Skip to main content

Value Ladenness and the Value-Free Ideal in Scientific Research

  • Reference work entry

Abstract

Regarding scientific research, value ladenness and the value-free ideal represent two poles. At the beginning of the twentieth century, the influential view was science as “value-free” (Wertfrei), whereas in the first decade of the twenty-first century the dominant perspective is science as “value-laden.” After considering the historical setting on values in science, the analysis here deals with the characteristics and relations between axiology of research and ethics of science. This involves taking into account the option in favor of holism of values and the alternative in terms of fractional orientations, either in “internal” terms or in “external” ones. Thus, the presence of values in basic science and in applied science is considered. After that, economics as a relevant case study is addressed through the distinction between positive economics and normative economics. There is also a coda with final remarks on the topics analyzed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Notes

  1. 1.

    This has been pointed out emphatically: [18]. See also [38]. Additional aspects can be found in [4, 16, 48, 53] and [57].

  2. 2.

    In addition to values in science, there is the issue of the value of science itself, cf. [42]. See also [55].

  3. 3.

    The designs in the sciences of the artificial take into account values, as can be seen in the case of the evaluative rationality regarding the ends of the designs, cf. [30].

  4. 4.

    Cf. [72]. See also [70].

  5. 5.

    The characteristics of Historismus can be found in W. Dilthey, cf. [20] pp. 109–137; especially, pp. 110–112 and 115–117.

  6. 6.

    “The idea of truth as the fundamental regulative principle – the principle that guides our search – can be regarded as an ethical principle. The search for truth and the idea of approximation to the truth are also ethical principles; as are the ideas of intellectual integrity and of fallibility, which lead us to a self-critical attitude and to toleration” [67, p. 199]. On the truth as epistemic value and ethical value in Popper, see [59], pp. 282–293.

  7. 7.

    [45]. On the intellectual precedents of Kuhn’s views, cf. [27] pp. 15–103; especially, pp. 23–27.

  8. 8.

    [60]. Before this Presidential address in the PSA, there is a paper on the same topic: [71].

  9. 9.

    On the status of “values” in general, see [75] and [76].

  10. 10.

    This discussion on this issue is in [65].

  11. 11.

    The objectivity of values is explicitly discussed in connection with human needs in [72], Chap. 3, pp. 73–96. See also [67].

  12. 12.

    However, following a pragmatic approach (sites, products, etc.), he does not see a clear distinction between “science” and “technology” (including “basic research” and technology), cf. [41] pp. 85–91, especially, p. 86.

  13. 13.

    This can be seen in the case of scientific prediction: “Probably the most deeply held values concern predictions: they should be accurate; quantitative predictions are preferable to qualitative ones; whatever the margin of permissible error, it should be consistently satisfied in a given field; and so on” [46], p. 185.

  14. 14.

    On the distinction between “applied science” and “application of science,” see [62], p. 9.

  15. 15.

    According to Imre Lakatos, “Scientists, as citizens, have responsibility, like other citizens, to see that science is applied to the right social and political ends,” in [50], p. 258.

  16. 16.

    Cf. [24], pp. 11–44; especially, pp. 22–26.

  17. 17.

    This is also the case in the sciences of the artificial, where there are certainly ethical concerns, for example, in the field of computer sciences. Cf. [17] and [36].

  18. 18.

    On this notion, see [73].

  19. 19.

    This thematic realm is receiving an increasing attention. Cf. [8].

  20. 20.

    The social consequences in this field are visible. See, for example, [40].

  21. 21.

    Cf. Rescher, N, Personal Communication, 27 Aug 1998. His conception is developed in [74]. On his philosophical approach, see [87]. On holism about values see [10] and [61].

  22. 22.

    Cf. Rescher, N, Personal Communication, 27 Aug 1998. Cf. [24], p. 22.

  23. 23.

    For Laudan, “epistemic values” (truth, falsity, …) can be distinguished from “cognitive values” (scope, generality, coherence, consilience, explanatory, …), cf. [52], p. 20.

  24. 24.

    Rescher, N, Personal Communication, 27 Aug 1998.

  25. 25.

    Cf. [51], pp. xi–xii, n. 2. The subtitle of his book is very clear: The Aims of Science and their Role in Scientific Debate. In his reticular model of scientific rationality, Laudan emphasizes that those values are good enough for the task: “Doubtless a wide range of cognitive goals or values can satisfy the demands laid down here” [51], p. 63.

