, R. (1967). A proof of atheism. Sophia, 6, 35–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, R. (2003). A moral argument for atheism. In M. Martin & R. Monnier (Eds.), The impossibility of God (pp. 157–81). Amherst: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawes, G. (2007). What is wrong with intelligent design? International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 61, 69–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawes, G. (2009). Theism and explanation. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (2006). The God delusion. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dole, A., & Chignell, A. (2005). The ethics of religious belief: A recent history. In A. Dole & A. Chignell (Eds.), God and the ethics of belief: New essays in philosophy of religion (pp. 1–30). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eagleton, T. (2009). Reason, faith and revolution: Reflections on the God debate. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A. (1955). Divine omnipotence and human freedom. In A. Flew & A. MacIntyre (Eds.), New essays in philosophical theology (pp. 144–69). London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geering, L. (1994). Tomorrow’s God: How we create our worlds. Wellington: Bridget Williams Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. (2002). Rocks of ages. New York: Ballantine Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimshaw, M. (2002). The prior Prior: Neglected early writings of Arthur N. Prior. Heythrop Journal, 43, 480–95.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. (1947). An examination of the argument from theology to ethics. Philosophy, 22, 3–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. (1955). Response to J. N. Findlay, ‘Can God’s existence be disproved?’. In A. Flew & A. MacIntyre (Eds.), New essays in philosophical theology (pp. 56–67). London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. (1962). Mr Martin on the Incarnation: A reply to Mr Plantinga and Mr Rowe. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 40, 208–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. (1963). The doctrine of the Trinity. Sophia, 2, 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. (1970). Plantinga on the rationality of God’s existence. Philosophical Review, 79, 246–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. (1982). John Buridan on self-reference: Chapter eight of Buridan’s Sophismata, with a translation, an introduction, and a philosophical commentary. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, G. (1990). Paul of Venice. Logica magna, Part II, Fascicule 4, Capitula De Conditionali et De Rationali, edited with English translation and notes, The British Academy Classical and Medieval Logic Texts, VI. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1956). The will to believe and other essays in popular philosophy, and human immortality. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroon, F. (1981). Plantinga on God, freedom and evil. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 12, 75–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroon, F. (1996). God’s blindspot. Dialogue: Canadian Philosophical Review, 35, 721–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2007). Divine evils. In L. Antony (Ed.), Philosophers without gods: Meditations on atheism and the secular life (pp. 231–42). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E., & Perszyk, K. (2011). Molinist conditionals. In K. Perszyk (Ed.), Molinism: The contemporary debate (pp. 96–117). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marshall, C. (2001). Beyond retribution: A New Testament vision for justice, crime, and punishment. Grand Rapids: W. B. Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. (1992). The logic of the ‘Nominales’, or, the rise and fall of impossible ‘Positio’. Vivarium, 30, 110–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. (1998). The logic of growth: Twelfth-century nominalists and the development of theories of the Incarnation. Medieval Philosophy and Theology, 7, 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. (1999). Non-reductive arguments from impossible hypotheses in Boethius and Philoponus. In D. Sedley (Ed.), Oxford studies in ancient philosophy (Vol. 17, pp. 279–302). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. (2004). Logic. In J. Brower (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Abelard (pp. 158–99). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, P., & Grimshaw, M. (Eds.). (2008). The Lloyd Geering reader: Prophet of modernity. Wellington: Victoria University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musgrave, A. (2009). Secular sermons: Essays on science and philosophy. Dunedin: Otago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nola, R. (1982). Morality and religion in Plato’s Euthyphro. Prudentia, 14, 83–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oddie, G., & Perrett, R. (1992). Simultaneity and God’s timelessness. Sophia, 31, 123–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Owens, J. (2004). The God whereof we speak: D. Z. Phillips and the question of God’s existence. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 78, 83–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson, J. (1992). Exploring Māori values. Palmerston North: Dunmore Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pelly, R., & Stuart, P. (Eds.). (2006). A religious atheist? Critical essays on the work of Lloyd Geering. Dunedin: Otago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrett, R. (1985a). Karma and the problem of suffering. Sophia, 24, 4–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrett, R. (1985b). Dualistic and nondualistic problems of immortality. Philosophy East and West, 35, 333–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrett, R. (1987a). Death and immortality. