Advertisement

End-of-Life Decisions

  • Kenneth ChambaereEmail author
  • Jan Bernheim
Reference work entry

Abstract

This chapter deals with the topic of medical decisions and decision-making that occur at the end of life and have the potential to allow the patient to die or hasten death. These decisions include: withholding and withdrawing treatment, intensified management of pain and other symptoms, active shortening of life without explicit patient request, euthanasia, physician-assisted suicide, and voluntary stopping eating and drinking. Evidently, such decisions are subject to considerable ethical deliberation and scrutiny, apart from their applicability in the legal framework of some jurisdictions. In this contribution, the main ethical principles – autonomy, beneficence, nonmaleficence and justice – are considered in the context of end-of-life decision-making. We go on with a discussion of intensely debated special topics such as: proportionality, the principle of double effect, (medical) futility, nonabandonment, and vulnerability. Next a glossary is provided of the most pertinent issues inherent in each type of end-of-life decision. Examples include: opioid phobia in pain management, the “slippery slope” argument in the assisted dying debate, and the relationship between palliative care and assisted dying. Finally, attention turns to a number of important topics related to communication in end-of-life decision-making: truth-telling, shared decision-making, advance care planning & advance directives, conflict, and cultural issues.

References

  1. Anscombe E. Intention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell; 1958.Google Scholar
  2. Ashby MA. The futility of futility: death causation is the “elephant in the room” in discussions about limitation of medical treatment. J Bioeth Inq. 2011;8(2):151–4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bagheri A. Medical futility. London: World Scientific and Imperial College Press; 2014.Google Scholar
  4. Bagheri A. Futility. In: ten Have H, editor. Encyclopedia of global bioethics [Internet]. Cham: Springer; 2017. p. 1–10.  https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-05544-2_204-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Baily MA. Futility, autonomy, and cost in end-of-life care. J Law, Med Ethics. 2011;39(2):172–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Battin MP, van der Heide A, Ganzini L, van der Wal G, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD. Legal physician-assisted dying in Oregon and the Netherlands: evidence concerning the impact on patients in “vulnerable” groups. J Med Ethics. 2007;33(10):591–7.PubMedPubMedCentralCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of biomedical ethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 1979.Google Scholar
  8. Bernheim JL, Raus K. Euthanasia embedded in palliative care. Responses to essentialistic criticisms of the Belgian model of integral end-of-life care. J Med Ethics. 2017;43(8):489–94.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Bernheim JL, Deschepper R, Distelmans W, Mullie A, Bilsen J, Deliens L. Development of palliative care and legalisation of euthanasia: antagonism or synergy? BMJ [Internet]. 2008;336(7649):864–7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Bernheim JL, Vansweevelt T, Annemans L. Medical futility and end-of-life issues in Belgium. In: Bagheri A, editor. Medical futility: a cross-national study. London: World Scientific and Imperial College Press; 2013. p. 59–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Boyle J. Medical ethics and double effect: The case of terminal sedation. Theor Med Bioethics. 2004;25(1):51–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Callahan D. When self-determination runs amok. Hast Cent Rep. 2008;22(2):52–5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Chambaere K, Bernheim JL. Does legal physician-assisted dying impede development of palliative care? The Belgian and Benelux experience. J Med Ethics. 2015;41(8):657–60.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Chambaere K, Bernheim JL, Downar J, Deliens L. Characteristics of Belgian “life-ending acts without explicit patient request”: a large-scale death certificate survey revisited. CMAJ Open. 2014;2(4):E262–7.PubMedPubMedCentralCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Chambaere K, Vander Stichele R, Mortier F, Cohen J, Deliens L. Recent trends in euthanasia and other end-of-life practices in Belgium. N Engl J Med. 2015;372(12):1179–81.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Clark D, ten Have H, Janssens R. Conceptual tensions in European palliative care. In: ten Have H, Clark D, editors. The ethics of palliative care. Philadelphia: Open University Press; 2002.Google Scholar
  17. Cohen-Almagor R. Euthanasia policy and practice in Belgium: critical observations and suggestions for improvement. Issues Law Med [Internet]. 2009;24(3):187–218.Google Scholar
  18. Cohen-Almagor R. First do no harm: pressing concerns regarding euthanasia in Belgium. Int J Law Psychiatry [Internet]. 2013;36(5–6):515–21.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Detering KM, Hancock AD, Reade MC, Silvester W. The impact of advance care planning on end of life care in elderly patients: randomised controlled trial. BMJ [Internet]. 2010;340(mar23 1):c1345–c1345.PubMedPubMedCentralCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Deyaert J, Chambaere K, Cohen J, Roelands M, Deliens L. Labelling of end-of-life decisions by physicians. J Med Ethics. 2014;40(7):505–7.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Druml C, Ballmer PE, Druml W, Oehmichen F, Shenkin A, Singer P, Soeters P, Weimann A, Bischoff SC. ESPEN guideline on ethical aspects of artificial nutrition and hydration. Clin Nutr. 2016;35(3):545–56.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Emanuel EJ, Emanuel LL. Four models of the physician-patient relationship. JAMA. 1995;267(16):2221–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Emanuel LL, Johnson R. Truth telling and consent. In: Cherny N, Fallon M, Kaasa S, Portenoy RK, Currow DC, editors. Oxford textbook of palliative medicine. Oxford University Press New York; 2013.Google Scholar
  24. Emanuel EJ, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD, Urwin JW, Cohen J. Attitudes and practices of Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide in the United States, Canada, and Europe. JAMA [Internet]. 2016;316(1):79.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Evans & Anor v Alder Hey Children's NHS Foundation Trust & Ors. EWCA Civ 805. British and Irish Legal Information Institute; 2018. 16 Apr 2018.Google Scholar
  26. Foster C. Choosing life, choosing death [Internet]. In: The tyranny of autonomy in medical ethics and law. Oxford and Portland: Hart Publishing; 2009. 189 p.Google Scholar
  27. Gawande A. Quantity and quality of life: Duties of care in life-limiting illness. JAMA. 2016;315(3):267–9.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Griffiths J, Bood A, Weyers H. Euthanasia and law in the Netherlands. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press; 1998.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Hall MA, Trachtenberg F, Dugan E. The impact on patient trust of legalising physician aid in dying. J Med Ethics. 2005;31(12):693–7.PubMedPubMedCentralCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Hudson P, Hudson R, Philip J, Boughey M, Kelly B, Hertogh C. Legalizing physician-assisted suicide and/or euthanasia: pragmatic implications. Palliat Support Care. 2015;13(5):1399–409.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Jaspers B, Müller-Busch HC, Nauck F. Integral palliative care: a contradiction in Terms? (in German). Z. Palliativmed. 2009; 10:162–6.Google Scholar
  32. Jox RJ, Black I, Borasio GD, Anneser J. Voluntary stopping of eating and drinking: is medical support ethically justified? BMC Med. 2017;15(1):186.PubMedPubMedCentralCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Ko DN, Blinderman CD. Withholding and withdrawing life-sustaining treatment (including artificial nutrition and hydration). In: Cherny N, Fallon M, Kaasa S, Portenoy RK, Currow DC, editors. Oxford textbook of palliative medicine. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013.Google Scholar
  34. Kogan S, Blanchette P, Masaki K. Talking to patients about death and dying: improving communication across cultures. In: Braun KL, Pietsch JHP, Blanchette PL, editors. Cultural issues in end-of-life decision making. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publishing; 2002. p. 305–26.Google Scholar
  35. Kontis V, Bennett JE, Mathers CD, Li G, Foreman K, Ezzati M. Future life expectancy in 35 industrialised countries: projections with a Bayesian model ensemble. Lancet. 2017;389(10076):1323–35.PubMedPubMedCentralCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Levy N. Forced to be free? Increasing patient autonomy by constraining it. J Med Ethics. 2014;40(5):293–300.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Lewis P, Black I. Reporting and scrutiny of reported cases in four jurisdictions where assisted dying is lawful: a review of the evidence in the Netherlands, Belgium, Oregon and Switzerland. Med Law Int. 2013;13(4):221–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. López-Saca JM, Guzmán JL, Centeno C. A systematic review of the influence of opioids on advanced cancer patient survival. Curr Opin Support Palliat Care. 2013;7(4):424–30.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Macauley R. The role of the principle of double effect in ethics education at US medical schools and its potential impact on pain management at the end of life. J Med Ethics. 2012;38(3):174–8.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Makoul G, Clayman ML. An integrative model of shared decision making in medical encounters. Patient Educ Couns. 2006;60(3):301–12.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Mangan J. An historical analysis of the principle of double effect. Theol Stud. 1949;10:41–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Materstvedt LJ, Bosshard G. Euthanasia and palliative care. In: Cherny N, Fallon M, Kaasa S, Portenoy RK, Currow DC, editors. Oxford textbook of palliative medicine. New York: Oxford University Press; 2013.Google Scholar
  43. Materstvedt LJ, Clark D, Ellershaw J, Forde R, Gravgaard AM, Muller-Busch HC, et al. Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide: a view from an EAPC Ethics Task Force. Palliat Med. 2003;17:97–101.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Mehter HM, Clark JA, Wiener RS. Physician approaches to provider-family conflict associated with end-of-life decision-making in the ICU: a qualitative study. Am J Respir Crit Care Med [Internet]. 2015;191.Google Scholar
  45. Mill JS. Utilitarianism. London: Parker, Son and Bourn; 1863. p. 26.Google Scholar
  46. Pereira J. Legalizing euthanasia or assisted suicide: the illusion of safeguards and controls. Curr Oncol. 2011;18(2):e38–45.PubMedPubMedCentralCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Quill TE, Dresser R, Brock D. The rule of double effect – a critique of its role in end-of-life decision making. New Eng J Med. 1997;337:1768.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Radbruch L, Leget C, Bahr P, Müller-Busch C, Ellershaw J, De Conno F, et al. Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide: a white paper from the European Association for Palliative Care. Palliat Med. 2016;30:104–16.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Roeland E, Cain J, Onderdonk C, Kerr K, Mitchell W, Thornberry K. When open-ended questions don't work: the role of palliative paternalism in difficult medical decisions. J Palliat Med. 2014;17(4):415–20.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Schneiderman LJ. Defining medical futility and improving medical care. J Bioeth Inq. 2011;8(2):123–31.PubMedPubMedCentralCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Shariff MJ. Assisted death and the slippery slope – finding clarity amid advocacy, convergence, and complexity. Curr Oncol [Internet]. 2012;19(3):143–54.Google Scholar
  52. Sleeman KE. End-of-life communication: let’s talk about death. J Roy Coll Phys Edinburgh. 2013;43(3):197–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Smets T, Cohen J, Bilsen J, Van Wesemael Y, Rurup ML, Deliens L. The labelling and reporting of euthanasia by Belgian physicians: a study of hypothetical cases. Eur J Pub Health. 2012;22(1):19–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Specker SL. Medical maternalism: beyond paternalism and antipaternalism. J Med Ethics. 2016;42(7):439–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. ten Have H, Janssens R. Futility, limits and palliative care. In: ten Have H, Clark D, editors. The ethics of palliative care. Philadelphia: Open University Press; 2002.Google Scholar
  56. Thorns A, Sykes N. Opioid use in last week of life and implications for end-of-life decision-making. Lancet [Internet]. 2000;356(9227):398–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Uhlmann AT, Uhlmann DR, Workman S. Distress of clinicians with decisions to withhold or withdraw life-support measures (multiple letters). J Crit Care. 2004;19:118–20.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. van der Heide A, Rietjens J. End-of-life decisions. In: Cohen J, Deliens L, editors. A public health perspective on end of life care. New-York: Oxford University Press; 2012.Google Scholar
  59. van der Heide A, van Delden JJM, Onwuteaka-Philipsen BD. End-of-life decisions in the Netherlands over 25 Years. N Engl J Med. 2017;377(5):492–4.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. van Marwijk H, Haverkate I, van Royen P, The AM. Impact of euthanasia on primary care physicians in the Netherlands. Palliat Med. 2007;21(7):609–14.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Vanden Berghe P, Mullie A, Desmet M, Huysmans G. Assisted dying – the current situation in Flanders: euthanasia embedded in palliative care. Eur J Palliat Care. 2013:20(6).Google Scholar
  62. Visser M, Deliens L, Houttekier D. Physician-related barriers to communication and patient- and family-centred decision-making towards the end of life in intensive care: a systematic review. Crit Care. 2014;18(6):604.PubMedPubMedCentralCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Wancata LM, Hinshaw DB. Rethinking autonomy: decision making between patient and surgeon in advanced illnesses. Ann Transl Med. 2016;4(4):77.PubMedPubMedCentralGoogle Scholar
  64. Wax JW, An AW, Kosier N, Quill TE. Voluntary stopping eating and drinking. J Am Geriatr Soc. 2018;66(3):441–5.PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. World Health Organisation. WHO definition of palliative care [Internet]. World Health Organisation. 2018 [cited 2018 Apr 29]. Available from http://www.who.int/cancer/palliative/definition/en/
  66. Youngner SJ, Arnold RM. The Oxford handbook of ethics at the end of life. [Internet]. 2016; Available from http://ovidsp.ovid.com/ovidweb.cgi?T=JS&PAGE=reference&D=psyc13&NEWS=N&AN=2016-26125-000

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.End-of-Life Care Research GroupVrije Universiteit Brussel (VUB) and Ghent UniversityBrusselsBelgium

Personalised recommendations