Encyclopedia of Medieval Philosophy

2011 Edition
| Editors: Henrik Lagerlund

Natural Philosophy

  • Johannes M. M. H Thijssen
Reference work entry
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-9729-4_348

Abstract

Before the publication of Newton’s Principia mathematica philosophiae naturalis (1689), Aristotle’s Physics was the most widely read and influential book of natural philosophy. After 1250, it constituted the core text of the discipline of natural philosophy and was, together with Aristotle’s other “natural books,” routinely studied at all European universities. Change and motion were the central topics in Aristotle’s “natural books,” and, as a consequence, came to be pivotal in medieval natural philosophy. For Aristotle, and the medievals in his wake, motion was not merely a starting point from everyday experience, but a phenomenon whose nature needed closer investigation. This article will pay attention to medieval studies of the nature of motion, but also to medieval dynamics and kinematics (gravity, accelerated free fall, projectile motion, and qualitative changes, such as heating). The medieval discussions raised interesting ontological, semantic, and mathematical issues. The focus will be on developments at the universities of Oxford and Paris.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in to check access.

Bibliography

  1. In addition to the bibliography provided in the cross-referenced entries, the following studies are useful for further orientation in medieval natural philosophy:Google Scholar
  2. Caroti S (1993) Oresme on motion. In: Murdoch JE, Thijssen JMMH (eds) History of late medieval science. Vivarium 31:8–37Google Scholar
  3. Clagett M (1959) The science of mechanics in the Middle Ages. The University of Wisconsin Press, MadisonGoogle Scholar
  4. Damerow P, Freudenthal G, McLaughlin P, Renn J (eds) (1992) Exploring the limits of preclassical mechanics. Springer, New York/BerlinGoogle Scholar
  5. Grant E (1996) The foundations of modern science in the Middle Ages. Their religious, institutional and intellectual contexts. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  6. Grant E (2007) A history of natural philosophy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge/New YorkGoogle Scholar
  7. Kirschner S (1997) Nicolaus Oresmes Kommentar zur Physik des Aristoteles. Steiner, StuttgartGoogle Scholar
  8. Lindberg DC (1992) The beginnings of western science. The European scientific tradition in philosophical, religious, and institutional context, 600 B.C. to A.D. 1450. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  9. Maier A (1949–1958) Studien zur Naturphilosophie der Spätscholastik, 5 vols. Edizione di storia et letteratura, RomaGoogle Scholar
  10. Murdoch JE, Sylla E (1978) The science of motion. In: Lindberg DC (ed) Science in the Middle Ages. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 206–265Google Scholar
  11. North JD (1992) Natural philosophy in late medieval Oxford. In: Catto JI, Evans R (eds) The history of the University of Oxford. Late medieval Oxford, vol 2. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 76–95Google Scholar
  12. O’Brien D (1995) Aristotle’s theory of movement. In: Cleary JJ, Wians WC (eds) Proceedings of the Boston area colloquium in ancient philosophy, vol XI, pp 47–138Google Scholar
  13. O’Leary De L (1980) How Greeks science passed to the Arabs. Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd., London/BostonGoogle Scholar
  14. Owen GEL (1985) Aristotelian mechanics. In: Gotthelf A (ed) Aristotle on nature and living things. mathesis Publications, Bristol, pp 227–245Google Scholar
  15. Sabra AI (1987) The appropriation and subsequent naturalization of Greek science in medieval Islam. Hist Sci 25:223–243Google Scholar
  16. Sarnowsky J (1987) Natural philosophy at Oxford and Paris in the mid-fourteenth century. In: Hudson A, Wilks M (eds) From Ockham to Wyclif. Oxford, pp 125–134Google Scholar
  17. Sarnowsky J (1989) Die aristotelisch-scholastische Theorie der Bewegung. Studien zum Kommentar Alberts von Sachsen zur Physik des Aristoteles. Aschendorff, MünsterGoogle Scholar
  18. Souffrin P (1992) Sur l’histoire du concept de vitesse d’Aristote à Galilée. Revue d’histoire des sciences 45:231–267Google Scholar
  19. Sylla ED (1986) Galileo and the Oxford ‘Calculatores’: analytic languages and the mean-speed theorem for accelerated motion. In: Wallace WA (ed) Reinterpreting Galileo. Catholic University of America Press, Washington, DC, pp 53–111Google Scholar
  20. Sylla ED (1993) Aristotelian commentaries and scientific change: the Parisian nominalists on the cause of the natural motion of inanimate bodies. In: Murdoch JE, Thijssen JMMH (eds) History of late medieval science. Vivarium 31:37–84Google Scholar
  21. Sylla ED (1997) Transmission of the new physics of the fourteenth century from England to the continent. In: Caroti S, Souffrin P (eds) La Nouvelle Physique du XIVe siècle. Olschki, Firenze, pp 65–111Google Scholar
  22. Thijssen JMMH (2004) The Buridan school reassessed. John Buridan and Albert of Saxony. Vivarium 42:18–43Google Scholar
  23. Thijssen JMMH (2010) The nature of change. In: Pasnau R (ed) The Cambridge history of medieval philosophy, vol 1. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 279–290Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  • Johannes M. M. H Thijssen
    • 1
  1. 1.Faculty of PhilosophyRadboud University NijmegenNijmegenThe Netherlands