Skip to main content

The Concept of Rights

Its Justification, Language and Relation to Inequality

  • Living reference work entry
  • First Online:
Global Handbook of Inequality

Abstract

The chapter tries to grapple with the concept of rights and navigate through the intellectual debates among the rights’ scholars that have shaped and challenged our understanding of rights. It tries to do this by firstly unpacking the content of rights and explicating rights as claims, privileges, powers and immunities. It then tries to summarise the discussion about what rights are understood to bring about freedom, expression of will or interests and how these conceptions conflict and merge. The third section of the chapter looks at the historical emergence of the language of rights and its effect on how we conceptualise and re-conceptualise our understanding of rights. This is followed by the explanation of philosophical assumptions and their battle about what justifications may be said to correctly ground rights. The deontological, consequential and the recent efforts to combine these or find alternate justifications are also discussed. It then asks the question of what happens when rights conflict with other goods via the intellectual debates and closes with a brief highlight of the criticisms of the rights discourse and its limitations vis-a-vis questions of inequality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Some authors have preferred the term liberties over privileges. For its use and discussion on terms, see Steiner (1996) and Thomson (1990).

  2. 2.

    Article 20 (3): No person accused of any offence shall be compelled to be a witness against himself.

  3. 3.

    H.L.A. Hart (1907–1992), English legal philosopher; Hans Kelsen (1881–1972), Austrian jurist and legal philosopher; Friedrich Carl Von Savigny (1779–1861), German jurist and historian.

  4. 4.

    Joseph (1939–2022) Israeli legal, moral and political philosopher; Caspar Rudolph von Jhering (1818–1892) German jurist; and John Austin (1790–1859) English legal theorist.

  5. 5.

    See Wenar (2017) for a detailed explanation of development and merits of the several functions theory.

  6. 6.

    Exclusionary and inclusionary here refer to finding justifications for rights outside of or within the legal jurisprudence.

  7. 7.

    Adolf Eichmann was a German military officer hanged by the state of Israel for his role in the extermination of the Jews during the Holocaust. (For the details of the trial, see https://www.britannica.com/biography/Adolf-Eichmann)

  8. 8.

    ‘The Grudge informer case’ refers to a wife having informed the Third Reich of her husband’s disapproving comments against the Reich. After the Nazi defeat, both the wife and the judge who had tried and sentenced her husband were indicted for unlawful restriction of another’s liberty. This case became the basis of an intellectual exchange between H.L.A. Hart and Lon L. Fuller. For the summary of the exchange, see Dyzenhaus (2008) (https://www.nyulawreview.org/issues/volume-83-number-4/the-grudge-informer-case-revisited/).

  9. 9.

    For a detailed explication, see Martin (2014).

References

  • Bilgrami, A. (2023). Economic rights, the very idea. The Indian Economic Journal, 71, 1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chetail, V. (2014). Are refugee rights human rights? An unorthodox questioning of the relations between refugee law and human rights law. Human Rights and Immigration, 19, 63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (2002). Sovereign virtue: The theory and practice of equality. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (2014). Rights, justice, and the bounds of liberty: Essays in social philosophy (Vol. 148). Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forst, R. (2012). The right to justification: Elements of a constructivist theory of justice. (J. Flynn, Trans.). Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forst, R. (2016). The justification of basic rights: A discourse-theoretical approach. Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy, 45, 7–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, D. (2014). Pro-Tanto versus absolute rights. Philosophical Forum, 45(4), 375–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L. (1958). Positivism and fidelity to law: A reply to professor Hart. Harvard Law Review, 71(4), 630–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, L. (1964). The morality of law. Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1958). Positivism & the separation of law & morality. Harvard Law Review, 71, 593–629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The concept of law (Clarendon law series). Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H. L., & Waldron, J. (1984). Are there any natural rights? In Arguing About Law (pp. 315–316). Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, J. (2004). Engaging China on human rights. Remarks to The Brookings Institution.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, M. H., & Steiner, H. (2007). Theories of rights: Is there a third way? Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 27(2), 281–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liberto, H. (2014). The moral specification of rights: A restricted account. Law and Philosophy, 33(2), 175–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N., Hacker, P. M. S., & Raz, J. (1977). Rights in legislation. In Hacker & Raz (Eds.), Law, morality and society essays for HLA Hart (pp. 189–209). Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, R. (2014). Overlapping consensus. In J. Mandle & D. A. Reidy (Eds.), The Cambridge Rawls lexicon (pp. 588–594). Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9781139026741.153

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Menon, N. (2004). Recovering subversion: Feminist politics beyond the law. Orient Blackswan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, P. (2015). Specification and moral rights. Law and Philosophy, 34(3), 241–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moyn, S. (2018). Not enough human rights in an unequal world. Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donnell, E. L., & Talbot-Jones, J. (2018). Creating legal rights for rivers. Ecology and Society, 23(1), 7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Donovan, O. (2009). The language of rights and conceptual history. Journal of Religious Ethics, 37(2), 193–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oberdiek, J. (2008). Specifying rights out of necessity. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 28(1), 127–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pennington, K. (1988). Law, legislative authority, and theories of government, 1150–1300. The Cambridge history of medieval political thought c, 350–1450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennington, K. (1998). The history of rights in western thought. Emory Law Journal, 47(1), 237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parekh, B. (1986). The modern conception of right and its Marxist critique. India International Centre Quarterly, 13(3/4), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1984a). On the nature of rights. Mind, XCIII(370), 194–214. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/XCIII.370.194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1984b). Hart on moral rights and legal duties. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 4(1), 123–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. (1998). What we owe to each other. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1980). Equality of what? In S. McMurrin (Ed.), Tanner lectures on human values (Vol. 1). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1982). Rights and agency. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 11, 3–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. (1995). Specifying absolute rights. Arizona Law Review, 37, 209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, H. I. (1996). An essay on rights. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1990). The realm of rights. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tierney, B. (1997). Rights, laws, and infallibility in medieval thought. Variorum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (1989). Rights in conflict. Ethics, 99(3), 503–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenar, L. (2005). The nature of human rights. In Real world justice (pp. 285–293). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wenar, L. (2013). The nature of claim-rights. Ethics, 123(2), 202–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenar, L. (2017). The nature of rights. In Rights: Concepts and contexts (pp. 213–242). Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anagha Ingole .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Section Editor information

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

Ingole, A. (2023). The Concept of Rights. In: Jodhka, S.S., Rehbein, B. (eds) Global Handbook of Inequality. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-97417-6_1-1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-97417-6_1-1

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-97417-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-97417-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Reference Social SciencesReference Module Humanities and Social SciencesReference Module Business, Economics and Social Sciences

Publish with us

Policies and ethics