Skip to main content
Log in

Human Nature: The Very Idea

  • Special Issue
  • Published:
Philosophy & Technology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The only biologically respectable notion of human nature is an extremely permissive one that names the reliable dispositions of the human species as a whole. This conception offers no ethical guidance in debates over enhancement, and indeed it has the result that alterations to human nature have been commonplace in the history of our species. Aristotelian conceptions of species natures, which are currently fashionable in meta-ethics and applied ethics, have no basis in biological fact. Moreover, because our folk psychology finds this misleading Aristotelian conception highly tempting, we are in fact better off if we refrain from mentioning human nature altogether in debates over enhancement.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Atran, S. (1990). Cognitive Foundations of Natural History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atran, S., Estin, P., Coley, J., & Medin, D. (1997). Generic species and basic levels: essence and appearance in folk biology. Journal of Ethnobiology, 17, 17–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barker, M. (2010). Specious intrinsicalism. Philosophy of Science, 77, 73–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briggle, A. (2010). A Rich Bioethics: Public Policy, Biotechnology and the Kass Council. University of Notre Dame Press.

  • Buchanan, A. (2009). Human nature and enhancement. Bioethics, 23, 141–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buss, D. (1999). Evolutionary Psychology: The New Science of the Mind. Allyn and Bacon.

  • Daly, M., & Wilson, M. (1988). Homicide. New York: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. (2009). Can Anyone Really be Talking About Ethically Modifying Human Nature? In J. Savulescu & N. Bostrom (Eds.), Human enhancement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1877/2004). The Descent of Man, Second Edition. Edited and introduced by J Moore and A Desmond. London: Penguin.

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 75, 344–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2010). Species have (partly) intrinsic essences. Philosophy of Science, 77, 648–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1981). Natural kinds and biological taxa. Philosophical Review, 90, 66–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2001). The poverty of the Linnean hierarchy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2008). Systematics and Taxonomy. In Sarkar & Plutynski (Eds.), The Blackwell companion to the philosophy of biology (pp. 99–118). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M. (2010). What’s wrong with the new biological essentialism? Philosophy of Science, 77, 674–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky, M., & Matthen, M. (2005). Taxonomy, polymorphism and history: an introduction to population structure theory. Philosophy of Science, 72, 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. (2001). Natural goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gelman, S., & Hirschfeld, L. (1999). How Biological is Essentialism? In S. Atran & D. Medin (Eds.), Folkbiology (pp. 403–445). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. (1997). Metaphysics and the Origin of Species. SUNY Press.

  • Griffiths, P. (1999). Squaring the circle: Natural kinds with historical essences. In: R. Wilson (Ed.) Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays (pp. 209–228). MIT Press.

  • Habermas, J. (2003). The Future of Human Nature. Polity.

  • Harris, J. (2007). Enhancing evolution: The ethical case for making better people. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (2012). What’s Social about Social Learning? Journal of Comparative Psychology. In press

  • Hull, D. (1986). Human nature. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2, 3–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kass, L. (1998). The wisdom of repugnance: Why we should ban the cloning of humans. Valparaiso University Law Review, 32, 679–705.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kass, L. (2003). Ageless Bodies, Happy Souls. New Atlantis Spring Edition: 9–28.

  • Lewens, T. (2007). Darwin. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. (2009a). What is wrong with typological thinking? Philosophy of Science, 76, 355–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. (2009b). Enhancement and human nature: The case of Sandel. Journal of Medical Ethics, 35, 354–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T. (2010). Foot note. Analysis, 70, 468–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewens, T (2012). Species, Essence and Explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences. In press

  • Linquist, S., Machery, E., Griffiths, P., & Stotz, K. (2011). Exploring the folkbiological conception of human nature. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 366, 444–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2008). A plea for human nature. Philosophical Psychology, 21, 321–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2002). Darwinian metaphysics: Species and the question of essentialism. Synthese, 131, 191–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ray, E., & Heyes, C. (2011). Imitation in infancy: The wealth of the stimulus. Developmental Science, 14, 92–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes alone. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. (2007). The case against perfection: Ethics in the Age of Genetic Engineering. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J., & Bostrom, N. (Eds.). (2009). Human enhancement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shuster, S. (1987). Alternative reproductive behaviors: Three discrete male morphs in Paracerceis sculpta. Journal of Crustacean Biology, 7, 318–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1980). Evolution, population thinking, and essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 47, 350–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (1995). The Representation of Life. In R. Hursthouse, G. Lawrence, & W. Quinn (Eds.), Virtues and reasons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2008). Life and action: Elementary structures of practice and practical thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Luciano Floridi and two anonymous referees from Philosophy and Technology for their very helpful comments on this paper. I would like to thank Russell Powell in particular for incisive comments on an earlier draft. The research leading to these results has received funding from the European Research Council under the European Union’s Seventh Framework Programme (FP7/2007-2013)/ERC Grant agreement no 284123.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tim Lewens.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lewens, T. Human Nature: The Very Idea. Philos. Technol. 25, 459–474 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-012-0063-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-012-0063-x

Keywords

Navigation