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrett, R. (1987b). Rebirth. Religious Studies, 23, 41–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrett, R. (Ed.). (1989). Indian philosophy of religion. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perrett, R., & Patterson, J. (1991). Virtue ethics and Māori ethics. Philosophy East and West, 41, 185–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perszyk, K. (1998a). Free will defence with and without molinism. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 43, 29–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perszyk, K. (1998b). An anti-molinist argument. Philosophical Studies, 90, 215–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perszyk, K. (1998c). Molinism and theodicy. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 44, 163–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perszyk, K. (1999a). Compatibilism and the free will defence: A reply to Bishop. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 77, 92–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perszyk, K. (1999b). Stump’s theodicy of redemptive suffering and molinism. Religious Studies, 35, 191–211.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perszyk, K. (2000). Molinism and compatibilism. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 48, 11–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perszyk, K. (2003). Molinism and the consequence argument: A challenge. Faith and Philosophy, 20, 131–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perszyk, K. (Ed.). (2011). Molinism: The contemporary debate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrove, G. (2005). Rights, reasons, and religious conflict: Habermas and Scanlon on the role of religion in public debate. In J. Rowan (Ed.), Human rights, religion, and democracy (pp. 81–93). Charlottesville: Philosophy Documentation Center.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrove, G. (2007). Forgiveness and interpretation. Journal of Religious Ethics, 35, 429–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrove, G. (2008). The dilemma of divine forgiveness. Religious Studies, 44, 457–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1984). Advice to Christian philosophers. Faith and Philosophy, 1, 253–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (2000). Warranted Christian belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A., & Tooley, M. (2008). Knowledge of God. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, D. (1989). Aseity as relational problematic. Sophia, 28, 13–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, D. (1992). Religious concepts of ‘world’: Comparative metaphysical perspectives. Sophia, 31, 74–88.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, D. (2002). Relational deity: Hartshorne and Macquarrie on God. Lanham: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, D. (2005). Religious plurality, referential realism and paradigms of pluralism. In A. Plaw (Ed.), Frontiers of diversity: Explorations in contemporary pluralism (pp. 191–209). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, D. (2007). Pluralism, postmodernism and interreligious dialogue. Sophia, 46, 243–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. (1955). Can religion be discussed? In A. Flew & A. MacIntyre (Eds.), New essays in philosophical theology (pp. 1–11). London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schellenberg, J. (1993). Divine hiddenness and human reason. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. (1955). Metaphysics, logic and theology. In A. Flew & A. MacIntyre (Eds.), New essays in philosophical theology (pp. 12–27). London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, J. (1966). Religious belief and ‘reductionism’. Sophia, 5, 3–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, J. (1967). Reductionism: A reply to Dr Mascall. Sophia, 6, 6–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, J. (1984). Miracles and God’s existence. Philosophy, 59, 219–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, R. (2006). Rescuing religious non-realism from Cupitt. Heythrop Journal, 47, 426–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wicks, R. (2007). Routledge philosophy guidebook to Kant on judgement. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolterstorff, N. (2009). How philosophical theology became possible within the analytic tradition of philosophy. In O. Crisp & M. Rea (Eds.), Analytic theology: New essays in the philosophy of theology (pp. 155–68). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, J. (2003). The death of God and the meaning of life. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, J. (2006). Nietzsche’s philosophy of religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Forrest .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this entry

Cite this entry

Forrest, P., Bishop, J., Perszyk, K. (2014). Philosophy of Religion in Australasia. In: Oppy, G., Trakakis, N. (eds) History of Philosophy in Australia and New Zealand. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6958-8_16

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6958-8_16

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-6957-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-6958-8

  • eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and Law

Publish with us

Policies and ethics