Skip to main content

From Conventionalism to Scientific Metaphysics

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
History of Philosophy in Australia and New Zealand
  • 804 Accesses

Abstract

By the end of the first decade of the twentieth century, the most urgent problem for philosophers of science appeared to be that of reconciling their philosophies with the astonishing discoveries in space-time theory and electromagnetism. Albert Einstein had written his remarkable paper on the electrodynamics of moving bodies, better known as the Special Theory of Relativity (STR); Max Planck had introduced his counterintuitive quantum hypothesis to explain the empirical laws of black body radiation; and Einstein had used Planck’s theory of atomic resonators to explain the photoelectric effect. The world of physics, which until then had seemed so solid and well ordered, was shaken and in some disarray. For these developments appeared not to be reconcilable with the Newtonian worldview that had, until then, dominated the scientific image of reality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 549.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    John Fox (2007) has recently convinced me that I did make one serious error of this kind. My ‘dinch’ scale for the measurement of length leads to inconsistencies, given the way in which I proposed to use it.

  2. 2.

    I remember Grünbaum saying to me once something to the effect that ‘The analytic-synthetic distinction [i.e., the distinction between what is true in virtue of the meanings of words, and what is not] is one thing, and may well be untenable, but the fact-convention distinction is another, and is absolutely fundamental’.

  3. 3.

    My 1963 paper was not published until November of that year.

References

  • Ayer, A. (1936). Language, truth and logic. London: Gollancz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J., Ellis, B., & Lierse, C. (1992). The world as one of a kind: Natural necessity and laws of nature. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43, 371–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bridgman, P. (1927). The logic of modern physics. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bridgman, P. (1962). A sophisticate’s primer of relativity. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, N. (1921). Physics: The elements. New York: Dover. Republished 1957 as Foundations of Science: The Philosophy of Theory and Experiment.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P., & Hooker, C. (Eds.). (1985). Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism, with a reply from Bas C. Van Fraassen. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colodny, R. (Ed.). (1965). Beyond the edge of certainty: Essays in contemporary science and philosophy. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1954). The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Trans. P. Wiener.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (1957). A comparison of process and non-process theories in the physical sciences. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 8, 45–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (1963). Universal and differential forces. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 14, l77–l94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (1966). Basic concepts of measurement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (1971). On conventionality and simultaneity: A reply. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 49, 177–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (1975). Physicalism and the contents of sense experience. In C.-Y. Cheng (Ed.), Philosophical aspects of the mind-body problem (pp. 64–77). Honolulu: University Press of Hawaii.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (1979). Rational belief systems. Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (1980). Truth as a mode of evaluation. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 1, 85–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (1985). What science aims to do. In P. Churchland & C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism, with a reply by Bas C. Van Fraassen (pp. 166–193). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (1987). The ontology of scientific realism. In P. Pettit, R. Sylvan, & J. Norman (Eds.), Metaphysics and morality: Essays in honour of J. J. C. Smart (pp. 50–70). Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (1990). Truth and objectivity. Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2002). The philosophy of nature: A guide to the new essentialism. London: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B., & Bowman, P. (1967). Conventionality in distant simultaneity. Philosophy in Science, 34, 116–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B., & Lierse, C. (1994). Dispositional essentialism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 72, 27–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (1986). The dynamics of belief. Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fox, J. (1987). Truthmaker. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 65, 188–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, J. (2007). Why we shouldn’t give Ellis a dinch. Analysis, 67, 301–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gðrdenfors, P. (1986). The epistemic importance of minimal changes of belief. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 62,136–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasking, D. (1940). Mathematics and the world. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 18, 97–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasking, D. (1960). Clusters. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 38, 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, A. (1964). Is a universal nocturnal expansion falsifiable or physically vacuous? Philosophical Studies, 15, 71–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, A. (1967). The denial of absolute space and the hypothesis of a universal nocturnal expansion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 45, 61–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, A., et al. (1969). Panel discussion of simultaneity by slow clock transport in the special and general theories of relativity. Philosophy in Science, 36, 1–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1963–1964). Proofs and refutations. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 14: 1–25, 120–39, 221–45, 269–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programs. In I. Lakatos & A. Musgrave (Eds.), Criticism and the growth of knowledge (pp. 91–196). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy in Science, 48, 19–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1952). Science and hypothesis. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (1959). The logic of scientific discovery. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, E., Pargetter, R., & Jackson, F. (1982). Three theses about dispositions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 19, 251–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1962). The analytic and the synthetic. In H. Feigl & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Scientific explanation, space, and time (pp. 358–397). Minneapolis: Minnesota University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1953). From a logical point of view: Nine logico-philosophical essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1958). The philosophy of space and time. New York: Dover. Trans. M. Reichenbach and J. Freund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (Ed.). (1967). The linguistic turn: Recent essays in philosophical method. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlesinger, G. (1964). It is false that overnight everything has doubled in size. Philosophical Studies, 15, 65–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlesinger, G. (1967). What does the denial of absolute space mean? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 45, 44–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. (1963). Philosophy and scientific realism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory (pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brian Ellis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this entry

Cite this entry

Ellis, B. (2014). From Conventionalism to Scientific Metaphysics. In: Oppy, G., Trakakis, N. (eds) History of Philosophy in Australia and New Zealand. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6958-8_12

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6958-8_12

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-6957-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-6958-8

  • eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and Law

Publish with us

Policies and ethics