Skip to main content

Mathematical Experiments on Paper and Computer

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice

Abstract

We propose a characterization of mathematical experiments in terms of a setup, a process with an outcome, and an interpretation. Using a broad notion of process, this allows us to consider arithmetic calculations and geometric constructions as components of mathematical experiments. Moreover, we argue that mathematical experiments should be considered within a broader context of an experimental research project. Finally, we present a particular case study of the genesis of a geometric construction to illustrate the experimental use of hand drawings and computers in mathematical practice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    As examples for the rich taxonomies of scientific experimentation developed by philosophers of science, see Hacking (1988, 508) and Galison (1988, 525), in which many different relations between experimentation, theory, and instrumentation are discussed. For a more recent overview, see Feest and Steinle (2016). In light of the turn in philosophy of science towards research processes and knowledge generation, one can see the present chapter as a contribution towards bringing together analyses of scientific and mathematical experimental practices.

  2. 2.

    In philosophy of science, we find this distinction under the labels of “theory-driven” and “exploratory” experiments (Steinle 1997, S70); for a discussion of the epistemological significance of exploratory experiments, see Steinle (1997, S72).

  3. 3.

    If the experiment is carried out by hand or as a thought experiment, the experimenter is directly involved in the process, but this should not affect the outcome.

  4. 4.

    Notice that a computation, understood as a process, is only a component of a mathematical experiment; this might answer in part Van Bendegem’s worry that “it seems that it is very difficult to make any sense out of the idea of considering a computation (whether aiming for a numerical result or a visual image) as a form of mathematical experiment” (Van Bendegem 1998, 178).

  5. 5.

    See Starikova and Giaquinto (2018) and Starikova (2023) for a discussion of mathematical thought experiments.

  6. 6.

    See Morgan’s discussion of different “materialities” of experiments in Morgan (2003): material, semi-material, nonmaterial, and mathematical; for a discussion of computer simulations, see Barberousse et al. (2009).

  7. 7.

    Van Bendegem considers such “real-world-experiments” but concludes that “they are quite uninteresting” for mathematics, “rather trivial,” and that “no serious implications should be drawn from them” (Van Bendegem 1998, 179).

  8. 8.

    This view about the context-dependency of experiments is not shared by everyone; Van Bendegem, for example, considers it “slightly, if not simply, odd” (Van Bendegem 1998, 175).

  9. 9.

    See Ferreirós (2015) and Wagner (2017) for general accounts of mathematical practices.

  10. 10.

    In the case of investigations directed at the solution of specific questions or problems, Detlefsen and Arana speak of “directed investigations” (Detlefsen and Arana 2011, 9); see also the notion of a “trial” in a mathematical thought experiment (Starikova and Giaquinto 2018, 263).

  11. 11.

    The iterative nature of experimental research in science has been emphasized by Chang (2004); see also Elliott (2012) for a discussion.

  12. 12.

    These passages are also referred to in Lakatos (1976, 7).

  13. 13.

    Similarly, Dedekind’s contemporary Cantor also speaks of his “experiments [Versuche] which have lasted many years” (Cantor 1883, quoted from the translation in Ewald 1996, 890).

  14. 14.

    See, e.g., Giardino (2018), Carter (2019), and Vold and Schlimm (2020). Because of the predominance of presenting mathematical reasoning in terms of external representations, some philosophers, such as Peirce and Wittgenstein, have claimed that all mathematical reasoning is ultimately based on observations.

  15. 15.

    Heath warns against interpreting the object of the postulates purely as limiting possible constructions (Heath 1968, 124).

  16. 16.

    The background of the development of this result is presented in the form of an interview in Fernández González and Schlimm (2023). Some of the reproductions from Juan’s notebooks shown in that article are also used below with permission from the authors.

  17. 17.

    As reported by Martin Gardner (1983, 82–83), Stanislaw Ulam’s discovery of particular patterns in the distribution of prime numbers (Stein et al. 1964) began in a similar, absent-minded kind of way: During a “long and very boring” conference talk, Ulam “doodled a grid of horizontal and vertical lines on a sheet of paper,” then numbered them in a specific way, circled the prime numbers, and “to his surprise the primes seemed to have an uncanny tendency to crowd into straight lines.” We are thankful to David Waszek for pointing us to this example.

  18. 18.

    Gilbert Labelle, emeritus professor at the Department of Mathematics at the Université du Québec à Montréal, helped Juan with the writing of the published article.

  19. 19.

    These results are presented in Fernández González (2016).

  20. 20.

    For more information about this freeware software package, see https://www.geogebra.org

  21. 21.

    See Starikova and Giaquinto (2018, 273–274) for a discussion of the importance of zooming in and out in mathematical research.

  22. 22.

    This last remark echoes a sentiment about mathematical proofs expressed in Hume’s Treatise (Norton and Norton 2007, 121).

  23. 23.

    This is in line with the application of Lakatos’ account of scientific research programs to mathematics, as discussed in Hallett (1979).

References

  • Baker A (2008) Experimental mathematics. Erkenntnis 68:331–344

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Barberousse A, Franceschelli BWS, Imbert C (2009) Computer simulations as experiments. Synthese 169:557–573

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Borwein J, Bailey D (2004) Mathematics by experiment. Plausible reasoning in the 21st century. A. K. Peters, Natick

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantor G (1883) Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre. Ein mathematisch-philosophischer Versuch in der Lehre des Unendlichen. Teubner, Leipzig. Translation by William Ewald in Ewald (1996), pp 878–920

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter J (2019) Exploring the fruitfulness of diagrams in mathematics. Synthese 196:4011–4032

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Chang H (2004) Inventing temperature: measurement and scientific progress. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Detlefsen M, Arana A (2011) Purity of methods. Philos Impr 11(2):1–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliott KC (2012) Epistemic and methodological iteration in scientific research. Stud Hist Phil Sci 43:376–382

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewald W (1996) From Kant to Hilbert: a source book in mathematics. Clarendon Press, Oxford. Two volumes

    Google Scholar 

  • Feest U, Steinle F (2016) Experiment. In: Humphreys P (ed) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of science. Oxford University Press, pp 274–295

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernández González J (2016) Chemins homothétiques. Bulletin de l’Association Mathématique du Québec 56(2):36–50

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernández González J, Schlimm D (2023) From a doodle to a theorem: a case study in mathematical discovery. J Humanist Math 13(1):4–35

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Ferreirós J (2015) Mathematical knowledge and the interplay of practices. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Galison P (1988) Philosophy in the laboratory. J Philos 85(10):525–527

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner M (1983) Martin Gardner’s sixth book of mathematical diversions from scientific American. University of Chicago Press, Chicago/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Giardino V (2018) Manipulative imagination: how to move things around in mathematics. Theoria 33(2):345–360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1988) On the stability of the laboratory sciences. J Philos 85(10):507–514

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haffner E (2021) The shaping of Dedekind’s rigorous mathematics: what do Dedekind’s drafts tell us about his ideal of rigor? Notre Dame J Form Log 62(1):5–31

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Hallett M (1979) Towards a theory of mathematical research programmes I and II. Br J Philos Sci 30(1–25):135–159

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Heath TL (ed) (1968) The thirteen books of Euclid’s elements, volume 1: introduction and books I, II. Dover Publications. Translated from the text of Heiberg with introduction and commentary by Sir Thomas L. Heath

    Google Scholar 

  • Klarreich E (2018) A tenacious explorer of abstract surfaces. In: Lin T (ed) The prime number consipracy: the biggest ideas in math from quanta. MIT Press, pp 147–154

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1976) In: Worrall J, Zahar E (eds) Proofs and refutations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Larkin JH, Simon HA (1987) Why a diagram is (sometimes) worth ten thousand words. Cogn Sci 11:65–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McEvoy M (2023) The new four color problem revisited. In: Sriraman B (ed) Handbook of the history and philosophy of mathematical practice. Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M (2003) Experiments without material intervention: model experiments, virtual experiments, and virtually experiments. In: Radder H (ed) The philosophy of scientific experimentation. University of Pittsburgh Press, pp 216–235

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Norton DF, Norton MJ (eds) (2007) David Hume: a treatise of human nature. A critical edition, vol 1. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Polya G (1954) Mathematics and plausible reasoning, volume 1: induction and analogy in mathematics. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schlimm D (2013) Axioms in mathematical practice. Philos Math 21(1):37–92

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Secco G (2017) Proofs versus experiments: Wittgensteinian themes surrounding the four-color theorem. In: Silva M (ed) How colours matter to philosophy. Springer, Cham, pp 289–307

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sørensen HK (2010) Exploratory experimentation in experimental mathematics: a glimpse at the PSLQ algorithm. In: Löwe B, Müller T (eds) PhiMSAMP. Philosophy of mathematics: sociological aspects and mathematical practice. College Publications, London, pp 341–360

    Google Scholar 

  • Starikova I (2023) Thought experiments in mathematics: from fiction to facts. In: Sriraman B (ed) Handbook of the history and philosophy of mathematical practice. Springer

    Google Scholar 

  • Starikova I, Giaquinto M (2018) Thought experiments in mathematics. In: Stuart MT, Fehige YJH, Brown JR (eds) The Routledge companion to thought experiments. Routledge, pp 257–278

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein ML, Ulam SM, Wells MB (1964) A visual display of some properties of the distribution of primes. Am Math Mon 71(5):516–520

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Steinle F (1997) Entering new fields: exploratory uses of experimentation. Philos Sci 64(S1):S65–S74

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tappenden J (2008) Chapter 9: mathematical concepts and definitions. In: Mancosu P (ed) The philosophy of mathematical practice. Oxford University Press, pp 256–275

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Bendegem JP (1998) What, if anything, is an experiment in mathematics? In: Anapolitanos D, Baltas A, Tsinorema S (eds) Philosophy and the many faces of science. Rowan & Littlefield Publishers, Ltd, Lanham, pp 172–182

    Google Scholar 

  • Vold K, Schlimm D (2020) Extended mathematical cognition: external representations with non-derived content. Synthese 179(9):3757–3777

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner R (2017) Making and breaking mathematical sense. Histories and philosophies of mathematical practice. Princeton University Press, Princeton/Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The authors would like to thank Jessica Carter, Valeria Giardino, Fenner Tanswell, and David Waszek for comments on a previous version of this chapter. This work was supported in part by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dirk Schlimm .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2024 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

Schlimm, D., Fernández González, J. (2024). Mathematical Experiments on Paper and Computer. In: Sriraman, B. (eds) Handbook of the History and Philosophy of Mathematical Practice. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-40846-5_112

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics