Skip to main content

Defining and Measuring Human Well-Being

  • Reference work entry
  • First Online:
Global Environmental Change

Part of the book series: Handbook of Global Environmental Pollution ((EGEP,volume 1))

Abstract

Human well-being is a complex concept that has been contested across the social and political sciences. This chapter considers three broad approaches to the concept and measurement of human well-being along with their respective merits from a cross-disciplinary perspective. The three broad approaches in question embrace utility (happiness, desire fulfillment, and preference), material well-being (most notably, income and resources), and “list-orientated” views (needs, rights, and capabilities). The final part of the chapter explicitly links human well-being with environmental issues and various notions of sustainable development. It is suggested that the idea of “sustainable human development” can help resolve the apparent tension between poverty reduction (involving more consumption) on the one hand and environmental conservation and sustainability on the other. Above all, a more comprehensive account of human well-being is required to bridge the gap between mental and physical states and to take note of the environmental and material basis of sustainable well-being.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 399.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 499.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The World Health Organization defines health in terms of well-being: “Health is a state of complete physical, mental and social wellbeing and not merely the absence of disease or infirmity” (WHO 1948, p. 1). Of course, it is possible to challenge such concepts. Many people choose lifestyles with unhealthy elements (drinking alcohol, smoking cigarettes); and on occasions even apparently “healthy” activities can be harmful (over dieting, excessive exercise) (see Clark 2002, 2005).

  2. 2.

    Secondary definitions refer to the “satisfactory condition (of a thing)” and “individual instances of welfare.” The focus here is entirely on human well-being. I also set aside the discussion of well-being and morality (except insofar as moral conduct is thought to contribute to living and faring well). See Griffin (1986), Crisp and Hooker (2000), and Crisp (2008) on morality and well-being.

  3. 3.

    Jeremy Bentham’s (1789) account of happiness as the sole basis of goodness devotes an entire chapter to cataloging 14 distinct types of pleasure and 12 kinds of pain. Some of the sources of these pleasures and pains are reminiscent of various capabilities, needs, and rights.

    There is a strong case for installing “time” in terms of the duration of relevant experiences (Clark and Hulme 2010) and “sustainability” (discussed presently) as additional features of well-being.

  4. 4.

    In contrast to the former, the latter usually takes the form of an independent assessment of human flourishing or need. An analogous distinction relates to “hedonic” and “eudaimonic” well-being (see Ryan and Deci 2001).

  5. 5.

    Gay Meeks has reminded me that Sen later recognizes this criticism will not apply if the person in question has an “undentable” cheery disposition. The argument that the disabled will become “doubly worse off” also depends on the implicit assumption that other people’s utility functions will not be adversely affected.

  6. 6.

    At the extreme we might regard some types of utility (e.g., the pleasure or satisfaction derived from subjecting another person to a lesser liberty) as “wrong” and argue the case for striking these pleasures or desires from utility functions (e.g., Rawls 1971, p. 31). Jim Griffin argues that similar criticisms apply to the desire fulfillment view of utility which is considered presently. He considers the case for excluding “immoral desires” such as those based on sadistic wishes (Griffin 1986, Chap. 2).

  7. 7.

    Consider Mill’s (1861) classic conclusion: “It is better to be a human being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be a Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied. And if the fool, or pig, is of a different opinion, it is because they only know their own side of the question” (p. 140). Sugden (2006, pp. 43–4) reminds us that Mill’s utilitarianism should not be confused with his liberalism: Mill holds that social evils such as drunkenness and gambling should be permitted (as long as no harm comes to others), even though these activities are harmful to the agent’s own happiness and well-being.

  8. 8.

    The adaptation argument is considered shortly.

  9. 9.

    The “revealed preference” approach has helped to make economics a respectful empirical science, although it has been criticized by some economists (e.g., Hahn and Hollis 1979, Chap. 1; Meeks 1991). In particular, Sen (2002, esp. Chap. 3) has expressed concerns about the “internal consistency of choice” by maintaining that some choices violate basic axioms of rationality such as transitivity.

  10. 10.

    In particular, there may be a case for excluding immoral or sadistic desires such as “hate, envy, spite, prejudice and intolerance” (see Griffin 1986, pp. 24, 25–26) – especially if these desires are permitted to affect other people’s well-being.

  11. 11.

    See, for example, Brickman and Campbell (1971); Diener, Lucas, and Scollon (2006); and Layard (2006, Chap. 4). The hedonic treadmill is consistent with the “Easterlin Paradox” – the finding that rapid growth in the advanced economies since the 1950s is associated with stable or declining happiness scores (Easterlin 1974).

  12. 12.

    In theory, the hedonic treadmill also works in reverse (a decline in income produces lower aspirations), although there is some evidence to suggest that adaptation is asymmetric: people adapt more to a rise in income but less so to a decline in income (see Clark 2012).

  13. 13.

    Nozick is also concerned that an experience machine would limit the world to a manmade construct that prevents the exploration of deeper realities (although the experience can be simulated).

  14. 14.

    The distinctions between experienced utility (including instant and remembered forms) and decision utility employed in this section have origins in the writings of Daniel Kahneman (e.g., Kahneman et al. 1997) and also feature in several of the chapters collected in Kahneman, Diener, and Schwartz (1999). Kahneman’s use of these terms has evolved over the years.

  15. 15.

    Layard (2006, pp.17–20) and Colander (2007) describe some of the breakthroughs in neuroscience and brain wave analysis that make the hedonimeter more of a practical possibility than a farfetched proposal.

  16. 16.

    In addition to remembered utility (retrospective happiness), other measures might include perceptions of current or future happiness as well as “life satisfaction” which Kahneman believes captures something more than experienced utility (see Jarden 2011).

  17. 17.

    The following discussion sets aside domain-specific questions that focus on subjective impressions of particular aspects of life (health, relationships, housing, work, finances, children, etc).

  18. 18.

    See WVS (2011) and questions V10 and V21. For a catalog of single-item happiness and life satisfaction questions derived from leading surveys, see Dolan, Peasgood, and White (2008, appendix A).

  19. 19.

    The British Household Survey and Russian Longitudinal Monitoring Survey both have scales with neutral middle points.

  20. 20.

    Studies show that single-item measures possess “moderate reliability” over time and correlate with external factors and other subjective well-being measures. For further discussions, see Diener (1984) and Krueger and Schkade (2008).

  21. 21.

    Many attempts have been made to measure subjective well-being at the national, regional, and global levels. Noteworthy examples include the UK’s so-called “happiness” index (Self et al. 2012), the Cambridge Well-Being Institute’s study of happiness levels across Europe (Huppert and So 2013), and the analysis of satisfaction data from the Gallup World Survey (Deaton 2008). In 2012 the first World Happiness Report was launched at the United Nations (Halliwell et al. 2012).

  22. 22.

    A fact long recognized by economists and their critics alike. See, for example, Hicks and Streeten (1979), Oswald (1997), and Daly (2006, p. 657).

  23. 23.

    Various adjustments to GNP have been proposed. A noteworthy example is William Nordhaus and James Tobin’s “Measure of Economic Welfare” discussed by Hicks and Streeten (1979) and Daly (2006).

  24. 24.

    A minimally decent form of life is typically defined in terms of health, nutrition, and literacy levels (Stewart 1996, p. 46). While BNA II endorses broader goals, practical applications tend to focus on material goods and services (Stewart 2006, p. 16).

  25. 25.

    Elsewhere I have argued that some other accounts of need (especially “human need,” “genuine needs,” and “authentic needs”) are susceptible to paternalism (Clark 2002, 2012, Chap. 3).

  26. 26.

    The quotation here is from David Ross’s translation of Nicomachean Ethics, book I (Oxford World Classics), 1095b5–7, which is slightly different from the translation provided by Irwin cited in the bibliography. I have stuck with the Ross translation, as it is frequently referred to in the well-being literature by Sen and others.

  27. 27.

    Several companion measures such as the Human Poverty Index, Gender-Related Index, and inequality-adjusted HDI have been developed (http://hdr.undp.org/en/statistics/indices/). Early attempts to develop a Political Freedom Index and Human Freedom Index were discontinued on the grounds that they were based on “qualitative judgments, not quantifiable empirical data” (UNDP 2000, p. 91).

  28. 28.

    At the time of writing, country ranking only appeared to be available through Wikipedia. The project website includes a useful summary of the EVI, including technical details of the mechanics of the index and a description of the 50 “smart indicators” utilized. (http://www.sopac.org/index.php/environmental-vulnerability-index).

  29. 29.

    The UNDP (2011) suggests that investing in equity is an important step toward sustainable human development for current and future generations.

References

  • Alkire S (2008) Concepts and measures of agency. In: Basu K, Kanbur R (eds) Arguments for a better world: essays in honour of Amartya Sen – volume 1, ethics, welfare and measurement. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 455–474

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Anand S, Sen AK (2000) Human development and economic sustainability. World Dev 28(12):2029–2049

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anand P, Hunter G, Carter I, Dowding K, Guala F, van Hees M (2009) The development of capability indicators. J Hum Dev Capab 10(1):125–152

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle (1999) Nicomachean Ethics, Book I, translated and edited by T. Irwin, 2nd edn. Hackett Publishing Co, Indiana

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson T, Cantillion B, Marlier E, Nolan B (2002) Social indicators: the EU and social inclusion. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bentham J (1776) A fragment of government, T. Payne, London. http://www.constitution.org/jb/frag_gov.htm. Accessed 19 May 2013

  • Bentham J (1789) [1907] An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham J (1843) ‘Anarchical Fallacies; being an examination of the Declaration of Rights issued during the French Revolution’, full text reprinted in J. Waldron (ed) (1987), ‘Nonsense upon Stilts’: Bentham, Burke, and Marx on the Rights of Man, Methuen, London, pp 46–69

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertrand M, Mullianinathan S (2001) Do people mean what they say? Implications for subjective survey data. Am Econ Rev 91(2):67–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biggeri M, Ballet J, Comim F (eds) (2011) Children and the capabilities approach. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke

    Google Scholar 

  • Braybrooke D (1987) Meeting needs. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Brickman P, Campbell D (1971) Hedonic relativism and planning the good society. In: Apley HM (ed) Adaptation level theory: a symposium. Academic Press, New York, pp 287–302

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome J (1991) Utility. Econ Philos 7:1–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brundtland Report (1987) Our common future, (Report of the World Commission on Environment and Development). Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chenery H, Ahluwalia MS, Bell CLG, Duloy JH, Jolly R (1974) Redistribution with growth. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiappero-Martinetti E (ed) (2009) Debating global society: reach and limits of the capability approach. Fondazione Giangiacomo Feltrinelli, Milan

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark DA (2002) Visions of development: a study of human values. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark DA (2003) Concepts and perceptions of human well-being: some evidence from South Africa. Oxford Dev Stud 31(2):173–196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark DA (2005) Sen’s capability approach and the many spaces of human well-being. J Dev Stud 41(8):1339–1368

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark DA (2006) Capability approach. In: Clark DA (ed) The Elgar companion to development studies. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 32–45

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Clark DA (2008) Relevant criteria for selecting indicators: a proposal. Background Paper (EHRC project on Developing the Equality Measurement Framework: Selecting the Indicators), Centre for Analysis of Social Exclusion, London School of Economics and Political Science, September. http://sticerd.lse.ac.uk/case/_new/research/equality/publications.asp. Accessed 17 May 2013

  • Clark DA (2012) Adaptation, poverty and development: the dynamics of subjective well-being. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark DA (2013) Creating capabilities, lists and thresholds: whose voices, value judgements and intuitions count? Journal of Human Development and Capabilities, 14(1):172–184

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark DA, Hulme D (2010) Poverty, time and vagueness: integrating the core poverty and chronic poverty frameworks. Camb J Econ 34(2):347–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark DA, Qizilbash M (2008) Core poverty, vagueness and adaptation: a new methodology and some results for South Africa. J Dev Stud 44(4):519–544

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen GA (1993), Equality of what? On welfare, goods and capabilities. In: Nussbaum MC and Sen AK (eds) The Quality of Life. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 9–29

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Colander D (2007) Edgeworth’s Hedonimeter and the quest to measure utility. J Econ Perspect 21(2):215–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Comim F, Qizilbash M, Alkire S (eds) (2008) The capability approach: concepts, measures and applications. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Crisp R (2008) Well-being. In: Edward N. Zalta (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Revised edition, winter 2008), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2008/entries/well-being/

  • Crisp R, Hooker B (eds) (2000) Well-being and morality: essays in honour of James Griffin. OUP, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Crocker D (2008) Ethics of global development: agency, capability, and deliberative democracy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins RA (2000) Subjective and objective quality of life: an interactive model. Soc Indic Res 52:55–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daly H (2006) Uneconomic growth. In: Clark DA (ed) The Elgar companion to development studies. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 654–658

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta P, Heal C (1979) Economic theory and exhaustible resources. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • de Gaay-Fortman B (2006) Human rights. In: DA Clark (ed) The Elgar companion to development studies. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 260–266

    Google Scholar 

  • Deaton A (2008) Income, health and well-being around the world: evidence from the Gallup world poll. J Econ Perspect 22(2):53–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener E (1984) [2009] Subjective well-being. In: Ed Diener (ed) The science of well-being: the collected works of Ed Diener. Springer, London, pp 11–58 [Reprint from the Pschological Bulletin, 95, pp. 542–75]

    Google Scholar 

  • Diener E, Suh EM, Lucas RE, Smith HL (1999) Subjective well-being: three decades of progress. Psychol Bull 125(2):276–302

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diener E, Lucas RE, Scollon CN (2006) Beyond the hedonic treadmill: revising the adaptation theory of well-being. Am Psychol 61(4):305–314

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dolan P, Peasgood T, White M (2008) Do we really know what makes us happy? A review of the economic literature on the factors associated with subjective well-being. J Econ Psychol 29:94–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorsey D (2013) The authority of competence and quality as extrinsic. Br J Hist Philos 21(1):78–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1984) Rights as trumps. In: Waldron J (ed) Theories of rights. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 153–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Easterlin R (1974) Does economic growth improve the human lot? Some empirical evidence. In: David PA, Reder MW (eds) Nations and households in economics growth: essays in honour or Moses Abramowitz. Academic Press, New York, pp 89–125

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Edgeworth FY (1881) Mathematical psychics: an essay on the application of mathematics to the moral sciences. C. Kegan Paul and Co., London

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (1983) Sour grapes: studies in the subversion of rationality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frey BS, Stutzer A (2002) Happiness and economics: how the economy and institutions affect human well-being. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldin I (2014) Is the planet full? Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin J (1986) Well-being: its meaning, measurement and moral importance. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn F, Hollis M (eds) (1979) Philosophy and economic theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Halliwell J, Layard R, Sachs J (2012) World happiness report. The Earth Institute, Columbia University, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartwick JM (2006) National accounting. In: Clark DA (ed) The Elgar companion to development studies. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 405–409

    Google Scholar 

  • Hicks N, Streeten P (1979) Indicators of development: the search for a basic needs yardstick. World Dev 7(6):567–580

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hulme D, Scott J (2010) The political economy of the MDGs: retrospect and prospect for the world’s biggest promise, BWPI working paper 110. University of Manchester, Manchester

    Google Scholar 

  • Huppert A, So T (2013) Flourishing across europe: application of a new conceptual framework for defining well-being. Soc Indic Res 110:837–861

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ILO (1976) Meeting basic needs: strategies for eradicating mass poverty and unemployment. International Labour Organization, Geneva

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaggar A (2006) Reasoning about well-being: Nussbaum’s methods of justifying the capabilities. J Polit Philos 14(3):301–322

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jarden A (2011) An interview with Daniel Kahneman. Int J Wellbeing 1(1):186–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Krueger AB (2006) Development in the measurement of subjective well-being. J Econ Perspect 20(1):3–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Wakker PP, Sarin R (1997) Back to bentham? Explorations of experienced utility. Q J Econ 112(2):375–406

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Diener E, Schwartz N (eds) (1999) Well-being: the foundations of Hedonic philosophy. Russell Sage Foundation, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Klugman J, Rodríguez F, Choi H-J (2011) The HDI 2010: new controversies, old critiques. J Econ Inequal 9:249–288

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight M, Tsuchiya A (2008) Well-being and the environment: research questions and connections, note for the well-being and environment workshop, 19 September. Centre for Health and Wellbeing in Public Policy, University of Sheffield. http://www.sheffield.ac.uk/polopoly_fs/1.72812!/file/Wellbeing-and-the-environment.pdf. Accessed 14 May 2013

  • Krueger AB, Schkade DA (2008) The reliability of subjective well-being measures. J Public Econ 92(8–9):1833–1845

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Layard R (2006) Happiness: lessons from a new science. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Meeks JG (ed) (1991) Thoughtful economic man: essays on rationality, moral rules and benevolence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS (1861) Utilitarianism, reprinted in On Liberty and Other Essays (ed. J. Grey, 1998), Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris MD, Liser FB (1977) PQLI: measuring progress in meeting human needs, Communiqué on Development 32. Overseas Development Council, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1974) Anarchy, state and utopia. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC (1995) Human capabilities, female human beings. In: Nussbaum MC, Glover J (eds) Women, culture and development. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 61–104

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC (2000) Women and human development: the capabilities approach. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum MC (2011) Creating capabilities: the human development approach. Belknap Press, Harvard

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • OED (1989) [2012] ‘Well-Being’, in the Oxford English Dictionary (1989 edition). http://www.oed.com/viewdictionaryentry/Entry/227050

  • Okin SM (2003) Poverty, well-being, and gender: what counts, who’s heard? Philos Public Aff 31(3):280–316

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oswald AJ (1997) Happiness and economic performance. Econ J 107(445):1815–1831

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit D (1984) Reasons and persons. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce D (2006) Environment and development. In: Clark DA (ed) The Elgar companion to development studies. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 164–167

    Google Scholar 

  • Prescott-Allen R (2001) The well-being of nations: a country-by-country index of quality of life and the environment. Island Press, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Qizilbash M (1998) The concept of well-being. Econ Philos 14:51–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ravallion M (2011) On multidimensional poverty indices. J Econ Inequal 9:235–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers DS, Duraiappah AK, Antons DC, Munoz P, Bai X, Fragkias M, Gutscher H (2012) A vision of human well-being: transition to social sustainability. Curr Opin Environ Sustain 4:1–13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan RM, Deci EL (2001) On happiness and human potentials: a review of research on hedonic and eudaimonic well-being. Annu Rev Psychol 52:141–161

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkosy Report (2009) Report by the Commission on the Measurement of Economic Performance and Social Progress. Commission on the Measurement of Economic Performance and Social Progress, Paris. http://www.stiglitz-sen-fitoussi.fr/. Accessed 18 May 2013

  • Scivotsky T (1976) The joyless economy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Seers D (1972) What are we trying to measure. J Dev Stud 8(3):21–36

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Self A, Thomas J, Randall C (2012) Measuring national well-being: life in the UK, 2012. Office of National Statistics, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1977) Rational fools: a critique of the behaviour foundations of economic theory. Philos Public Aff 6(4):317–344

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1980) Equality of what. In: McMurrin SM (ed) The tanner lectures on human value. University of Utah Press, Salt Lake City, pp 195–220

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1982) Choice, welfare and measurement. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1985a) Agency, well-being and freedom: the Dewey lectures 1984. J Philos 82(4):169–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1985b) Commodities and capabilities. Elsevier Science Publishers, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1992) Inequality re-examined. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1999) Development as freedom. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (2002) Rationality and freedom. Belknap Press of HUP, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (2004) Elements of a theory of human rights. Philos Public Aff 32(4):315–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (2006) Human development index. In: Clark DA (ed) The Elgar companion to development studies. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 256–260

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (2009) The idea of justice. Allen Lane, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (2013) The ends and means of sustainability. J Hum Dev Capab 14(1):6–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK, Williams B (eds) (1982) Utilitarianism and beyond. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1982) Models of bounded rationality. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • SOPAC (2005) Building resilience in SIDS: the environmental vulnerability index. South Pacific Applied Geoscience Commission and the United Nations Environment Programme, Suva. http://www.vulnerabilityindex.net/Files/EVI%20Final%20Report%202005.pdf. Accessed 15 May 2013

  • Stewart F (1996) Basic needs, capabilities and human development. In: Offer A (ed) In pursuit of the quality of life. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 46–65

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart F (2006) Basic needs approach. In: Clark DA (ed) The Elgar companion to development studies. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 14–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Streeten P, Burki S, ul Haq M, Hicks N, Stewart F (1981) First things first, meeting basic human needs in developing. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (1993) Welfare, resources, and capabilities: a review of inequality reexamined by Amartya Sen. J Econ Lit 31:1947–1962

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden R (2006) Mill and Sen on the value of opportunity. Utilitas 18(1):33–51

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • UN-DESA (2011) World population prospects: the 2010 revision (Volume I: Comprehensive tables). United Nations Department of Economics and Social Affairs, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • UNDP (2000) Human development report 2000: human rights and human development. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • UNDP (2010) Human development report 2010: the real wealth of nations. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • UNDP (2011) Human development report 2011: sustainability and equity. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Vizard P (2010) The idea of justice: Sen’s treatment of human rights. J Hum Dev Capab 11(4):615–621

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White H (2006) Millennium development goals. In: Clark DA (ed) The Elgar companion to development studies. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 382–389

    Google Scholar 

  • WHO (1948) Constitution of the World Health Organization. http://apps.who.int/gb/bd/PDF/bd47/EN/constitution-en.pdf. Accessed 19 May 2013

  • World Bank (1992) World development report 1992: development and the environment. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • WVS (2011) WVS 2010-2012 Wave, revised master, OCT 2011. World values surveys. http://www.worldvaluessurvey.org/wvs/articles/folder_published/article_base_136/files/WVS_2010-2012_REVISED_OCT_2011.pdf. Accessed 17 May 2013

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Gay Meeks for helpful comments on drafts of this chapter. In writing this chapter, I have benefited enormously from Gay Meeks’ “Philosophical Issues in Economics” lectures at Cambridge University (now part of the MPhil in Development Studies) and from interactions with talented students following this course. I am also indebted to Mozaffar Qizilbash for many helpful conversations over the years. The structure and shape of this chapter has been influenced by the writings of Jim Griffin, Amartya Sen, and Roger Crisp. The usual disclaimers apply. © David A. Clark, 2013.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David A. Clark .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this entry

Cite this entry

Clark, D.A. (2014). Defining and Measuring Human Well-Being. In: Freedman, B. (eds) Global Environmental Change. Handbook of Global Environmental Pollution, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5784-4_66

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics