Skip to main content
Log in

Making sense of nature conservation after the end of nature

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The concept of nature in Western thought has been informed by the assumption of a categorical distinction between natural and artificial entities, which goes back to John Stuart Mill or even Aristotle. Such a way of articulating the natural/artificial distinction has proven unfit for conservation purposes mainly because of the extent and the pervasiveness of human activities that would leave no nature left to be conserved, and alternative views have been advanced. In this contribution, after arguing for the importance of the concept of naturalness as a guide for conservation, I will try to provide an account of the natural/artificial distinction suited to contemporary conservation framing. Focusing on a particular kind of objects that I suggest to name “environmental objects”, I propose and defend the view of “naturalness as independence” according to which the more or less an environmental object's identity conditions and survival depend on human intervention, the more or less that object is artificial or natural, respectively. According to this view, conserving environmental objects will equate to maintaining or improving their naturalness (vis-à-vis their artefactualness) or even originating artificial objects that may become new natural objects. This view has the advantage, on the one hand, of providing a rationale for a distinction which is not only part of how people think, but also pervasive in conservation practices and policies and, on the other hand, of accounting for the global pervasiveness of human intervention in the so-called natural world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In John Stuart Mill’s formulation, the second and third meaning will become as follows: “In one sense, [nature] means all powers existing in either the outer or inner world and everything which takes place by means of those powers” while, in another sense, “it means, not everything which happens, but only what takes place without the agency, or without the voluntary and intentional agency, of man.” ([1874] 2006, p. 375).

  2. See also Dussault (2016) and DesRoches (2018). A specific form of the dilemma can be found in ecological restoration, a “conservation strategy” (Jordan 2003, p. 13) consisting of restoring natural entities and systems in the aftermath of anthropogenic damage (Garson 2017). Restoration has been accused of being “a big lie” (Katz 1992), a way of “faking nature” (Elliot 1992), based on the argument that something is natural if it is not created or manipulated by humans, otherwise it becomes an artefact, endowed with a lesser value than its natural counterpart. Accordingly, restoring ecosystems or other natural entities would amount to producing more artefacts. In Katz’s words, “The re-created natural environment that is the end result of a restoration project is nothing more than an artefact created for human use” (Kats 1992, p. 392).

  3. As Tim Low puts it, “Like computers, humans are probably wired to think in opposites—yes and no, good and bad, winners and losers, nature and culture, natural and artificial. The world isn’t divided up like this, but our minds like to see it that way” (Low 2002, cit. in Hobbs et al. 2013, p. 355).

  4. See, for instance, the Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human Being with regard to the Application of Biology and Medicine—the “Oviedo Convention”, in particular art. 1 and 13.

  5. ESUs, ESPs, and MUs are units other than species specifically individuated for conservation purposes (mainly to recognize major elements of intraspecific diversity, see Funk et al. 2012). An ESU (Evolutionary Significant Unit) is a set of populations considered of particular evolutionary significance (normally because of its genetic distinctiveness, see Casacci et al. 2013). ESUs have been criticized as redundant since they often end up coinciding with phylogenetic species and it has been proposed to replace them with smaller units (Ryder 1986), i.e. ESPs (Evolutionary Significant Populations). MUs (Management Units) are instead populations with a significant divergence of allele frequencies, regardless of the phylogenetic distinctiveness of the alleles (Moritz 1994).

  6. I am referring here to the so-called “species problem”. See, among others, Richards (2010) and Ereshefsky (2010).

  7. de Queiroz (2007), Casetta and Vecchi (2019). The concept of “gene-phene pool” is defined, in analogy with Mayr’s concept of “gene-pool” (i.e. “The totality of the genes of a given population existing at a given time.” Mayr 1970, p. 417), as “the totality of the genetic and phenotypic properties of a given population or metapopulation existing at a given time” (Casetta and Vecchi 2019).

  8. I.e. “The application of science, technology, and engineering to facilitate and accelerate the design, manufacture, and/or modification of genetic materials in living organisms” (Piaggio et al. 2017, p. 100).

  9. For instance, it is currently under study the possibility of implementing a synthetic biology solution to the problem of invasive rodents by “manufacturing” mice producing only male offspring thanks to the insertion of a gene from the Y chromosome onto chromosome 17. Piaggio et al. (2017).

  10. For instance, the IUCN explicitly states that its criteria “can be applied to any taxonomic unit at or below the species level” (IUCN 2012, p. 4), and for the purposes of the Endangered Species Act, an entity, once listed, “becomes” a species, regardless of whether it was originally listed as a species, a subspecies, or a distinct population segment (i.e. a population or group of populations that is discrete from other populations of the same species and that is considered to be significant in relation to the taxon to which it belongs, for instance, based on the genetic difference between it and the rest of the species; Kelly 2010).

  11. There is also a more technical sense in which a place may be said to have a location, i.e. that every place is located exactly at itself (this is the so-called axiom of conditional reflexivity; Casati and Varzi 1999).

  12. See below the second case study.

  13. The ascription of gradable properties may lead to the famous Sorites paradox. For a possible semantic treatment, see van Deemter (2006).

  14. This solution assumes that species and places are 3D entities that extend in the three dimensions of space but not in time (endurantism). However, a different, Lewisian view is possible, i.e. that species and places are 4D entities, namely, that they extend in both the three spatial dimensions and in the temporal dimension (perdurantism). A perdurantist would see species and places not as changing their naturalness/artificialness through time, but rather as hybrid objects, i.e. the mereological sums of all their temporal parts or stages—some of which are fully natural, some other fully artificial. For a discussion on the endurantism/perdurantism debate applied to biological species, see Reydon (2008).

  15. BirdLife International 2017. Todiramphus cinnamominus (amended version of 2016 assessment). The IUCN Red List of Threatened Species 2017: e.T22725862A117372355. https://dx.doi.org/10.2305/IUCN.UK.2017-3.RLTS.T22725862A117372355.en. Downloaded on 08 May 2019.

  16. For a discussion, see Lowe (1989).

  17. The identity criteria conditions are relative to the species concept adopted or, to put it differently, to the kind of species at issue. For instance, “not being able to interbreed with other species of the same genus” clearly will not be among the asexual species’ identity conditions.

  18. Prima facie, extinction may be defined as the death of the last organism of a species. However, this is not uncontroversial because of the possibility of de-extinction (Finkelman 2018).

  19. www.institutoterra.org.

References

  • Angermeier, P. L. (2001). The natural imperative for biological conservation. Conservation Biology, 14(2), 373–381.

    Google Scholar 

  • Attfield, R. (1999). The ethics of the global environment. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bensaude-Vincent, B., & Newman, W. R. (2007). The artificial and the natural: An evolving polarity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cairns, J. (1995). Ecosocietal restoration reestablishing humanity's relationship with natural systems. Environment: Science and Policy for Sustainable Development, 37(5), 4–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callicott, B. (1992). La nature est morte, vive la nature! The Hastings Center Report,22(5), 16–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casacci, L. P., Barbero, F., & Balletto, E. (2013). The “Evolutionarily Significant Unit” concept and its applicability in biological conservation. Italian Journal of Zoology. https://doi.org/10.1080/11250003.2013.870240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casati, R., & Varzi, A. (1999). Parts and places. The structure of spatial representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casetta, E., & Marques da Silva, J. (2015). Facing the big sixth. From prioritizing species to conserving biodiversity. In E. Serrelli & N. Gontier (Eds.), Macroevolution—explanation, interpretation, evidence (pp. 377–403). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casetta, E., & Vecchi, D. (2019). Species are, at the same time, kinds and individuals. A causal argument based on an empirical approach to species identity. Synthese. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02199-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chapman, R. L. (2006). Ecological restoration restored. Environmental Values,15, 463–478.

    Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2008). Ontological dependence. Philosophy Compass,3(5), 1013–1032. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2008.00170.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowell, C. M. (1993). Ecological restoration and environmental ethics. Environmental Ethics,15, 19–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell, T. (2004). Place: A short introduction. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Queiroz, K. (2007). Species concepts and species delimitation. Systematic,56(6), 879–886.

    Google Scholar 

  • DesRoches, C. T. (2018). What is natural about natural capital during the anthropocene? Sustainability,10, 806–816. https://doi.org/10.3390/su10030806.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dussault, A. C. (2016). Ecological Nature: A non-dualistic concept for rethinking humankind’s place in the world. Ethics & the Environment,21(1), 1–37. https://doi.org/10.2979/ethicsenviro.21.1.01.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Editorial. (2008). Handle with care. Nature,455, 263–264. https://doi.org/10.1038/455263b.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliot, R. (1992). Intrinsic value, environmental obligation and naturalness. The Monist,75(2), 138–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elliot, R. (1997). Faking nature. The ethics of environmental restoration. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2010). Microbiology and the species problem. Biology and Philosophy,25, 553–568. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-010-9211-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Finkelman, L. (2018). De-extinction and the conception of species. Biology and Philosophy,33, 32. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9639-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Funk, W. C., Mckay, J. K., Hohenlohe, P. A., & Allendorf, F. W. (2012). Harnessing genomics for delineating conservation units. Trends in Ecology & Evolution,27, 489–496. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2012.05.012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2017). Ecological restoration and biodiversity conservation. In J. Garson, A. Plutynski, & S. Sarkar (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of biodiversity (pp. 326–337). London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (1974). A radical solution to the species problem. Systematic Zoology,23, 436–444.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gies, E. (2018). Fortresses of Mud. Nature,562, 178–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higgs, E. (2003). Nature by design. People, natural process, and ecological restoration. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hildebrandt, T. B., et al. (2018). Embryos and embryonic stem cells from the white rhinoceros. Nature Communications,9, 2589. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41467-018-04959-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs, R. J., Hallett, L. M., Ehrlich, P. R., & Mooney, H. A. (2011). Intervention ecology: Applying ecological science in the twenty-first century. BioScience,61(6), 442–450. https://doi.org/10.1525/bio.2011.61.6.6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs, R. J., Higgs, E. S., & Hall, C. (Eds.). (2013). Novel ecosystems: intervening in the new ecological world order. Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • IUCN. (2012). IUCN red list: categories and criteria, version 3.1, 2nd edn. Retrieved from https://www.iucnredlist.org/static/categories_criteria_3_1

  • Jones, C. G., Lawton, J. H., & Shachak, M. (1994). Organisms as ecosystem engineers. Oikos,69(3), 373–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan, W. R. (2003). The sunflower forest: Ecological restoration and the new communion with nature. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, E. (1992). The big lie: Human restoration of nature. Research in Philosophy and Technology,12, 231–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, R. P. (2010). The use of population genetics in endangered species act listing decisions. Ecology Law Quarterly,37, 1107–1159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lammer, A. (2016). Defining nature: From Aristotle to Philoponus to Avicenna. In A. Alwishah & J. Hayes (Eds.), Aristotle and the Arabic Tradition (pp. 121–142). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindenmayer, D. B., et al. (2008). Novel ecosystems resulting from landscape transformation create dilemmas for modern conservation practice. Conservation Letters,1, 129–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Low, T. (2002). The new nature: winners and losers in Wild Australia. Camberwell, Victoria: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, J. (1989). What is a criterion of identity? The Philosophical Quarterly,39(154), 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mace, G. (2014). Whose conservation? Science,345, 1558–1560. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1254704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maselko, M., Heinsch, S. C., Chacón, J. M., Harcombe, W. R., & Smanski, M. J. (2017). Synthetic species made to shun sex with wild organisms. Nature Commun.,8, 883.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1970). Populations, species, and evolution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mckibben, B. (1990). The end of nature. New York, NY: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. [1874] 2006. Nature. In Collected Works of John Stuart Mill, Volume X. Ed. By Robson, J.M. Liberty Fund: Indianapolis, IN

  • Moreno, E. (2012). Design and construction of “synthetic species”. PLoS ONE,7(7), e39054. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pone.0039054.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moritz, C. (1994). Defining ‘evolutionarily significant units’ for conservation. Tree,9(10), 373–375.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, N., Ignatieva, M., Nilon, C. H., Werner, P., & Zipperer, W. C. (2013). Patterns and trends in urban biodiversity and landscape design. In T. Elmqvist (Ed.), Urbanization, biodiversity and ecosystem services: challenges and opportunities. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Owens, J. (1968). Teleology of nature in aristotle. The Monist,52(2), 159–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearson, I. (2008). The future of life. Creating natural, artificial, synthetic and virtual organisms. EMBO Report,9(1), S75–S77. https://doi.org/10.1038/embor.2008.62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pepper, J. W., & Herron, M. D. (2008). Does biology need an organism concept? Biological Reviews,83(4), 621–627. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1469-185X.2008.00057.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piaggio, A. J., et al. (2017). Is it time for synthetic biodiversity conservation? Trends in Ecology & Evolution,32(2), 97–107. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.tree.2016.10.016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, J. C. (2011). Doing philosophy of technology. Essays in a pragmatist spirit. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Redford, K. H., et al. (2011). What does it mean to successfully conserve a (vertebrate) species? BioScience,61, 39. https://doi.org/10.1525/bio.2011.61.1.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Redford, K. H., Adams, W., & Mace, G. M. (2013). Synthetic biology and conservation of nature: Wicked problems and wicked solutions. PLoS Biology,11(4), e1001530. https://doi.org/10.1371/journal.pbio.1001530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reydon, T. (2008). Species in three and four dimensions. Synthese,164(2), 161–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reydon, T. (2019). Are species good units for biodiversity studies and conservation efforts? In E. Casetta, J. Marques da Silva, & D. Vecchi (Eds.), From assessing to conserving biodiversity. Conceptual and practical challenges (pp. 167–193). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R. (2010). The species problem. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, H., III. (2001). Natural and unnatural; wild and cultural. Western North American Naturalist,61(3), 267–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryder, O. A. (1986). Species conservation and systematics: The dilemma of the subspecies. Trends in Ecology & Evolution,1, 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Santana, C. (2019). Waiting for the Anthropocene. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 70(4),1073–1096.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (2002). Defining “biodiversity”; assessing biodiversity. The Monist,85(1), 131–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (2005). Biodiversity and environmental philosophy. An INTRODUCTION. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (2012). Environmental philosophy: From theory to practice. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, B. (2015). How to clone a mammoth: The science of de-extinction. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siipi, H. (2008). Dimensions of naturalness. Ethics and the Environment,13(1), 71–103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1986). Philosophical problems for environmentalism. In B. Norton (Ed.), The preservation of species: The value of biological diversity. Princeton University Press: Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soulé, M. E. (1985). What is conservation biology? BioScience,35(11), 727–734.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soulé, M. E. (1990). The onslaught of alien species, and other challenges in the coming decades. Conservation Biology,4(3), 233–239.

    Google Scholar 

  • Takacs, D. (1996). The idea of biodiversity. Philosophies of paradise. Baltimore and London: John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Temkin, L. S. (2011). Rethinking the good: Moral ideals and the nature of practical reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, F. (1994). The invented landscape. In A. D. Baldwin, J. De Luce, & C. Pletsch (Eds.), Beyond preservation: Restoring and inventing landscapes (pp. 35–66). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Haperen, P. F., Gremmen,  B., & Jacobs, J. (2012). Reconstruction of the ethical debate on naturalness in discussions about plant-biotechnology. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 25(6),797–812.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Deemter, K. (2006). Generating referring expressions that involve gradable properties. Computational Linguistics,32(2), 195–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varzi, A. (2011). Boundaries, conventions, and realism. In J. K. Campbell, M. O’Rourke, & M. H. Slater (Eds.), Carving nature at its joints (pp. 129–154). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, S. (2015). Thinking like a Mall: Environmental philosophy after the end of nature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wapner, P. (2010). Living through the end of nature: The future of American environmentalism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wickson, F. (2008). What is nature, if it’s more than just a place without people? Nature,456, 29. https://doi.org/10.1038/456029b.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank the audience at the IHPST seminar in Paris (in particular Caroline Angleraux, Philippe Huneman, and Sophia Rousseau-Mermans) where the ideas proposed in this article were presented and discussed for the first time; Claudio Calosi, Tina Heger, Stefano Tiozzo, Davide Vecchi for incisive feedback and suggestions; and the two anonymous reviewers for their fundamental inputs. I acknowledge the financial support of the Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia (BIODECON R&D Project Grant PTDC/FER-HFC/30665/2017) and of MIUR Department of excellence project 2018–2022 awarded to the Department of Philosophy and Education at the University of Turin.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Elena Casetta.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Casetta, E. Making sense of nature conservation after the end of nature. HPLS 42, 18 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-020-00312-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-020-00312-3

Keywords

Navigation