Skip to main content

Hering, Jean (1890–1966)

  • Living reference work entry
  • First Online:
Encyclopedia of Phenomenology
  • 6 Accesses

Johannes, Hans, Jean: The Lives of an “Old Fellow Phenomenologist”

Husserl (1968, p. 15). See Mehl (2021, pp. 56–58), on Hering’s iter alsaticum. See also Pradelle and Serban (2016) for the introduction to a monographic journal issue on Hering, touching on the many different aspects of his thought.

JohannesFootnote 1 or Hans (as he used to be known before WWI) or Jean Hering (sometimes: Héring) was born in 1890 in Ribeauvillé when Alsace was still part of Germany. Dissatisfied with the teaching at the University of Strasbourg (where he first enrolled to study philology), Hering decided in 1909 to move to Göttingen, where he would stay for 3 years. At the Georgia Augusta, Hering studied with Husserl and attended Adolf Reinach’s seminars (Hering 1939, p. 267); he soon became one of the prominent figures of the phenomenological circle, serving as the president of the recently founded Philosophische Gesellschaftin WS 1912/1913. He wrote his doctoral dissertation on the theory of the a...

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Stein (2014, p. 321).

  2. 2.

    On Hering’s life, see Monseu (2005, pp. 15ff.) and Dupont (2014, pp. 218ff.).

  3. 3.

    The volume exists also in Italian (Hering 2010) and Spanish translation (2019). A new French edition of the text will soon be available.

  4. 4.

    On Hering’s phenomenology of dream and “dreaming consciousness,” which we will not be able to discuss here, see Serban (2016) and Zippel (2016, pp. 188–190).

  5. 5.

    Hering refers the reader to the opening page of Reinach’s lecture “On Phenomenology,” originally published in Reinach 1921, p. 379 (now in Reinach 1989, p. 531).

  6. 6.

    […] “lorsque Reinach nous demanda si selon nôtre impression Husserl enseignait la même chose que lui, nous ne pûmes que lui répondre: Pour vous, la phénoménologie est une méthode, pour Husserl une branche de la philosophie. Nous eussions peut-être mieux fait de dire que la méthode […] était la même, mais que Husserl était avant tout préoccupé de la mettre au service d’une discipline fondamentale qu’il appelait phénoménologie” (Hering 1939, p. 368).

  7. 7.

    For a first systematic assessment of Hering’s dissertation, see De Santis (2021a).

  8. 8.

    “Sodann sind die phänomenologischen Bedingungen der Möglichkeit des Erscheinens einer Welt als zusammenhängende Totalität von realem Seienden zu untersuchen, die sich als die wirkliche und einzige ausgibt.”

  9. 9.

    Hering calls the c-definition of phenomenology l’emploi large du terme, “the term used in a broad manner” (Hering 1926b, p. 77). For a most balanced analysis of Hering’s position vis-à-vis Husserl, see Mehl (2021, pp. 58–64).

  10. 10.

    […] “le primat épistémologique de l’étude de la conscience, accepté par des élèves bien plus nombreux que le soupçonnait peut-être le professeur, se transforma en primat métaphysique de la conscience.”

  11. 11.

    “Ce que Husserl affirme d’une manière non équivoque, c’est que le ‘cogito’ peut exister sans entrainer par là l’existence du κόσμος. Acceptons cette thèse, quoiqu’elle contienne quelque chose de plus que l’affirmation cartésienne de l’indubitabilité du ‘cogito.’ Mais alors, il s’agit de savoir, si vraiment elle n’est pas réversible. Pourquoi les ‘choses’ auraient-elles besoin de la conscience, non seulement pour être pensées, mais pour exister?”

  12. 12.

    The “necessary positing of a fact” and “the positing of a necessary fact” are two different things (Hering 2015, pp. 40, 47). Husserl would be confusing the (epistemological nature of the) former with the (metaphysical nature of the) latter.

  13. 13.

    See Monseu (2005, pp. 51, 53), who interprets Hering’s claims about the metaphysical nature of Husserl’s statements in §49 as revolving around the question of transcendental idealism. The same holds true of Avé-Lallemant (1975, p. 29), who, for example, never raises the question about the meaning of the term metaphysics in Hering. For an interpretation that differs from ours, see Tedeschini (2014, pp. 248–249) and (2018, p. 395); on the sense of Hering’s “realism,” see the contribution by Boccaccini (2016).

  14. 14.

    And it is only at this point, Hering would further add that the metaphysical problem of the existence of religious objects can be addressed as well (Hering 1926b, p. 78). On the development of Husserl’s concept of metaphysics, see De Santis (2021b) and in particular Trizio (2019, 2021).

  15. 15.

    There already exist a Spanish (Hering 2004), an Italian (Hering 2014), and an English (Hering 2021) translation of the text. In the following, I will always translate Wesenheit with “essentiality” and not with “ideal quality” (as is done in the English edition, following Ingarden 1966, p. 309). There are three reasons for doing so. One, because Wesenheit implies a reference to Wesen (on the basis of which it is constructed), which is lost in the phrase “ideal quality.” Two, because for Hering, “qualities” are always individual and belong to either a real or an ideal “individual” object, a quality always being a “concretized Wesenheit” (Hering 1921, p. 514). Three, because Hering explicitly distinguishes between eidos (or Wesenheit) and “ideal objects.” Thus if we translate Wesenheit with ideal quality, it would follow that ideal-individual objects have ideal-individual qualities that are in turn the result of the concretization of ideal qualities!

  16. 16.

    Hering quotes directly from the beginning of Ideas and explicitly uses Husserl’s definition of Wesen (Hering 1921, p. 497; Hering 2021, pp. 56–57). He also writes that he is using the term Idee according to “Husserl’s earlier terminology” (Hering 1921, p. 533; Hering 2021, p. 91), the one from the Logical Investigations. For a meticulous reconstruction of these relations and differences, see De Santis (2014, pp. 59–61). On the relations and differences between Husserl’s terminology and Hering’s, see, for example, Seifert (1996, Ch. I); Ferrari (2001, p. 64); and De Santis (2014, pp. 60–61).

  17. 17.

    In §15 of Ideen, Husserl defines the individuum as a “this-here, whose material essence is a concretum,” namely, an “absolutely independent essence” (Hua III/1, p. 35; Husserl 2014, p. 30).

  18. 18.

    For example, during his quick discussion of Hering, Patočka speaks of the Sosein as “divided into (se člení na) τί and ποῖον” (Patočka 1965, p. 182).

  19. 19.

    Stein explains this point as follows: “τί εἶναι and ποῖον εἶναι coincide, if we mean by ποῖον εἶναι the sum total of the essential characteristics in the order which is imposed upon them by the τί” (Stein 1962, p. 146; Stein 2002, p. 151).

  20. 20.

    With this account, and despite the language of “features” (Züge), Hering avoids assuming the essence as a set of properties instantiated or inhering in a bare substratum.

  21. 21.

    Hering’s distinction might remind the reader of the more traditional one between essentialia, attributa, and modi. The attributa do not belong to the essence of an object but are grounded in it (the essence being their sufficient condition); the modi are grounded in the essentialia only as possibilities, since their obtaining requires an external cause (see the role these distinctions play in C. Wolff according to Pichler 1910, pp. 24–25).

  22. 22.

    On this, see De Santis (2015, pp. 164–165); see Fréchette (2015, p. 160), for a different perspective on the core.

  23. 23.

    At this point, one could raise the question about the consistency of Hering’s rebuttal of Chestov’s criticism of Husserl. Is not Hering reducing the ontological “thickness” of individual objects (especially “real” ones) to be nothing other than a connection of morphai, i.e., of individually realized nonindividual eide?

  24. 24.

    It is important to stress that although Essenz stands in opposition to Existenz, the content of the idea (what Hering calls its “total configuration”) (Hering 1921, p. 530; Hering 2021, p. 88) includes – for example, in the case of empirical objects – a “hic-et-nunc moment.” In sum, the Essenz is not indifferent to the individuals’ mode of being.

  25. 25.

    On the basis of a still unpublished letter from Ingarden to Hering, it can be inferred that Hering himself regarded the “Essential Questions” as an “improvement” (Fortschritt) on his own investigations (Ingarden 1926, p. 1). For a discussion of Ingarden’s ontology, see, for example, Bertolini (2016).

  26. 26.

    See Borden Sharkey (2016) on the way in which Stein uses Hering’s essentialities.

  27. 27.

    See Bancalari (2015, pp. 39–48), on Hering’s religious philosophy in connection with Max Scheler. For an introduction to Hering, see Hernández Marcelo and Herrero Hernández (2019). On the problem of God in Husserl, see, for example, Ales Bello (2005), Serban (2020), and Trizio (2022).

References

  • Avé-Lallemant, E. 1975. Die Antithese Freiburg-Göttingen in der Geschichte der Phänomenologie. In Die Münchener Phänomenologie, ed. H. Kuhn, E. Avé-Lallemant, and R. Gladiator, 19–38. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bancalari, S. 2015. Logica dell’epochè: Per un’introduzione alla fenomenologia della religione. Pisa: ETS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertolini, S. 2016. Idea ed essenza nello sviluppo dell’ontologia di Roman Ingarden. Discipline filosofiche 26: 171–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boccaccini, F. 2016. De Reinach à Levinas: Hering et le réalisme phénoménologique. Revue de théologie et de philosophie 148: 433–448.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borden Sharkey, S. 2016. Edith Stein’s use of Hering’s Wesenheit to move through phenomenology to metaphysics. Discipline filosofiche 26: 193–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chestov, L. 1926. Memento mori: Á propos de la théorie de la connaissance d’Edmond Husserl. Revue philosophique de la France et de l’étranger 101: 5–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1927. Qu’est-ce que la vérité? (Ontologie et éthique). Revue philosophique 1: 36–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad-Martius, H. 1957. Das Sein. München: Kösel Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Santis, D. 2014. L’idea della fenomenologia come fenomenologia delle Idee: Su di un Peri Ideon tra Gottinga e Monaco. In Di Idee ed essenze: Un dibattito su fenomenologia e ontologia (1921–1930), with essays by Jean Hering, Roman Ingarden, and Herbert Spiegelberg, ed. D. De Santis, 7–139. Mimesis: Milan.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Wesen, Eidos, Idea: Remarks on the “Platonism” of Jean Hering and Roman Ingarden. Studia Phaenomenologica 15: 155–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Jean Hering on Eidos, Gegenstand, and Methexis: Phenomenological adventures and misadventures of “Participation.”. Discipline filosofiche 26: 145–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021a. “An Ocean of Difficult Problems”: Husserl and Jean Hering’s Dissertation on the A Priori in R. H. Lotze. Husserl Studies 37: 19–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021b. The development of Husserl’s concept of metaphysics. In The Husserlian Mind, ed. H. Jacobs, 481–493. London/New York: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dupont, C. 2014. Phenomenology in French Philosophy: Early encounters. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Jean Héring and the introduction of Husserl’s Phenomenology to France. Studia Phaenomenologica 15: 129–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ferrari, D. 2001. Consciousness in time. Heidelberg: C. Winter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fréchette, G. 2015. Essential Laws: On ideal objects and their properties in early phenomenology. In Objects and pseudo-objects: Ontological deserts and jungles from Brentano to Carnap, ed. B. Leclercq, S. Richard, and D. Seron, 143–166. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hauter, Ch. 1957. Hommage de la Faculté de Théologie de Strasbourg au Prof. Jean Héring. Revue d’histoire et de philosophie religieuse 37 (1): 1–2.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. 1967. Sein und Zeit. GA 2. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Being and time. Trans. J. Stambaugh. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, H. 1914. Lotzes Lehre vom Apriori. Eine philosophische Studie. Strasbourg: Fondation du Chapitre de Saint-Thomas (unpublished).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hering, J. 1921. Bemerkungen über das Wesen, die Wesenheit und die Idee. Jahrbuch für Phänomenologie und phänomenologische Forschung 4: 495–543.