Skip to main content

The Epistemological Subject(s) of Mathematics

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice
  • 23 Accesses

Abstract

Paying attention to the inner workings of mathematicians has led to a proliferation of new themes in the philosophy of mathematics. Several of these have to do with epistemology. Philosophers of mathematical practice, however, have not (yet) systematically engaged with general (analytic) epistemology. To be sure, there are some exceptions, but they are few and far between. In this chapter, I offer an explanation of why this might be the case and show how the situation could be remedied. I contend that it is only by conceiving the knowing subject(s) as embodied, fallible, and embedded in a specific context (along the lines of what has been done within social and feminist epistemology) that we can pursue an epistemology of mathematics sensitive to actual mathematical practice. I further suggest that this reconception of the knowing subject(s) does not force us to abandon the traditional framework of epistemology in which knowledge requires justified true belief. It does, however, lead to a fallible conception of mathematical justification that, among other things, makes Gettier cases possible. This shows that topics considered to be far removed from the interests of philosophers of mathematical practice might reveal to be relevant to them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Throughout the chapter, I will use epistemology to mean analytic epistemology. This clarification is needed in a context like the one of the present volume, which assembles heterogenous contributions belonging to different traditions. As I use the term, analytic epistemology is the theory of knowledge (and justification) in the analytic philosophical tradition of the Anglo-American world – a very different topic compared, for example, with épistémologie in the French tradition, which has to do with the critical and historical study of science and scientific knowledge.

  2. 2.

    To be sure, there are significant exchanges already, albeit not systematic ones – I will turn to some of those in the conclusion. See, for example, Azzouni (2006), Easwaran (2015), and Tanswell and Kidd (2020).

  3. 3.

    Lakatos (1976), Kitcher (1984), and Ferreirós (2016).

  4. 4.

    See, for example, the discussion in Kitcher (1992).

  5. 5.

    This view is explicitly endorsed in Ferreirós (2016) and implicitly assumed in a plethora of works, such as the ones discussing (like Netz’s) the roles of diagrams and notations in mathematics; see, for example (Chemla 2018; Manders 2008).

  6. 6.

    Thanks to Gisele Secco whose criticism helped me realize the importance of this issue.

  7. 7.

    See, for example J.A. Carter and Pritchard (2015), Bengson and Moffett (2011), and Habgood-Coote (2019).

  8. 8.

    Note that this “or” is inclusive. It is the standard disjunctive connective of classical logic: “A or B” is true unless both A and B are false.

  9. 9.

    This lead to knowledge first approaches in epistemology; see Williamson (2000).

  10. 10.

    It is therefore somewhat bizarre that the famous problem of access to abstract objects originally formulated in Benacerraf (1973) involved Goldman’s causal theory of knowledge (more on this later).

  11. 11.

    There are ways to apply them to mathematics, however. See, for example, Clarke-Doane (2020).

  12. 12.

    This has not always been the case. For instance, Descartes’s most radical form of skepticism involved mathematical beliefs, but these do not feature in most contemporary discussions.

  13. 13.

    Frege’s third realm, however, differently from Popper’s third world, only accommodates necessary immutable truths, leaving out the laws of science.

  14. 14.

    As Susan Haack (1979) explains, it is not trivial to pin down the exact locus of the negative feature of the type of subjectivism Popper had in mind. First, the objective/subjective dichotomy can be conceived in several different ways. Second, the notion of intersubjectivity can be placed in between, thus leaving the dichotomy to give space to something more nuanced.

  15. 15.

    For an analysis of the reasons (some of which are institutional in nature) why psychologism started to be conceived as a major sin in the German philosophy departments of the beginning of the twentieth century, see Kusch (1995).

  16. 16.

    To be sure, this is a simplification. Frege critique of psychologism is sophisticated and developed across multiple works.

  17. 17.

    See Sinaceur (2019).

  18. 18.

    And in fact, the most virulent form of psychologism, against which Frege’s criticism were levelled, arises from the application of psychology to logic and mathematics.

  19. 19.

    Think, for example, about conventionalism and Quine’s holistic empiricism. For an elaboration on these ideas, see De Toffoli (2021a).

  20. 20.

    See Burgess (2015, 145) illuminating discussion of different types of indifference in mathematical practice.

  21. 21.

    For a recent endeavor in that direction, see Pettigrew (2021).

  22. 22.

    See De Toffoli (2021b).

  23. 23.

    See Easwaran (2009) and De Toffoli (2021a).

  24. 24.

    In my view, transferability can also be understood in terms of the a priori – given a minimal, fallible conception of a priori justification. In this volume, Danielle Macbeth (2021, 13) also connects transferability to the a priori: “The proof is, as it is sometimes put, “transferable” (Easwaran 2009). Indeed, it is in just this sense that mathematical knowledge is a priori: It is a priori not because it is infallible but because and insofar as it does not rely on empirical evidence, whether that of one’s own senses or that given on the testimony of another.”

  25. 25.

    See Habgood-Coote and Tanswell (2021).

  26. 26.

    See Garavaso (2018).

  27. 27.

    See Longino (2002).

  28. 28.

    See, for example, Soler et al. (2014).

  29. 29.

    Its beginning could be pinned to Kuhn’s (1962) influential work on scientific revolutions; later on, emphasis on practice was prominent among historians and sociologists of science.

  30. 30.

    Although there are important precursor, like (Lakatos 1976), the philosophy of mathematical practice took off much later. See, for example, Mancosu (2008).

  31. 31.

    For instance, this would be in line with Kornblith (2012).

  32. 32.

    See, for example, Hieronymi (2006).

  33. 33.

    Note that such a belief might not be an unqualified belief in the conclusion of the proof but can be the conditional belief that the conclusion is implied by the (explicit or implicit) premises.

  34. 34.

    The example is adapted from the classic Singer (1972).

  35. 35.

    See Chignell (2018).

  36. 36.

    This is also related to John Dewey’s critique to traditional epistemology according to which the subject of knowledge, like the classical subject of perception, is passive.

  37. 37.

    Some steps in this directions have been taken in (Clarke-Doane 2020).

  38. 38.

    See Tanswell (2016).

  39. 39.

    See, for example, Silva (2022).

  40. 40.

    Actually, the Goldbach conjecture says that every even number larger than 2 is the sum of two primes.

  41. 41.

    This is done in Pettigrew (2021).

  42. 42.

    See, for example, Berto and Nolan (2021).

  43. 43.

    A similar approach can be (and has been) adopted with respect to science. See for example the discussion in Bird (2010).

  44. 44.

    Reported in Dummett (1978, xxviii).

  45. 45.

    See, for example, Burgess (1983).

  46. 46.

    There are exceptions, however. Sometimes the truth of certain axioms (such as the axiom of choice) is debated by practicing mathematicians.

  47. 47.

    This is in line with Peirce’s view of mathematics. According to him, in deductive reasoning we start from an “hypothetical state of things and are led to conclude that, however it may be with the universe in other respects, wherever and whenever the hypothesis may be realized, something else not explicitly supposed in that hypothesis will be true invariably” (1998, 212).

  48. 48.

    Even though this story is not universally accepted. For example, it is criticized by constructivist mathematicians. This unveils other instances (in this case linked to intuitionism) in which metaphysical positions can indeed lead one to endorse particular epistemological views.

  49. 49.

    See Avigad (2021).

  50. 50.

    To be sure, this holds nowadays, not of the historical practice.

  51. 51.

    It is worth noting that he proposes a different account for elementary mathematics.

  52. 52.

    Interesting similarities could perhaps be drawn from Putnam’s internal realism, but Ferreirós does not discuss them.

  53. 53.

    Ironically, Justin Clarke-Done (2020) uses examples similar to the ones by Ferreirós to argue for mathematical realism and against mathematical objectivity. In his view, an objective question admits a single answer. He uses the case of non-Euclidean geometry precisely to highlight the non-objective character of mathematics. Although there is much more to be said about this, for reasons of space I have to postpone the discussion to another time.

  54. 54.

    To be sure, this claim can be interpreted in many ways – see Pedersen and Wright (2018).

  55. 55.

    A coherence notion of truth for mathematics is developed by Crispin Wright (1992, 1999). For a detailed discussion on how to apply Wright’s ideas to mathematics, see (S. Shapiro 2007).

  56. 56.

    This example is actually due to Carl Ginet.

  57. 57.

    I changed the notation for the subject and the proposition to make it coherent with the one adopted in the rest of the chapter.

  58. 58.

    See the discussion in De Toffoli (2022).

  59. 59.

    Other relevant approaches in epistemology are ones inspired by the embodied cognition research program, broadly understood to include embedded, enactive, and extended cognition (Shapiro and Spaulding 2021).

References

  • Aberdein A (2023) Deep disagreement in mathematics. Glob Philos 33(17):1–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Aberdein A, Rittberg CJ, Tanswell FS (2021) Virtue theory of mathematical practices: an introduction. Synthese 199(3–4):10167–10180

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Avigad J (2021) Reliability of mathematical inference. Synthese 198:7377–7399

    Google Scholar 

  • Azzouni J (2006) How and why mathematics is unique as a social practice. In: Hersh R (ed) 18 unconventional essays on the nature of mathematics. Springer, pp 201–219

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barton N (manuscript) Mathematical Gettier cases and their implications

    Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf P (1973) Mathematical truth. J Philos 70(19):661–679

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Bengson J, Moffett MA (2011) Knowing how: essays on knowledge, mind, and action. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Berto F, Nolan D (2021) Hyperintensionality. In: Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2021/entries/hyperintensionality/

  • Bird A (2010) The epistemology of science – a bird’s-eye view. Synthese 175(S1):5–16

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess J (1983) Why I am not a nominalist. Notre Dame J Formal Logic 24(1):93–105

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess J (2015) Rigor and Structure. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter J (2019) Exploring the fruitfulness of diagrams in mathematics. Synthese 196:4011–4032

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Carter JA, Pritchard D (2015) Knowledge-how and cognitive achievement. Philos Phenomenol Res 91(1):181–199

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavaillès J (1937) Réflexions Sur le Fondement des Mathématiques. Travaux du IXe Congrès International de Philosophie 6:136–139

    Google Scholar 

  • Cavaillès J (1938) Methode axiomatique et formalisme. Hermann

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemla K (2018) The proof is in the diagram: Liu Yi and the graphical writing of algebraic equations in eleventh-century China. Endeavour 42(2):60–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Chignell A (2018) The ethics of belief. In: Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2018/entries/ethics-belief/

  • Christensen D (2004) Putting logic in its place: formal constraints on rational believing. Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke-Doane J (2020) Morality and mathematics. Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • De Toffoli S (2021a) Groundwork for a fallibilist account of mathematics. Philos Q 71(4):823–844

    Google Scholar 

  • De Toffoli S (2021b) Reconciling rigor and intuition. Erkenntnis 86:1783–1802

    Google Scholar 

  • De Toffoli S (2022) Intersubjective propositional justification. In: Silva P Jr, Oliveira L (eds) Propositional and doxastic justification: new essays on their nature and significance. Routledge, pp 241–262

    Google Scholar 

  • De Toffoli S (2023) Who’s Afraid of Mathematical Diagrams? Philosophers’ Imprint 23(1):1–20

    Google Scholar 

  • De Toffoli S, Fontanari C (2023) Recalcitrant disagreement in mathematics: an endless and depressing controversy in the history of Italian algebraic geometry. Glob Philos 33:1–29

    Google Scholar 

  • De Toffoli S, Giardino V (2014) Roles and forms of diagrams in knot theory. Erkenntnis 79(3):829–842

    Google Scholar 

  • Dean W, Kurokawa H (2014) The paradox of the knower revisited. Ann Pure Appl Logic 165:199–224

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett M (1978) Truth and other enigmas, vol 31. Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Easwaran K (2009) Probabilistic proofs and transferability. Philos Math 17(3):341–362

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Easwaran K (2015) Rebutting and undercutting in mathematics. Philos Perspect 29(1):146–162

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Ferreirós J (2016) Mathematical knowledge and the interplay of practices. Princeton University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garavaso P (2018) Introduction to epistemology. In: Garavaso P (ed) The Bloomsbury companion to analytic feminism. Bloomsbury, pp 3–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Gettier EL (1963) Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis 23(6):121–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert M (2004) Collective epistemology. Episteme 1(2):95–107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gödel K (1964) What is Cantor’s continuum problem? In: Benacerraf P, Putnam H (eds) Philosophy of mathematics: selected readings. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, pp 258–273

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldberg S (2018) To the best of our knowledge: social expectations and epistemic normativity. Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A (1967) A causal theory of knowing. J Philos 64(12):357–372

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman A (1979) What is justified belief? In: Justification and knowledge. D. Reidel Publishing, pp 1–23

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco D, Hedden B (2016) Uniqueness and metaepistemology. J Philos 113(8):365–395

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haack S (1979) Epistemology with a knowing subject. Rev Metaphys XXXIII (2) (130):309–335

    Google Scholar 

  • Habgood-Coote J (2019) Knowledge-how, abilities, and questions. Australas J Philos 97(1):86–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Habgood-Coote J, Tanswell FS (2021) Group knowledge and mathematical collaboration: a philosophical examination of the classification of finite simple groups. Episteme:1–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellman G (1989) Mathematics without numbers: towards a modal-structural interpretation, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hieronymi P (2006) Controlling attitudes. Pac Philos Q 87(1):45–74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1984) The nature of mathematical knowledge. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1992) The naturalists return. Philos Rev 101(1):53–114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith H (2012) On reflection. Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn T (1962) The structure of scientific revolutions. University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch M (1995) Psychologism. Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lackey J (2016) What is justified group belief? Philos Rev 125(3):341–396

    Google Scholar 

  • Lackey J (2020) The epistemology of groups. Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1976) Proofs and refutations. Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leite A (2004) On justifying and being justified. Philos Issues 14:219–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1996) Elusive knowledge. Australas J Philos 74(4):549–567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino H (1998) Feminist epistemology. In: Greco J, Sosa E (eds) The Blackwell guide to epistemology. Blackwell Publishing, Oxford, UK, pp 327–353

    Google Scholar 

  • Longino H (2002) The fate of knowledge. Princeton University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Macbeth D (2010) Diagrammatic reasoning in Euclid’s elements. In: van Kerkhove B, van Bendegem JP, de Vuyst J (eds) Philosophical perspectives on mathematical practice. College Publications

    Google Scholar 

  • Macbeth D (2021) Formal Proofs in Mathematical Practice. In B. Sriraman (Ed.), Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Springer, pp 1–23

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu P (ed) (2008) The philosophy of mathematical practice. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Manders K (2008) The Euclidean diagram. In: Mancosu P (ed) The philosophy of mathematical practice. Oxford University Press, pp 80–133

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Netz R (1999) The shaping of deduction in Greek mathematics: a study in cognitive history. Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Panza M (2012) The twofold role of diagrams in Euclid’s plane geometry. Synthese 186(1):55–102

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Pedersen NJLL, Wright C (2018) Pluralist Theories of Truth. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/truth-pluralist

  • Peirce CS (1998) The essential Peirce. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrew R (2021) Logical ignorance and logical learning. Synthese 198(10):9991–10020

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1968) Epistemology without a knowing subject. In: Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics. Elsevier, pp 333–373

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1967) Mathematics without foundations. J Philos 64(1):5–22

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rittberg C, Tanswell F, Van Bendegem JP (2020) Epistemic injustice in mathematics. Synthese 197(9):3875–3904

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro S (2007) The objectivity of mathematics. Synthese 156(2):337–381

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro L, Spaulding S (2021) Embodied cognition. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2021/entries/embodied-cognition/

  • Sher G (2016) Epistemic friction: an essay on knowledge, truth, and logic. Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Silva P Jr (2022) Knowledge-first theories of justification. In: Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. https://iep.utm.edu/kft-just/

  • Sinaceur H (2019) Jean Cavaillès: Philosophie Mathematique. Vrin

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer P (1972) Famine, affluence, and morality. Philos Public Aff 1(3):229–243

    Google Scholar 

  • Soler L, Zwart S, Lynch M, Israel-Jost V (2014) Science after the practice turn in the philosophy, history, and social studies of science (eds: Soler L, Zwart S, Lynch M, Israel-Jost V). Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa E (2007) A virtue epistemology: volume I: apt belief and reflective knowledge. Oxford University Press UK

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker R (1976) Possible worlds. Noûs 10(1):65–75

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Tanswell F (2016) Proof, rigour & informality: a virtue account of mathematical knowledge. PhD, Philosophy, St. Andrews

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanswell F, Kidd IJ (2020) Mathematical practice and epistemic virtue and vice. Synthese 199(1–2):407–426

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T (2000) Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright C (1992) Truth and objectivity. Harvard University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wright C (1999) Truth: a traditional debate reviewed. In: Blackburn S, Simmons K (eds) Truth. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski L (1994) The inescapability of Gettier problems. Philos Q 44(174):65–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am indebted to the following people for helpful feedback: José Ferrirós, Pieranna Garavaso, Valeria Giardino, Andrea Sereni, and Guido Tana.

This research was financed by MUR – Ministero dell’Università e della Ricerca tramite PRIN PNRR Missione 4 “Istruzione e Ricerca” – Componente C2 Investimento 1.1, “Fondo per il Programma Nazionale di Ricerca e Progetti di Rilevante Interesse Nazionale (PRIN)” Finanziato dall'Unione Europea Next GenerationEU (Progetto: “Understanding Scientific Disagreement and its Impact on Society,” n. P2022A8F82) – CUP I53D23006880001.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Silvia De Toffoli .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

De Toffoli, S. (2024). The Epistemological Subject(s) of Mathematics. In: Sriraman, B. (eds) Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-40846-5_51

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics