Skip to main content

Homology: A Philosophical and Biological Perspective

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:

Abstract

Current discussions of the concept of homology center on metaphysical and epistemological issues: what are homologs, and how can they be discovered? Homology is the relation of common ancestry shared by homologs. Homologs are the “same” parts of two or more organisms under every variation of form or function that are shared due to inheritance from a common ancestor. Homology is the key to phylogeny reconstruction, because the hierarchy of homologs/homologies is isomorphic with the phylogenetic hierarchy of taxa. Consequently, the discussion of homologs as evolving entities shares many parallels with the discussion of species evolution. Homologs are conceptualized as tokens of natural kinds that engage in causal processes of ontogeny, phylogeny, and physiology. Operational criteria for the discovery of homology are the topological relations (connectivity) shared by homologs. These operational criteria are (at least to some degree) grounded in ontogeny, where developmental modules may share the relation of homology. In that sense, the operational criteria for the discovery of homology are aligned with the structure of the causal processes in which the homologs qua tokens of natural kinds engage. The discussion of concepts of partial homology and the complementarity of static (taxic, hierarchical) versus dynamic (developmental, transformational) approaches to homology reveals empirical as well as a semantic components.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   1,099.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

References

  • Audi R (2003) Epistemology. A contemporary introduction to the theory of knowledge, 2nd edn. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Belon P (1555) L’Histoire de la Nature des Oyseaux. Guillaume Cavellat, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Bock WJ (1974) Philosophical foundations of classical evolutionary classification. Syst Zool 22:375–392

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R (1991) Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philos Stud 61:127–148

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R (1999) Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species; new interdisciplinary essays. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 141–185

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN (1999) The units of selection revisited: the modules of selection. Biol Philos 14:67–180

    Google Scholar 

  • Brower AVZ, Schawaroch V (1996) Three steps of homology assessment. Cladistics 12:265–272

    Google Scholar 

  • Cain AJ, Harrison GA (1958) An analysis of the taxonomist’s judgment of affinity. Proc Zool Soc Lond 131:85–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859) The origin of species. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • dePinna MCC (1991) Concepts and tests of homology in the cladistic paradigm. Cladistics 7:367–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt M, Sterelny K (1999) Language and reality. An introduction to the philosophy of language. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré J (1993) The disorder of things. Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupuis C (1984) Willi Hennig’s impact on taxonomic thought. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 15:1–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farris SJ (1983) The logical basis of phylogenetic analysis. In: Platnick NI, Funk VA (eds) Advances in cladistics, vol 2. Columbia University Press, New York, pp 7–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert SF (1988) Developmental biology, 2nd edn. Sinauer Ass, Sunderland

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert SF, Bolker JA (2001) Homologies of process and molecular elements of embryonic construction. In: Wagner GP (ed) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic, San Diego, pp 435–454

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman (1972) Seven strictures on similarity. In: Goodman N (ed) Problems and projects. The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Indianapolis, pp 437–447

    Google Scholar 

  • Grant T, Kluge AG (2004) Transformation series as an ideographic character concept. Cladistics 20:23–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (1999) Squaring the circle: natural kinds with historical essences. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species; new interdisciplinary essays. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 209–228

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack S (1998) Evidence and inquiry. Towards reconstruction in epistemology. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall BK (1994) Introduction. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. The hierarchical basis of comparative biology. Academic, San Diego, pp 1–19

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall BK (1995) Homology and development. Evol Biol 28:1–37

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Hanson NR (1961) Patterns of discovery. An inquiry into the conceptual foundations of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Härlin M (1999) The logical priority of the tree over characters and some of its consequences for taxonomy. Biol J Linn Soc 68:497–503

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hennig W (1950) Grundzüge einer Theorie der Phylogenetischen Systematik. Deutscher Zentralverlag, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig W (1957) Systematik und Phylogenese. In: Hannemann HJ (ed) Bericht über die Hundertjahrfeier der Deutschen Entomologischen Gesellschaft Belin. Akademie Verlag, Berlin, pp 50–71

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennig W (1966) Phylogenetic systematics. University of Illinois Press, Urbana

    Google Scholar 

  • Hey J (2001) Genes, categories, and species. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillis AL (1994) Homology in molecular biology. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. The hierarchical basis of comparative biology. Academic, San Diego, pp 339–368

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1976) Are species really individuals? Syst Zool 25:174–191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1988) Science as a process. An evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1997) The ideal species concept-and why we cannot get it. In: Claridge MF, Dawah HA, Wilson MR (eds) Species: the units of biodiversity. Chapman & Hall, London, pp 358–380

