Skip to main content

Philosophy of Science, Mathematical Models in

  • Living reference work entry
  • First Online:
Encyclopedia of Complexity and Systems Science
  • 405 Accesses

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Abbreviations

Philosophy of Science:

Philosophy of science is a branch of philosophy that studies and reflects on the presuppositions, concepts, theories, models, data, arguments, methods, and aims of science. Philosophers of science are concerned with general questions which include the following: What is a scientific theory and when can it be said to be confirmed by its predictions? What are mathematical models and how are they validated? In virtue of what are models representations of the structure and possible behaviors of their target systems? In sum, a major task of philosophy of science is to analyze and make explicit common patterns that are implicit in scientific practice.

Target System:

A target system is an effectively isolated (physical, chemical, biological, or other empirical) part of the universe, made to function or run by some internal or external causes, whose interactions with the universe are strictly delineated by a fixed (input and output) interface, and whose structure, mechanism, or behavior are the principal objects of mathematical modeling. Changes produced in the target system are presumed to be externally detectable via measurements of the system’s characterizing quantitative properties.

Mathematical Model:

A mathematical object of a given type is said to be a mathematical model of a target system just in case it provides substantive information about the system’s modes of being, mechanisms, and behavior in all possible situations in which the system might find itself. The amount of information carried by the model is contingent upon the scope and depth of encoding of the target’s features in the representing mathematical object’s structure. Why model at all? Answer: because investigators who think with mathematical models consistently outperform those who do not. Models help generate testable predictions and explanations and thereby support a better understanding of their targets.

From the standpoint of classical set-theoretic model theory, a mathematical model of a target system is specified by a nonempty set, called the model’s domain, endowed with some algebraic operations and relations, delineated by suitable axioms and intended empirical interpretation. No doubt, this is the simplest definition of a model that, unfortunately, plays a limited role in scientific applications of mathematics. Because applications exhibit a need for a large variety of vastly different mathematical structures – some topological or smooth; some algebraic, computational, stochastic, order-theoretic, or combinatorial; some measure-theoretic or analytic; and so forth, no useful overarching definition of a mathematical model is known even in the edifice of modern category theory. It is invariably difficult to come up with a workable concept of a mathematical model that is applicable and adequate in most fields of applied mathematics and anticipates future extensions.

Bibliography

  • Atmanspacher H, Primas H (2003) Epistemic and ontic realities. In: Castell L, Ischebeck O (eds) Time, quantum and information. Springer, New York, pp 301–321

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bailer-Jones DM (2002) Scientists’ thoughts on scientific models. Perspect Sci 10:275–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batitsky V, Domotor Z (2007) When good theories make bad predictions. Synthese 157:79–103

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Bueno O, French S, Ladyman J (2002) On representing the relationship between the mathematical and the empirical. Philos Sci 69:497–518

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty A (2004) Structuralism as a form of scientific realism. Int Stud Philos Sci 18:151–171

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Da Costa NCA, French S (2003) Science and partial truth. A unitary approach to models and scientific reasoning. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Domotor Z, Batitsky V (2010) An algebraic-analytic framework for measurement theory. Measurement 43:1142–1164

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dukich JM (2012) Two types of empirical adequacy: a partial structures approach. Synthese 185(1):1–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel K-J, Nagel R (2000) One-parameter semigroups for linear evolution equations, vol 194, Graduate texts in mathematics. Springer, New York

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Ermentrout G, Edelstein-Keshet L (1993) Cellular automata approaches to biological modeling. J Theor Biol 160(1):97–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French S (2006) Structure as a weapon of the realist. P Aristotelian Soc 106:1–19

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Fulford G, Forrester P, Jones A (1997) Modelling with differential and difference equations. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Giere R (2004) How models are used to represent reality. Philos Sci (Proc) 71:742–752

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hellman G (2001) Three varieties of mathematical structuralism. Philos Math 9:184–211

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman J (1998) What is structural realism? Stud Hist Philos Sci 29:409–424

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lambek J, Rattray BA (1979) A general Stone-Gelfand duality. T Am Math Soc 248:1–35

    MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Lasota A, Mackey MC (1994) Chaos, fractals and noise. Stochastic aspects of dynamics, 2nd edn. Springer, New York

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Lawvere FW (2005) Taking categories seriously. Theory Appl Categor 8:1–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Lotka AJ (1956) Elements of mathematical biology. Dover, New York

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Mac Lane S (1996) Structure in mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica 20:1–175

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • May RM (2004) Uses and abuses of mathematics in biology. Science 303:790–793

    Article  ADS  Google Scholar 

  • Oberst U (1990) Multidimensional constant linear systems. Acta Appl Math 68:59–122

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Pincock C (2011) Mathematics and scientific representation. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Polderman JW, Willems JC (1998) Introduction to mathematical systems theory: a behavioral approach, vol 26, Texts in applied mathematics. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Röhrl H (1977) Algebras and differential equations. Nagoya Math J 68:59–122

    MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Sargent RG (2003) Verification and validation of simulation models. In: Chick S, Sanchez PJ, Ferrin E, Morrice DJ (eds) Proceedings of the 2003 winter simulation conference. IEEE, Piscataway, pp 37–48

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner M (1998) The applicability of mathematics as a philosophical problem. Harvard University Press, New York

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Suarez M (2003) Scientific representation: against similarity and isomorphism. Int Stud Philos Sci 17:225–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (1988) Scientific structures and their representation. preliminary version. Stanford University, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller P (2001) Twilight of the perfect model. Erkenntnis 55:393–415

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen BC (1994) Interpretation in science; science as interpretation. In: Hilgevoord J (ed) J. Physics and our view of the world, Cambridge/New York, pp 169–187

    Google Scholar 

  • Walcher S (1991) Algebras and differential equations. Hadronic Press, Palm Harbor

    Google Scholar 

  • Willems JC (1991) Paradigms and puzzles in the theory of dynamical systems. IEEE T Automat Contr 36:259–294

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zoltan Domotor .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media New York

About this entry

Cite this entry

Domotor, Z. (2014). Philosophy of Science, Mathematical Models in. In: Meyers, R. (eds) Encyclopedia of Complexity and Systems Science. Springer, New York, NY. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-27737-5_407-3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-27737-5_407-3

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, New York, NY

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-27737-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Reference Physics and AstronomyReference Module Physical and Materials ScienceReference Module Chemistry, Materials and Physics

Publish with us

Policies and ethics