Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy

Living Edition
| Editors: Henrik Lagerlund

Jacques Almain

  • Thomas M. IzbickiEmail author
Living reference work entry
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-024-1151-5_252-2
  • 2 Downloads

Abstract

Jacques Almain was one of the most prominent exponents of conciliarism in the early sixteenth century. He studied the arts and theology at the University of Paris, receiving his doctorate in 1512. Almain wrote extensively on issues of philosophy and ethics. When the Council of Pisa met in 1512, it tried to depose Pope Julius II (1503–1513); and when Cajetan attacked the council on the pope’s behalf, the university chose Almain to reply. His arguments were grounded in the belief that the church was able to act in its own defense, even against its visible head, the pope. Cajetan replied, but Almain did not live to respond in turn. He died unexpectedly in 1515. John Mair, his teacher, answered Cajetan instead, advocating conciliar supremacy in the church.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in to check access.

Bibliography

Primary Sources

  1. Jacques, A. (1506). Embammata phisicalia seu embammata totius philosophiae naturalis. Paris: Jehan Petit.Google Scholar
  2. Jacques, A. (1508). Consequentiae. Paris: Bernard Aubri.Google Scholar
  3. Jacques, A. (1510). Moralia. Egidius de Gourmont: Paris.Google Scholar
  4. Jacques, A. (1512). Libellus de auctoritate ecclesie seu sacrorum conciliorum eam representantium. Paris: Jehan Branion.Google Scholar
  5. Jacques, A. (1516). In tertium Sententiarum. Paris: Johannes Granion.Google Scholar
  6. Jacques, A. (1518). Opuscula. Paris: Nicolaus de Pratis (Contains: Moralia, In tertium Sententiarum librum, De paenitentia, Expositio circa decisiones M. Guillermi Ockham super potestate summi pontificis, Libellus de auctoritate ecclesie, Vespersarum quaestio, Dictata super sententias magistri Roberti Holcot).Google Scholar
  7. Jacques, A. (1997a). A book concerning the authority of the church. In: Conciliarism and papalism (trans: Burns, J. H. & Izbicki, T. M.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Jacques, A. (1997b). Question at Vespers. In: J. Kraye (Ed.), Cambridge translations of renaissance philosophical texts (vol. 2: Political philosophy, pp. 13–35). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar

Secondary Sources

  1. Burns, J. H. (1991). Scholasticism: Survival and revival. In J. H. Burns & M. Goldie (Eds.), The Cambridge history of political thought 1450–1700. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Burns, J. H. (1994). Jacques Almain on “dominium”: A neglected text. In A. E. Bakos (Ed.), Politics, ideology and the law in early modern Europe: Essays in honor of J. H. M. Salmon. Rochester: University of Rochester Press.Google Scholar
  3. Izbicki, T. M. (1999). Cajetan’s attack on parallels between church and state. Cristianesimo nella storia, 29, 81–89.Google Scholar
  4. Kennedy, L. A. (1993). The philosophy of Robert Holcot, fourteenth-century skeptic. Lewiston: Edwin Mellen.Google Scholar
  5. Kraye, J. (1988). Moral philosophy. In C. B. Schmitt et al. (Eds.), The Cambridge history of renaissance philosophy (pp. 303–386). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Oakley, F. (1998). The absolute and ordained power of god in sixteenth- and seventeenth-century theology. Journal of the History of Ideas, 59, 437–461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Oakley, F. (2003). The conciliarist tradition: Constitutionalism in the catholic church 1300–1870. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Shogimen, T. (2014). Ockham, Almain, and the idea of heresy. In K. Bollermann, T. M. Izbicki, & C. J. Nederman (Eds.), Religion, power and resistance from the eleventh to the sixteenth centuries: Playing the heresy card (pp. 153–168). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Alexander LibraryRutgers State University of New JerseyNew BrunswickUSA