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1999) On the plurality of species: questioning the party line. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species; new interdisciplinary essays. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 23–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Jardine N (1969) The observational and theoretical components of homology: a study based on the morphology of the dermal skull roofs of rhipidistian fishes. Biol J Linn Soc 1:327–361

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keller RA, Boyd RN, Wheeler QD (2003) The illogical basis of phylogenetic nomenclature. Bot Rev 69:93–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1993) The advancement of science. Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitching IJ, Forey PL, Humphries CJ, Williams DM (1998) Cladistics, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kluge AG (1989) A concern for evidence, and a phylogenetic hypothesis of relationships among Epicrates (Boidae, Serpentes). Syst Zool 38:7–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kluge AG (1997) Testability and the refutation and corroboration of cladistic hypotheses. Cladistics 13:81–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kluge AG (2003a) The repugnant and the mature in phylogenetic inference: atemporal similarity and historical identity. Cladistics 19:356–368

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kluge AG (2003b) On the deduction of species relationships: a précis. Cladistics 19:233–239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kluge AG (2004) On total evidence: for the record. Cladistics 20:205–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Körner S (1970) Erfahrung und Theorie. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S (2002) Naming and necessity. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • La Porte J (2004) Natural kinds and conceptual change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lankester ER (1870) On the use of the term homology in modern zoology, and the distinction between homogenetic and homoplastic agreements. Ann Mag Nat Hist 4(6):34–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton P (2004) Inference to the best explanation, 2nd edn. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Luntley M (1999) Contemporary philosophy of thought. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner M, Bunge M (1997) Foundations of biophilosophy. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayhall CW (2002) On Carnap. Wadsworrth/Thomson, Belmont

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin E (2002) A case for scientific realism. In: Balashov Y, Rosenberg A (eds) Philosophy of science. Contemporary readings. Routledge, London, pp 248–281

    Google Scholar 

  • Mindell DP, Meyer A (2001) Homology evolving. Tree 16:434–440

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitter C (1980) The thirteenth annual numerical taxonomy conference. Syst Zool 29:177–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel E (1961) The structure of science. Problems in the logic of scientific explanation. Hartcourt, Brace & World Inc, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Leary MA, Gatesy J, Novacek MJ (2003) Are the dental data really at odds with the molecular data? Morphological evidence for whale phylogeny (re)reexamined. Syst Biol 52:853–864

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Oyama S, Griffiths PE, Gray RD (2001) Introduction: what is developmental systems theory? In: Oyama S, Griffiths PE, Gray RD (eds) Cycles of contingency. Developmental systems and evolution. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 1–11

    Google Scholar 

  • Panchen AL (1994) Richard Owen and the concept of homology. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. The hierarchical basis of comparative biology. Academic, San Diego, pp 21–62

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson C (1982) Morphological characters and homology. In: Joysey KA, Friday AE (eds) Problems of phylogenetic reconstruction. Academic, London, pp 21–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson C (1988) Homology in classical and molecular biology. Mol Biol Evol 5:603–625

    CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Peckham M (1959) The origin of species by Charles Darwin. A variorum text. University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia

    Google Scholar 

  • Platnick NI (1978) Philosophy and the transformation of cladistics. Syst Zool 28:537–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Platts M (1997) Ways of meaning. An introduction to a philosophy of language, 2nd edn. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WV (1964) Word and object. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WV (1994) Natural kinds. In: Stalker D (ed) Grue. The new riddle of induction. Open Court, La Salle, pp 42–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WV (2001) Two dogmas of empiricism. In: Martinich AP, Sosa D (eds) Analytic philosophy, an anthology. Blackwell MS, Malden, pp 450–462

    Google Scholar 

  • Raff RA (1996) The shape of life. Genes, development, and the evolution of animal form. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Raff RA, Sly BJ (2000) Modularity and dissociation in the evolution of gene expression territories in development. Evol Dev 2:102–113

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Reichert C (1837) Über die Visceralbogen der Wirbelthiere im allgemeinen und deren Metamorphosen bei den Vögeln und Säugethieren. Arch Anat Physiol Wiss Med 1837:120–222

    Google Scholar 

  • Remane A (1952) Die Grundlagen des Natürlichen Systems der Vergleichenden Anatomie und der Phylogenetik. Akademische Verlagsgesellschaft, Leipzig

    Google Scholar 

  • Riedl R (1977) Die Ordnung des Lebendigen. Systembedingungen der Evolution. Paul Parey, Hamburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (1988) Fundamentals of comparative biology. Birkhäuser Verlag, Basel

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (1993) The conceptual relationship of ontogeny and phylogeny: the taxic approach. Evol Biol 27:1–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2001) Georges-Louis Leclerc, Compte de Buffon (1707–1788). In: Jahn I, Schmitt M (eds) Darwin & Co. Eine Geschichte der Biologie in Porträts. C.H. Beck Verlag, München, pp 157–175

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2003a) Popper and systematics. Syst Biol 52:259–271

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2003b) Semaphoronts, cladograms, and the roots of total evidence. Biol J Linn Soc 80:167–186

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2004a) The language of systematics, and the philosophy of ‘total evidence’. Syst Biodiv 2:9–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2004b) What happens when the language of science threatens to break down in systematics-A Popperian perspective. In: Williams DM, Forey PL (eds) Milestones in systematics. CRC Press, Boca Raton, pp 5–100

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2004c) Modules, kinds, and homology. J Exp Zool (Mol Dev Evol) 304B:18–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O, Kearney M (2002) Similarity. Biol J Linn Soc 75:59–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth VL (1984) On homology. Biol J Linn Soc 22:13–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M (1988) Philosophy of biology today. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell ES (1982) Form and function. With a new introduction by George V. Lauder. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Sattler R (1990) Towards a more dynamic plant morphology. Acta Biotheor 38:303–315

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sattler R (1996) Classical morphology and continuum morphology: opposition and continuum. Ann Bot 69:249–262

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S (2003) On what there are. In: Shoemaker S (ed) Identity, cause, and mind, expanded edition. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 358–380

    Google Scholar 

  • Shubin NH (1994) The phylogeny of development and the origin of homology. In: Grande L, Rieppel O (eds) Interpreting the hierarchy of nature. Academic, San Diego, pp 201–225

    Google Scholar 

  • Shubin N, Tabin C, Carroll S (1997) Fossils, genes and the evolution of animal limbs. Nature 388:639–648

    Article  CAS  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Sneath PHA, Sokal RR (1973) Numerical taxonomy. WH Freeman, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Soames S (2002) Beyond rigidity. The unfinished semantic agenda of naming and necessity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Soames S (2003) Philosophical analysis in the twentieth century, vol 1, The dawn of analysis. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1981) Evolutionary theory and the ontological status of properties. Philos Stud 40:147–176

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984) Discussion: sets, species, and evolution. Comments on Philip Kitcher’s ‘species’. Philos Sci 51:334–341

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1985) A likelihood justification of parsimony. Cladistics 1:209–233

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (1994) The nature of species. Philos Books 35:9–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swoyer C (2000) Properties. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Winter 2000 edn. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2000/entries/properties/

  • Wägele K (2004) Hennig’s phylogenetic systematics brought up to date. In: Williams DM, Forey PL (eds) Milestones in systematics. CRC Press, Boca Raton, pp 101–125

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1989) The biological concept of homology. Ann Rev Ecol Syst 20:51–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1994) Homology and the mechanisms of development. In: Hall BK (ed) Homology. The hierarchical basis of comparative biology. Academic, San Diego, pp 273–299

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1996) Homologues, natural kinds and the evolution of modularity. Am Zool 36:36–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (2001) Characters, units, and natural kinds. In: Wagner GP (ed) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic, San Diego, pp 1–10

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Westen PH (2000) Process morphology from a cladistic perspective. In: Scotland R, Pennington RT (eds) Homology and systematics. Taylor and Francis, London, pp 124–144

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler WC (1998) Alignment characters, dynamic programming and heuristic solutions. In: DeSalle R, Schierwater B (eds) Molecular approaches to ecology and evolution, 2nd edn. Birkhäuser, Basel, pp 243–251

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wiesemüller G, Rothe H, Henke W (2003) Phylogenetische Systematik. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wiley EO, Siegl-Causey D, Brooks DR, Funk VA (1991) The compleat cladist. A primer of phylogenetic procedures. The University of Kansas Museum of Natural History, Lawrence, Special Publication No. 19

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams DM (2004) Homologues and homology, phenetics and cladistics: 150 years of progress. In: Williams DM, Forey PL (eds) Milestones in systematics. CRC Press, Boca Raton, pp 191–224

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson EO (1965) A consistency test for phylogenies based on contemporaneous species. Syst Zool 14:214–220

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson RA (1999) Realism, essence and kind: resuscitating species essentialism? In: Wilson RA (ed) Species; new interdisciplinary essays. The MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 187–207

    Google Scholar 

  • Winther RG (2001) Varieties of modules: kinds, levels, origins, and behaviors. J Exp Zool (Mol Dev Evol) 291:116–129

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Olivier Rieppel .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this entry

Cite this entry

Rieppel, O. (2015). Homology: A Philosophical and Biological Perspective. In: Henke, W., Tattersall, I. (eds) Handbook of Paleoanthropology. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-39979-4_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics