Skip to main content
Log in

Bio-machine Hybrid Technology: A Theoretical Assessment and Some Suggestions for Improved Future Design

  • Special Issue
  • Published:
Philosophy & Technology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In sociology, there has been a controversy about whether there is any essential difference between a human being and a tool, or if the tool–user relationship can be defined by co-actor symmetry. This issue becomes more complex when we consider examples of AI and robots, and even more so following progress in the development of various bio-machine hybrid technologies, such as robots that include organic parts, human brain implants, and adaptive prosthetics. It is argued that a concept of autonomous agency based on organismic embodiment helps to clarify the situation. On this view, agency consists of an asymmetrical relationship between an organism and its environment, because the continuous metabolic and regulatory activity of the organism gives rise to its own existence, and hence its specific behavioral domain. Accordingly, most (if not all) of current technologies are excluded from the class of autonomous agents. Instead, they are better conceptualized as interfaces that mediate our interactions with the world. This has important implications for design: Rather than trying to help humans to achieve their goals by duplicating their agency in artificial systems, it would be better to empower humans directly by enhancing their existing agency and lived experience with technological interfaces that can be incorporated into their embodiment. This incorporation might be especially facilitated by bio-machine hybrid technology that is designed according the principles of biological autonomy and multi-agent coordination dynamics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Because capitalism is founded on the untenable ideal of constant economic growth in a world of limited resources, it might be argued that these global crises have more to do with the economic system in which most technology is nowadays embedded, rather than with the technology per se. But this is not entirely accurate. The development of new technology already grew exponentially long before the modern rise of capitalism (Ambrose 2001), and the demise of many pre-capitalist ancient civilizations is closely linked to the technologically enabled overexploitation of resources (Wood 2005). Nevertheless, capitalism has surely contributed to the scale of the crises.

  2. It is an interesting open question to consider what the essential differences are between tools and technologies more generally. As one reviewer asked, can one extend the concept of tool to all techniques: house, books, robots, cities, factories, or machines? We may want to differentiate the tool itself from the totality of equipment to which it belongs and also the kinds of relationships humans can have with tools when compared with large-scale techniques (De Preester 2012). In any case, there are good reasons to believe that all techniques mediate our relationship with the world to some extent (Khatchatourov et al. 2007), and that is what is most important here.

  3. This work is part of a European Commission FP7 funded project on the Collective Experience of Empathic Data Systems (CEEDs), which aims to develop novel, integrated technologies to support human experience, analysis, and understanding of very large datasets. I share their idea of placing our experience at the center of technical solutions, which I try to motivate as being applicable to all kinds of complex problems, including our understanding of major crises.

  4. Interestingly, bio-machine hybrid robots could also be considered examples of lived technology in this specific sense—except that in this case it is the perceptual interactions of nonhuman organisms that are primarily being modulated. This change in perspective could be useful for future design of hybrid robots because the goal of creating an augmenting interface for one or more existing biological individuals, rather than creating another genuine hybrid agent as such, places significantly less demands on the engineering process (Froese and Ziemke 2009).

References

  • Ambrose, S. H. (2001). Paleolithic technology and human evolution. Science, 291(5509), 1748–1753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X., Di Paolo, E. A., & Rohde, M. (2009). Defining agency: Individuality, normativity, asymmetry, and spatio-temporality in action. Adaptive Behavior, 17(5), 367–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baudrillard, J. ([1981] 1995). Simulacra and simulation. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.

  • Bedau, M. A., McCaskill, J. S., Packard, N. H., & Rasmussen, S. (2010). Living technology: Exploiting life’s principles in technology. Artificial Life, 16, 89–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (1995). A dynamical systems perspective on agent–environment interaction. Artificial Intelligence, 72, 173–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Betella, A., Carvalho, R., Sanchez-Palencia, J., Bernadet, U., & Verschure, P. F. M. J. (2012). Embodied interaction with complex neuronal data in mixed-reality. In S. Richir (Ed.), Proceedings of the 2012 Virtual Reality International Conference (VRIC’12). New York, NY: ACM.

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs: Minds, technologies, and the future of human intelligence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. J. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Preester, H. (2011). Technology and the body: The (Im) possibilities of re-embodiment. Foundations of Science, 16, 119–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Preester, H. (2012). Equipment and existential spatiality: Heidegger, cognitive science and the prosthetic subject. In J. Kiverstein & M. Wheeler (Eds.), Heidegger and cognitive science (pp. 276–308). Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2009a). Extended life. Topoi, 28(1), 9–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2009b). Overcoming autopoiesis: An enactive detour on the way from life to society. In R. Magalhaes, & R. Sanchez (Eds.), Autopoiesis in organizations and information systems (pp. 43–68). Elsevier.

  • Di Paolo, E. A. (2010). Living technology. In M. A. Bedau, P. Guldborg Hansen, E. Parke, & S. Rasmussen (Eds.), Living technology: 5 questions. Birkerød: Automatic Press/VIP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. ([1961] 2001). Madness and civilization: A history of insanity in the age of reason. London, UK: Routledge.

  • Franklin, S. (1995). Artificial minds. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T. (2009). Hume and the enactive approach to mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 8(1), 95–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2011). The enactive approach: Theoretical sketches from cell to society. Pragmatics & Cognition, 19(1), 1–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., & Fuchs, T. (2012). The extended body: A case study in the neurophenomenology of social interaction. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11(2), 205–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., & Ziemke, T. (2009). Enactive artificial intelligence: Investigating the systemic organization of life and mind. Artificial Intelligence, 173(3–4), 366–500.

    Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., Lenay, C., & Ikegami, T. (2012a). Imitation by social interaction? Analysis of a minimal agent-based model of the correspondence problem. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 6(202), doi:10.3389/fnhum.2012.00202.

  • Froese, T., McGann, M., Bigge, W., Spiers, A., & Seth, A. K. (2012b). The enactive torch: A new tool for the science of perception. IEEE Transactions on Haptics, 5(4), 365–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., Suzuki, K., Ogai, Y., & Ikegami, T. (2012c). Using human–computer interfaces to investigate ‘mind-as-it-could-be’ from the first-person perspective. Cognitive Computation, 4(3), 365–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Froese, T., Gershenson, C., & Rosenblueth, D. A. (2013). The dynamically extended mind: A minimal modeling case study. In 2013 I.E. Congress on Evolutionary Computation (pp. 1419–1426). IEEE Press.

  • Gallagher, S. (in press). The socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research.

  • Hampson, R. E., Gerhardt, G. A., Marmarelis, V., Song, D., Opris, I., Santos, L., et al. (2012). Facilitation and restoration of cognitive function in primate prefrontal cortex by a neuroprosthesis that utilizes minicolumn-specific neural firing. Journal of Neural Engineering, 9(5), 056012. doi:10.1088/1741-2560/9/5/056012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. (2003). The companion species manifesto: Dogs, people, and significant otherness. Chicago: Prickly Paradigm Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haraway, D. (2008). When species meet. Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. ([1927] 1962). Being and time. New York, NY: Harper and Row.

  • Heidegger, M. ([1954] 2008). The question concerning technology. In D. F. Krell (Ed.), Martin Heidegger: basic writings (pp. 307–342). New York, NY: HarperCollins.

  • Ieropoulos, I., Greenman, J., Melhuish, C., & Horseld, I. (2010). EcoBot-III: A robot with guts. In H. Fellermann, M. Dörr, M. M. Hanczyc, L. L. Laursen, S. Maurer, D. Merkle, et al. (Eds.), Artificial Life XII: Proceedings of the Twelfth International Conference on the Synthesis and Simulation of Living Systems (pp. 733–741). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

  • Ihde, D. (1999). Technology and prognostic predicaments. AI & Society, 13, 44–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (2003). If phenomenology is an albatross, is post-phenomenology possible? In D. Ihde & E. Selinger (Eds.), Chasing technoscience: Matrix for materiality (pp. 131–144). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (2011a). Husserl’s Galileo needed a telescope! Philosophy & Technology, 24(1), 69–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ihde, D. (2011b). Stretching the in-between: Embodiment and beyond. Foundations of Science, 16(2–3), 109–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1968). Biological foundations of individuality. International Philosophical Quarterly, 8(2), 231–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1979). Toward a philosophy of technology. The Hastings Center Report, 9(1), 34–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. ([1966] 2001). The phenomenon of life: Toward a philosophical biology. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

  • Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self-organization of brain and behavior. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Khatchatourov, A., Stewart, J., & Lenay, C. (2007). Towards an enactive epistemology of technics. In Proceedings of ENACTIVE/07: 4th International Conference on Enactive Interfaces (pp. 129–132). Grenoble, France: Association ACROE.

  • Kwok, R. (2013). Once more, with feeling: Prosthetic arms are getting ever more sophisticated. Now they just need a sense of touch. Nature, 497, 176–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. (1994). On technical mediation—Philosophy, sociology, genealogy. Common Knowledge, 3(2), 29–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenay, C. (2012). Separability and technical constitution. Foundations of Science, 17(4), 379–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leroi-Gourhan, A. ([1964–1965] 1993). Gesture and speech. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

  • McGregor, S., & Virgo, N. (2011). Life and its close relatives. In G. Kampis, I. Karsai, & E. Szathmáry (Eds.), Advances in artificial life: 10th European Conference, ECAL 2009 (pp. 230–237). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. ([1945] 2002). Phenomenology of perception (Trans: Smith, C.). Oxon, UK: Routledge.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. ([1961] 1964). Eye and mind (Trans: Dallery, C.). In J. M. Edie (Ed.), The primacy of perception: And other essays on phenomenological psychology, the philosophy of art, history and politics (pp. 159–190). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

  • Nasuto, S. J., & Bishop, J. M. (2013). Of (Zombie) mice and animats. In V. C. Müller (Ed.), Philosophy and theory of artificial intelligence (pp. 85–106). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (1995). The mangle of practice: Time, agency, & science. London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenblueth, A. N., Wiener, N., & Bigelow, J. (1943). Behavior, purpose and teleology. Philosophy of Science, 10, 18–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sessa, B. (2008). Is it time to revisit the role of psychedelic drugs in enhancing human creativity? Journal of Psychopharmacology, 22(8), 821–827.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A., & Newell, A. (1958). Heuristic problem solving: The next advance in operations research. Operations Research, 6(1), 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smuts, B. (2001). Encounters with animal minds. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7), 293–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. (2010). Foundational issues in enaction as a paradigm for cognitive science: From the origin of life to consciousness and writing. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Toward a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 1–31). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J., Gapenne, O., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2010). Introduction. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. A. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Toward a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. vii–xvii). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stiegler, B. (1998). Technics and time, 1: The fault of Epimetheus (Trans: Beardsworth, R. & Collins, G.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

  • Talwar, S. K., Xu, S., Hawley, E. S., Weiss, S. A., Moxon, K. A., & Chapin, J. K. (2002). Rat navigation guided by remote control. Nature, 417, 37–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2001). Empathy and consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 8(5–7), 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E., & Stapleton, M. (2009). Making sense of sense-making: Reflections on enactive and extended mind theories. Topoi, 28(1), 23–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., & Kaminski, J. (2009). Like infant, like dog. Science, 325, 1213–1214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Topál, J., Gergely, G., Erdőhegyi, Á., Csibra, G., & Miklósi, Á. (2009). Differential sensitivity to human communication in dogs, wolves, and human infants. Science, 325, 1269–1272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1991). Organism: A meshwork of selfless selves. In A. I. Tauber (Ed.), Organism and the origins of self (pp. 79–107). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Warwick, K., Xydas, D., Nasuto, S. J., Becerra, V. M., Hammond, M. W., Downes, J. H., et al. (2010). Controlling a mobile robot with a biological brain. Defence Science Journal, 60(1), 5–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1, 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, M. (2005). In search of the first civilizations. London: BBC Books.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Tom Froese is grateful to Mark Bishop and Yasemin Erden for their support and encouragement during the writing of this article. He also thanks three anonymous reviewers for their helpful and constructive comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tom Froese.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Froese, T. Bio-machine Hybrid Technology: A Theoretical Assessment and Some Suggestions for Improved Future Design. Philos. Technol. 27, 539–560 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-013-0130-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-013-0130-y

Keywords

Navigation