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1926a. Phénoménologie et philosophie religieuse. Paris: Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1926b. Jean Hering, Phénoménologie et philosophie religieuse. Revue d’histoire et de philosophie religieuse 1: 73–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1927. Sub specie aeterni: Réponse à une critique de la philosophie de Husserl. Revue d’histoire et de philosophie religieuse 7: 351–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1932. E. Levinas, La théorie de l’intuition dans la phénoménologie de Husserl. Revue philosophique de la France et de l’étranger 113: 474–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1939. La phénoménologie d’Edmund Husserl il y a trente ans: Souvenirs et réflexions d’un étudiant de 1909. Revue Internationale de Philosophie 1 (2): 366–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1940. Le mouvement phénoménologique aux Etats Unies. Revue d’histoire et de philosophie religieuse 21: 232–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1943. Littérature phénoménologique récente. Revue d’histoire et de philosophie religieuse 23: 237–245.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1947. Concerning image, idea, and dream. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 8 (2): 188–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1952. Edith Stein, Werke II. Endliches und ewiges Sein. Revue d’histoire et de philosophie religieuse 2: 157–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1959. Souvenirs et réflexions. In Edmund Husserl: 1859–1959, ed. H.L. Van Breda and J. Taminiaux, 26–28. La Haye: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1960. De Max Scheler à Hans Reiner: Remarques sur la théorie des valeurs morales dans le mouvement phénoménologique. Revue d’histoire et de philosophie religieuse 40: 152–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Observaciones sobre la esencia, la esencialidad, y la idea. Trans. R. Rovira. Madrid: Ediciones encuentro.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Fenomenologia e religione. A cura di G. Di Salvatore. Verona: Centro Studi Campostrini.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Osservazioni sull’essenza, l’essenzialità, e l’Idea. Trans. D. De Santis. In Di Idee ed essenze: Un dibattito su fenomenologia e ontologia (1921–1930), with essays by Jean Héring, Roman Ingarden, and Herbert Spiegelberg, ed. D. De Santis, 141–195. Mimesis: Milan.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Phänomenologie als Grundlage der Metaphysik (1917). ed. S. Camiller, Trans. A. Iyer. Studia Phaenomenologica, 15, 35–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2019. Fenomenología y filosofía religiosa. Estudio sobre la teoría de la conciencia religiosa. Trad. Francisco Javier Herrero Hernández, Jimmy Hernández Marcelo. Madrid: Ediciones Universidad San Dámaso.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021. Remarks concerning essence, ideal quality, and idea. Trans. A. Szylewicz. Phenomenological Investigations, Vol. 1, 51–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hernández Marcelo, J. 2016. Hering y Chestov: el primer debate sobre la fenomenología en Francia. Cuadernos salmantinos de filosofía 43: 137–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hernández Marcelo, J., and F.J. Herrero Hernández. 2019. La contribución de Jean Héring à la fenomenología y la filosofía de la religión. In Fenomenología y filosofía religiosa. Estudio sobre la teoría de la conciencia religiosa, ed. J. Héring, XI–XXIX.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hua III/1: Husserl, E. (1976). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie, ed. K. Schuhmann. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 1968. Briefe an Roman Ingarden. Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Ideas. Trans. D. Dahlstrom. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. 1925. Essentiale Fragen. Ein Beitrag zum Wesensproblem. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 7: 125–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1926. Brief an Jean Hering (4. IV. 1926). Strasbourg: Fondation du Chapitre de Saint-Thomas. (unpublished).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966. Jean Héring (1890–1966). Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 27: 308–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, E. 1930. La théorie de l’intuition dans la phénoménologie de Husserl. Paris: Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. The theory of intuition in Husserl’s Phenomenology. Trans. A. Orianne. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mehl, É. 2021. La “philosophie religieuse” de Jean Héring. Revue d’histoire et de philosophie religieuse 1: 55–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzger, A. 1925. Der Gegenstand der Erkenntnis. Studien zur Phänomenologie des Gegenstandes (Erster Teil). Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung 7: 613–770.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monseu, N. 2005. Les usages de l’intentionnalité: Recherches sur la première réception de Husserl en France. Louvain/Paris/Dudley: Éditions de l’institut supérieur de philosophie.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patočka, J. 1965. Husserlova nauka o eidetickém názoru a její současní kritikové. In Fenomenologické spisy II, ed. J. Patočka. OIKYMENH: Praha 2009, 175–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pichler, H. 1910. Ueber Ch. Wolffs Ontologie. Leipzig: Dürr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pöll, W. 1936. Wesen und Wesenserkenntnis. Untersuchungen mit besonderer Berücksichtigung der Phänomenologie Husserls und Schelers. München: Verlag von Ernst Reinhardt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradelle, D., and C. Serban. 2016. Jean Héring – de l’eidétique à la phénoménologie de la religion: Présentation du dossier. Revue de théologie et de philosophie 1: 401–407.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinach, A. 1921. Gesammelte Schriften, ed. by his students. Halle: Max Niemeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Sämtliche Werke. Band I, ed. K. Schuhmann and B. Smith. München/Hamden/Wien: Philosophia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seifert, J. 1996. Sein und Wesen. Heidelberg: C. Winter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Serban, C. 2016. De l’eidétique à la phénoménologie du rêve. Revue de théologie et de philosophie 1: 481–496.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. 1930. Über das Wesen der Idee. Eine ontologische Untersuchung. Jahrbuch für Phänomenologie und phänomenologische Forschung 11: 1–238.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, E. 1962. Endliches und ewiges Sein. Versuch eines Aufstieges zum Sinn des Seins. Freiburg/Basel/Wien: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Life in a Jewish family. Trans. J. Koeppel. Washington, DC: ICS Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. On the problem of empathy. Trans. W. Stein. Washington, DC: ICS Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Finite and eternal being an attempt at an ascent to the meaning of being. Washington, DC: ICS Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010a. Aus dem Leben einer jüdischen Familie und weitere autobiographische Beiträge. ESGA 1. Freiburg/Basel/Wien: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010b. Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie und der Geisteswissenschaften. ESGA 6. Freiburg/Basel/Wien: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. “Freiheit und Gnade” und weitere Beiträge zu Phänomenologie und Ontologie. ESGA 9. Freiburg/Basel/Wien: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Zum Problem der Einfühlung. ESGA 5. Freiburg/Basel/Wien: Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tedeschini, M. 2014. La controversia idealismo-realismo (1907–1931): Breve storia concettuale della contesa tra Husserl e gli allievi di Gottinga e Monaco. Lexicum philosophicum 2: 236–260.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018. La controversia idealismo-realismo in fenomenologia: Un nuovo caso di studio per la Konstellationsforschung? Studi germanici 14: 391–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trizio, E. 2019. Husserl’s early concept of metaphysics as the ultimate science of reality. The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy 17: 309–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021. Philosophy’s nature: Husserl’s phenomenology, natural science, and metaphysics. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendel, F. 1966. Hommage de la Faculté de Théologie de Strasbourg à Jean Héring. Revue d’histoire et de philosophie religieuse 46 (2): 111–115.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zippel, N. 2016. Dreaming consciousness: A contribution from phenomenology. Rivista internazionale di filosofia e psicologia 2: 180–201.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The present work was supported by the Czech Science Foundation, financing the project: “Intentionality and Person in Medieval Philosophy and Phenomenology” (GAČR 21-08256S), and by the European Regional Development Fund-Project “Creativity and Adaptability as Conditions of the Success of Europe in an Interrelated World” (No. CZ.02.1.01/0.0/0.0/16_019/0000734).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniele De Santis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this entry

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this entry

De Santis, D. (2023). Hering, Jean (1890–1966). In: de Warren, N., Toadvine, T. (eds) Encyclopedia of Phenomenology. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-47253-5_35-1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-47253-5_35-1

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-47253-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-47253-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Reference Religion and PhilosophyReference Module Humanities and Social SciencesReference Module Humanities

Publish with us

Policies and ethics