Skip to main content

Philosophical Health

  • 33 Accesses

Abstract/Summary

In the last decades of the twentieth century, the first contemporary “philosophical counselors” started to appear in Europe and the USA, sometimes equating the idea of “philosophical health” with “spiritual health” or “therapy for the sane,” thus partly reviving traditions of Ancient Greek and Roman philosophical practice. Philosophical health is a state of fruitful coherence between a person’s ways of thinking and speaking and their ways of acting, such that the possibilities for a sublime life are increased and the need for self- and intersubjective flourishing satisfied. One is engaging in philosophical health when one’s behavior is careful (and care-full) in considering not only the physical or psychological individual balance but also a certain idea of what the collective and holistic good of humans and all beings on earth might be. Compared to “physical health” and “psychological health,” the idea of “philosophical health” may still appear to be new. In the twentieth century, the phrase was mostly used as a metaphor to describe sound philosophical thinking versus faulty reasoning, and the meaning has been since then extended to describe the attunement of a way of life with its conceptual evaluative grounding. A first step to understand that the idea of philosophical health is equally as important as physical and psychological health is to recognize that any human being possesses philosophical beliefs, intellectual allegiances, and conceptual concerns, even if not yet fully explicit or compossible.

Keywords

  • Philosophy
  • Health
  • Care
  • Eudynamia
  • Possible
  • Philosophical counseling

This is a preview of subscription content, access via your institution.

References

  • Åkerblom, E. (2020). Governing of the Nation: Generation Pep as biopolitical strategy. Sport, Education and Society, 25(7), 752–763.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Ayers, M. R. (1985). The end of metaphysics and the historiography of philosophy. In A. J. Holland (Ed.), Philosophy, its history and historiography. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentley, J. (1845). Health made easy for the people. London: Darton, Clark and Wright.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1911). Creative evolution. New York: Holt and Co.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • de Miranda, L. (2017). On the concept of creal: The politico-ethical horizon of a creative absolute. In P. de Assis & P. Giudici (Eds.), The dark precursor: Deleuze and artistic research (pp. 510–516). Louvain: Leuven University Press.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • de Miranda, L. (2019). Imagining the future of physical, psychological and philosophical health. Paris: Global Futures Literacy Design Forum, UNESCO.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Miranda, L. (2020). Artificial intelligence and philosophical creativity: From analytics to crealectics. Human Affairs, 30(4), 597–607.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • de Miranda, L. (2021). Thinking into the place of the other: The crealectic approach to philosophical health and care. International Journal of Philosophical Practice, 7, xx.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2008). Journal of Happiness Studies, 9, 1–11.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Diener, E. (1984). Subjective well-being. Psychological Bulletin, 95, 542–575.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Gilmore, R. A. (1999). Philosophical health: Wittgenstein’s method in ‘philosophical investigations’. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grob, G. N. (1983). Mental illness and American Society: 1875–1840. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot, P. (1995). Philosophy as a way of life (M. Chase, Trans.). Oxford/Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot, P. (2014). Discours et mode de vie philosophique. Paris: Belles Lettres.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1995). The fundamental concepts of metaphysics (W. McNeill & N. Walker, Trans.). Bloomington/Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1996). Being and time (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1996). What does it mean to orient oneself in thinking? (1786). In Religion and rational theology (Wood and Di Giovanni, Ed., & Trans., pp. 1–18). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2007). Anthropology, history, and education (G. Zöller & R. B. Louden, Ed., & M. Gregor, et al., Trans.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson, P. C. (2017). Psychological healing: Historical and philosophical foundations of professional psychology. Eugen: Resource Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, M. R., Dignan, M. B., & Shirreffs, J. H. (1984). Life and health. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moran, J. (2018). Aristotle on Eudaimonia (‘Happiness’). Think, 17(48), 91–99.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Nancy, J.-L. (1996). The muses (P. Kamuf, Trans.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pachoumi, E. (2013). The religious-philosophical concept of personal Daimon and the Magico-Theurgic ritual of Systasis in the Greek magical papyri. Philologus, 157(1), 46–69.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Parry, M. (2006). Thomas W. Salmon: Advocate of mental hygiene. American Journal of Public Health, 96(10), 1741.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Peterman, J. F. (1992). Philosophy as therapy: An interpretation and defense of Wittgenstein’s later philosophical project. New York: SUNY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raabe, P. B. (2001). Philosophical counseling: Theory and practice. Westport: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieff, P. (2006). The triumph of the therapeutic. Wilmington: ISI Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, N. (2020). Interview, in Carvalho, S.R., et al. “Our psychiatric future and the (bio)politics of Mental Health: Dialogues with Nikolas Rose” (part 4). Interface, 24. https://doi.org/10.1590/Interface.190732.

  • Shephard, R. J. (2015). An illustrated history of health and fitness. Zürich: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinclair, M. (2017). The actual and the possible: Modality and metaphysics in modern philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    CrossRef  Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1929). Process and reality. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations (G. E. M. Anscombe & R. Rhees, Ed.). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luis de Miranda .

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and Permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this entry

Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

de Miranda, L. (2022). Philosophical Health. In: The Palgrave Encyclopedia of the Possible. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-98390-5_209-1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-98390-5_209-1

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-98390-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-98390-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Reference Behavioral Science and PsychologyReference Module Humanities and Social Sciences