  26. 26.

    See, for example, [34] and [85].

  27. 27.

    There is usually a tension in the scientist between the defense of his or her autonomy and the need for responsibility, cf. [14].

  28. 28.

    The constitutive elements of science are presented in [28], pp. 3–49; especially, pp. 10–11.

  29. 29.

    On this distinction, cf. [62] and [80].

  30. 30.

    The existence of differences between basic science and applied science can be seen on analyzing the latter, cf. [63] and [64].

  31. 31.

    This means that scientific progress is commonly modulated by an “economics of research.”

  32. 32.

    Cf. [72], Chaps. 7, 8, and 9, pp. 151–203.

  33. 33.

    The repercussion is even more noticeable when technology is involved, cf. [2] and [3].

  34. 34.

    The concept of “neutrality” in science has been analyzed in [1], Chap. III.

  35. 35.

    Rescher, N, Personal Communication, 27 Aug 1998.

  36. 36.

    This kind of approach affects the issue of “intrinsic” versus “extrinsic” values. On intrinsic and relational properties, see [37]. See also [9].

References

  1. Agazzi E (1992) Il bene, il male e la scienza: Le dimensioni etiche dell'impresa scientifico-tecnologica. Rusconi, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  2. Agazzi E (1999) Valores éticos en la empresa científico-tecnológica: De la Ciencia como value-free al compromiso ético de la Ciencia y la Tecnología. Arbor 162(638):173–193

    Google Scholar 

  3. Agazzi E (1999) Límites éticos del quehacer científico y tecnológico. Arbor 162(637):241–263

    Google Scholar 

  4. Agazzi E, Minazzi F (eds) (2008) Science and ethics. The axiological contexts of science. P. Lang, Brussels

    Google Scholar 

  5. Alexandra A, Matthews S, Miller S (2002) Reasons, values and institutions. Tertiary Press, Croydon

    Google Scholar 

  6. Alexandra A, Miller S (2005) Common morality and “institutionalising” ethics. Australian J Prof Appl Ethics 7(1):24–33

    Google Scholar 

  7. Alexandra A (2009) “Ethical theory”, “common morality”, and professional obligations. Theor Med Bioeth 30(1):69–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Audin R (2009) Business ethics and ethical business. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  9. Bradley B (1998) Extrinsic value. Philos Stud 91:109–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Brown C (2007) Two kinds of holism about values. Philos Q 57(228):456–463

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Bruun HH (2007) Science, values and politics in Max Weber’s methodology, new expanded edition. Ashgate, Farnham, (1st edition 1972)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ciaffa JA (1998) Max Weber and the problems of value-free social science: a critical examination of the Werturteilsstreit. Associated University Presses, New Jersey

    Google Scholar 

  13. Douglas HE (2000) Inductive risk and values in science. Philos Sci 67:559–579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Douglas HE (2003) The moral responsibilities of scientists: tensions between autonomy and responsibility. Am Philos Q 40(1):59–68

    Google Scholar 

  15. Douglas HE (ed) (2009) Science, policy, and the value-free ideal. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  16. Elliot KC (2011) Direct and indirect roles for values in science. Philos Sci 78(2):303–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Floridi L (ed) (2010) The Cambridge handbook of information and computer ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  18. Forge J (2009) Science is value-laden: you can count on that! Metascience 18(2):257–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Fortner RS, Fackler M (eds) (2011) The handbook of global communication and media ethics. Wiley-Blackwell, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  20. Gonzalez WJ (1984) La interpretación historicista de las Ciencias Sociales. Anales de Filosofía 2:109–137

    Google Scholar 

  21. Gonzalez WJ (1994) Economic prediction and human activity. An analysis of prediction in economics from action theory. Epistemologia 17:253–294

    Google Scholar 

  22. Gonzalez WJ (1998) Prediction and prescription in economics: a philosophical and methodological approach. Theoria 13(32):321–345

    Google Scholar 

  23. Gonzalez WJ (1999) Ciencia y valores éticos: De la posibilidad de la Ética de la Ciencia al problema de la valoración ética de la Ciencia Básica. Arbor 162(637):139–171

    Google Scholar 

  24. Gonzalez WJ (1999) Racionalidad científica y actividad humana. Ciencia y valores en la Filosofía de N. Rescher. In: Rescher N Razón y valores en la Era científico-tecnológica. Paidós, Barcelona, pp 11–44

    Google Scholar 

  25. Gonzalez WJ (2001) De la Ciencia de la Economía a la Economía de la Ciencia: Marco conceptual de la reflexión metodológica y axiológica. In: Avila A, Gonzalez WJ, Marques G (eds) Ciencia económica y Economía de la Ciencia: Reflexiones filosófico-metodológicas. FCE, Madrid, pp 11–37

    Google Scholar 

  26. Gonzalez WJ (2003) Erklären-Verstehen to Prediction-Understanding: the methodological framework in economics. In: Sintonen M, Ylikoski P, Miller K (eds) Realism in action: essays in the philosophy of social sciences. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 33–50

    Google Scholar 

  27. Gonzalez WJ (2004) Las revoluciones científicas y la evolución de Thomas S. Kuhn. In: Gonzalez WJ (ed) Análisis de Thomas Kuhn: Las revoluciones científicas. Trotta, Madrid, pp 15–103

    Google Scholar 

  28. Gonzalez WJ (2005) The philosophical approach to science, technology and society. In: Gonzalez WJ (ed) Science, technology and society: a philosophical perspective. Netbiblo, A Coruña, pp 3–49

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  29. Gonzalez WJ (2006) Novelty and continuity in philosophy and methodology of science. In: Gonzalez WJ, Alcolea J (eds) Contemporary perspectives in philosophy and methodology of science. Netbiblo, A Coruña, pp 1–28

    Google Scholar 

  30. Gonzalez WJ (2008) Rationality and prediction in the sciences of the artificial: economics as a design science. In: Suppes P, Galavotti MC, Scazzieri R (eds) Reasoning, rationality and probability. CSLI Publications, Stanford, pp 165–186

    Google Scholar 

  31. Gonzalez WJ (2008) Economic values in the configuration of science. In: Agazzi E, Echeverría J, Gómez A (eds) Epistemology and the social, Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and the humanities. Rodopi, Amsterdam, pp 85–112

    Google Scholar 

  32. Haddock A, Millar A, Pritchard D (eds) (2009) Epistemic value. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  33. Hausman DM, McPherson MS (1996) Economic analysis and moral philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  34. Hausman DM, McPherson MS (2006) Economic analysis, moral philosophy, and public policy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (This is the second edition of the previous book. But it is an enlarge version – 93 pages more – and with an addition in the title – and Public Policy –, details that justified to list here in two entries.)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  35. Hempel CG (1960) Science and human values. In: Spillar R (ed) Social control in a free society. University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia, pp 39–64 (Reprinted in: Hempel CG (1965) Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. Free Press, New York, pp 81–96)

    Google Scholar 

  36. Himma KE, Tavani HT (eds) (2008) The handbook of information and computer ethics. Wiley, Hoboken, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  37. Kagan S (1998) Rethinking intrinsic value. J Ethics 2(4):277–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Kincaid H, Dupré J, Wyley A (eds) (2007) Value-free science: ideals and illusions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  39. Kitcher PH (1993) The advancement of science: science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  40. Kitcher PH (1996) The lives to come: the genetic revolution and human possibilities. Simon and Schuster/Penguin, N. York/London (Reprinted with an important postscript in 1997)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Kitcher PH (2001) Science, truth, and democracy. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  42. Koertge N (1998) Science, values, and the value of science. Philos Sci 67(3):S45–S57

    Google Scholar 

  43. Koslowski P (ed) (2000) Contemporary economic ethics and business ethics. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  44. Koslowski P (2001) Principles of ethical economy. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  45. Kuhn ThS (1962) The structure of scientific revolutions. International Encyclopedia of unified science: foundations of the unity of science 2(2). The University of Chicago Press, Chicago (2nd edn., 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  46. Kuhn ThS (1970) Postscript – 1969. In: Kuhn ThS The structure of scientific revolutions, 2nd edn. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 174–210

    Google Scholar 

  47. Kuhn ThS (1973) Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. Lecture at the University of Furman, 30 Nov 1973; reprinted in: Kuhn ThS (1977) The essential tension: selected studies in scientific tradition and change. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 320–339

    Google Scholar 

  48. Lacey H (2002) The ways in which the sciences are and are not value free. In: Gardenfors P, Kijania-Placek K, Wolenski J (eds) In the scope of logic, methodology, and philosophy of science. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp 513–526

    Google Scholar 

  49. Lacey H (2005) Is science value free?: Values and scientific understanding. Routledge, London, 1999; 2nd edn, Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  50. Lakatos I (1970) The social responsibility of science, Paper delivered on 18 Feb 1970, and published in: Lakatos I (1978) Mathematics, science and epistemology (ed by Worrall J, Currie G) Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 256–258

    Google Scholar 

  51. Laudan L (1984) Science and values: an essay on the aims of science and their role in scientific debate. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  52. Laudan L (2004) The epistemic, the cognitive, and the social. In: Machamer P, Wolters G (eds) Science, values, and objectivity. University of Pittsburgh Press/Universitätsverlag, Pittsburgh/Konstanz, pp 14–23

    Google Scholar 

  53. Lekka-Kowalik A (2010) Why science cannot be value-free: understanding the rationality and responsibility of science. Sci Eng Ethics 16(1):33–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Longino HE (1990) Science as social knowledge: values and objectivity in scientific inquiry. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  55. Machamer PK, Douglas H (1998) How values are in science. Crit Q 40(2):29–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Machamer PK, Douglas H (1999) Cognitive and social values. Sci Educ 8:45–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Machamer P, Wolters G (eds) (2004) Science, values, and objectivity. University of Pittsburgh Press/Universitätsverlag, Pittsburgh/Konstanz

    Google Scholar 

  58. Martin JD, Petty JW, Wallace JS (eds) (2009) Value-based management with corporate social responsibility. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  59. Martínez Solano JF (2005) El problema de la verdad en K. R. Popper: Reconstrucción histórico-sistemática. Netbiblo, A Coruña

    Google Scholar 

  60. McMullin E (1983) Values in science. In: Asquith PD, Nickles Th (eds) PSA 1982. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, pp 3–28

    Google Scholar 

  61. McNaugton D, Rawling P (2008) Holism about value. In: Lance MN, Potrč M, Strahovnik V (eds) Challenging moral particularism. Routledge, New York, pp 166–184

    Google Scholar 

  62. Niiniluoto I (1993) The aim and structure of applied research. Erkenntnis 38:1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  63. Niiniluoto I (1995) Approximation in applied science. Poznan Stud Philos Sci Humanit 42:127–139

    Google Scholar 

  64. Niiniluoto I (1995) The emergence of scientific specialities: six models. Poznan Stud Philos Sci Humanit 44:211–223

    Google Scholar 

  65. Niiniluoto I (2009) Facts and values – a useful distinction. Acta Philos Fennica 86:109–133

    Google Scholar 

  66. Popper KR (1969) The moral responsibility of the scientist. Encounter 32(3):52–54 and 56–57. (Reprinted in: Popper, KR (1994) The myth of the framework. In defence of science and rationality. Routledge, London, pp 121–129)

    Google Scholar 

  67. Popper, KR (1982) Duldsamkeit und Intellektuelle Veranwortlichkeit. In: Stuhlmacher, P, Abramowski, L (eds) Toleranz. Atempto Verlag, Tubinga, pp 173–185. Reprinted as Duldsamkeit und intellektuelle Verantwortlichkeit (gestohlen von Xenophanes und von Voltaire). In: Popper, KR (1984) Auf der Suche nach einer besseren Welt. Piper, Munich, pp 213–230. English translation: Toleration and intellectual responsibility. In: Mendus, S, Edwards, D (eds) (1987) On toleration. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 17–34. Later published as Toleration and intellectual responsibility (Stolen from Xenophanes and Voltaire), in: Popper, KR (1992) In search of a better world. Lectures and Essays from Thirty Years. Routledge, London, pp 188–203

    Google Scholar 

  68. Pritchard D (2007) Recent work on epistemic value. Am Philos Q 44:85–110

    Google Scholar 

  69. Radnitzky G (1981) Wertfreiheitsthese: Wissenschaft, Ethik und Politik. In: Radnitzky G, Andersson G (eds) Voraussetzungen und Grenzen der Wissenschaft. Mohr, Tubingen, pp 47–126

    Google Scholar 

  70. Rescher N (1965) The ethical dimension of scientific research. In: Colodny RG (ed) Beyond the edge of certainty, Essays in contemporary science and philosophy. University Press of America, Lanham, MD, (reprinted in 1983), pp 261–276

    Google Scholar 

  71. Rescher N (1977) Values in science. Proceedings of the eight international conference on the unity of the sciences, (Washington, 1976), New York, Vol 2, pp 1023–1030

    Google Scholar 

  72. Rescher N (1999) Razón y valores en la Era científico-tecnológica, edited by WJ Gonzalez, Paidós, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  73. Rescher N (2003) Collective responsibility. In: Rescher N (ed) Sensible decisions. Issues of rational decision in personal choice and public policy. Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham, MD, pp 125–138

    Google Scholar 

  74. Rescher N (1993) A system of pragmatic idealism, vol II: The validity of values: human values in pragmatic perspective, Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  75. Rescher N (2004) Value matters: studies in axiology. Ontos Verlag, Frankfurt

    Google Scholar 

  76. Rescher N (2006) Studies in value theory. Collected papers, vol 8. Ontos Verlag, Frankfurt

    Google Scholar 

  77. Resnik DB (1998) The ethics of science. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  78. Schumpeter J (1949) Science and ideology. American economic review 39. Reprinted in: Hausman D (ed) (2008) The philosophy of economics, 3rd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 207–221

    Google Scholar 

  79. Sen A (1986) Prediction and economic theory. In: Mason J, Mathias P, Westcott JH (eds) Predictability in science and society. The Royal Society/The British Academy, London, pp 3–23

    Google Scholar 

  80. Sintonen M (1990) Basic and applied sciences – can the distinction (still) be drawn? Sci Stud 3(2):23–31

    Google Scholar 

  81. Solow R (1971) Science and ideology in economics. Public Interest 21:94–107

    Google Scholar 

  82. Todt O, Rodríguez Alcázar J, Luján JL (2010) Practical values and uncertainty in regulatory decision-making. Soc Epistemol 24(4):349–362

    Article  Google Scholar 

  83. Weber M (1904) Die “Objektivität” sozialwissenschaftlicher und sozialpolitischer Erkenntnis. In: Weber M (1968) Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre, 3rd edn., foreword by Johannes Winckelmann J. C. B. Mohr-Paul Siebeck, Tübingen, (1st edn., J. C. B. Mohr, Tubinga, 1922), pp 146–214. Translated and edited by Shils EA, Finch HA: “Objectivity” in Social science and social policy, in: Weber M (1949) The methodology of the social sciences. The Free Press, New York, pp 50–112

    Google Scholar 

  84. Weber M (1917) Der Sinn der ‘Wertfreiheit’ der soziologischen und ökonomischen Wissenschaften. In: Weber M Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre, 3rd edn., foreword by Johannes Winckelmann J. C. B. Mohr-Paul Siebeck, Tübingen, 1968 (1st edn., J. C. B. Mohr, Tübingen, 1922), pp 489–540. Translated and edited by Shils EA, Finch HA: The meaning of ‘ethical neutrality’ in Sociology and economics, in: Weber M (1949) The methodology of the social sciences. The Free Press, New York, pp 1–47

    Google Scholar 

  85. Worrall J (2006) Why randomize? Evidence and ethics in clinical trials. In: Gonzalez WJ, Alcolea J (eds) Contemporary perspectives in philosophy and methodology of science. Netbiblo, A Coruña, pp 65–82

    Google Scholar 

  86. Worrall J (2007) Why there’s no cause to randomize. Brit J Philos Sci 58(3):451–488

    Article  Google Scholar 

  87. Wusterhube A, Quante M (eds) (1998) Pragmatic idealism: critical essays on Nicholas Rescher’s system of pragmatic idealism. Rodopi, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Wenceslao J. Gonzalez .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this entry

Cite this entry

Gonzalez, W.J. (2013). Value Ladenness and the Value-Free Ideal in Scientific Research. In: Luetge, C. (eds) Handbook of the Philosophical Foundations of Business Ethics. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1494-6_78

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1494-6_78

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-007-1493-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-007-1494-6

  • eBook Packages: Humanities, Social Sciences and Law

Publish with us

Policies and ethics