Skip to main content
Log in

Just How Emergent is the Emergence of Semiosis?

  • Published:
Biosemiotics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Studying the origin of semiosis is a task obscured by terminological and metaphysical issues which create an ambiguous set of definitions for biosemiotics when referring to the concept of emergence. The question is, how emergent can semiosis be? And what are the conditions for semiosis to be an emergent of a certain type? This paper will attempt to briefly deal with the general terminology of emergence from a philosophical point of view and will discuss the characterization of semiosis as an emergent phenomenon based on the distinctions made by Bedau, Kim and Chalmers. Accordingly, we will consider the possibility of strong and weak emergence in an attempt to bring some clarity to what it means for something in biosemiotics to be an emergent and how the philosophical concepts play out when applied to biosemiotic research. In inquiring into the metaphysical status of semiosis, we change our semiotic theories to correspond to the assumptions contained in the elementary objects of our theories. This being the case, the way semiosis–the constitutive element that it is for semiotics–is taken to be with regards to its possible ontology, will conduct to different research objects for the long-term investigation of its origins and necessary conditions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It’s important to note that this same description has been referred to in Brier (2008: 369) and Martinelli (2010: 194). Kull (2007: 4) also includes it among different approaches to biosemiotics. I will not try to document all possible perspectives, as it is beyond the scope of this research. The idea is, in any case, that the emergentist foundation of biosemiotics seems to be unproblematic except in its actual implementation, as we will later see.

  2. The arguments against the epiphenomenalism of mental properties could be reworked into arguments against the epiphenomenalism of semiosis stating, for instance, the relevance of sign processes for living systems, as opposed to the qualitative irrelevance needed to make the epiphenomenal argument work. This, however, is a different discussion altogether.

  3. See Stephan (1992: 25–26) for a historical survey of its stages in philosophy.

  4. While the language used by Chalmers in this initial definition talks about ‘phenomena’, the concept of emergence deals more often with properties.

  5. Supervenience itself, also called upwards determination, appears commonly divided in three different types, weak, strong and global, related to possible worlds (Kim 1984: 157). We will limit our talk on different types of supervenience to the common usage in standard discussions of emergence.

  6. A better place to look for such an exposition can be found in Kim (2010), Deacon (2011), or from a more general semiotic perspective, Szívós (2008).

  7. While it appears that Peirce considers chance as the best possible explanation, there is no reason in principle to stop there, as his remarks on evolution may suggest other possibilities.

  8. A notable contribution in this respect has been carried by El-Hani et al. (2009).

  9. The author refers to Kauffman’s view on emergence, but these claims can be generalized without much trouble. It is important to note, however, that Kauffman is associated with weak emergence.

  10. We will avoid the issue of representation and reference altogether to skip extra complexities in the argument. These aspects can, however, play a role in more developed accounts of cognition within an emergentist framework.

  11. At this point it is important to remark that, while inextricably related, the question of the emergence of life does not refer exactly to the same problems that appear when dealing with the emergence of semiosis.

  12. Stjernfelt carries out the rest of the analysis of chemotaxis through biosemiotic terminology, reaching the striking, yet not unexpected conclusion that “in the perception-action circle of a bacterium, we find some of the minimum requirements for semiotic processes: the self-regulatory stability of a metabolism involving categorized signal and action involvement with the surroundings” (Stjernfelt 2007: 209).

  13. Yet, once the object is part of the relation, we see that the relation, while not determined simply by it, needs it to exist.

  14. The difference between dynamical and immediate object does not have an impact on this conclusion as both are taken in the same relation.

  15. The argument for physical representamina is explored by Deely (2001) from a different philosophical perspective, but it is worth noting that the language used is perfectly valid in this particular formulation.

  16. This quotation is far from straightforward. Peirce goes on to state that “the example of the imperative command shows that it need not be of a mental mode of being.” (CP 5.473) This passage, in any case, discusses causation in different levels, starting with microscopic animals and continuing with verbal military commands, from where the reference to imperative commands comes. While naive in his psychological interpretation, it seems Peirce points to the fact that the interpretant is wider than the concept of a mental image or idea. A discussion on this passage can be found in Hulswit (2002: 140–143).

  17. An important passage from the same text states that

    Semiosis, more shortly, could be defined as the appearance of a connection between things, which do not have a priori anything in common, in the sense that they do not interact or convert each other through direct physical or chemical processes. However, as far as the relation between them, once established (by a subject), is nevertheless intermediated by physical or chemical processes, this infers that the relation is semiotic as long as it is established through learning (Kull 1998: 303–304).

    This is something to keep in mind when dealing with the possible properties of semiosis as an emergent phenomenon. The hierarchy between the elements of semiosis is not equal, despite the necessity of every element once the relation has been established.

  18. The original quote states that “the laws of nature, which are all expressible by differential equations, might be semeiotic at the bottom, although of a degenerated kind” (Romanini and Fernández 2014: 3).

  19. van Hateren (2015) also proposes what he calls “a strong form of emergence” (403) of meaningful phenomena, but the argument only seems to require weak emergence to hold.

  20. In brief, Bedau maintains that “although strong emergence is logically possible, it is uncomfortably like magic […]. But the most disappointing aspect of strong emergence is its apparent scientific irrelevance” (Bedau 1997: 377). On the contrary, “science apparently does need weak emergence” (Bedau 1997: 377).

  21. This may not turn out to be true if we hold that repeatable specific conditions do not need to have any explanatory value for emergents in that the property would not be deducible even if we are aware of what it takes for it to emerge. However, the fact that the specific initial conditions can be understood and even derived indicates that there may be a chance to reduce the possible emergents to monadic properties of some sort.

  22. Conway’s Game of Life has some important traction in the discussion of determinism (Dennett 1991), but this must be set aside for the time being, though it can have some interesting and serious implications for biosemiotics.

  23. A good introduction to this type of research can be seen in Nöth (1990: 107–114), however, there are many specific variations and elucidations on the Peircean theme and its extension, such as the ones in Farias and Queiroz (2007) and Borges (2010).

  24. Similarly, there is a conceptual difference between resultant and emergent properties, with the former being predictable unlike the latter. Regarding the extent to which downward causation is actual causation, a review can be found in Hulswit (2005).

  25. Chalmers sees consciousness as the only case of strong emergence (Chalmers 2006: 246).

  26. There is a different issue altogether with whether we should characterize all semiosis as perception. This will not be treated here, but in principle I do not wish to characterize all forms of sign usage, especially at the higher levels of cognition, to be based on the same principle.

References

  • Bedau, M. A. (1997). Weak emergence. Philosophical Perspectives: Mind, Causation, and World, 11, 375–399.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, M. A. (2002). Downward causation and the autonomy of weak emergence. Principia, 6, 5–50.

  • Berto, F., & Tagliaube, J. (2012). Cellular automata. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (summer 2012 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/cellular-automata/.

  • Borges, P. (2010). A visual model of Peirce’s 66 classes of signs unravels his late proposal of enlarging semiotic theory. In L. Magnani, W. Carnielli, & C. Pizzi (Eds.), Model-based reasoning in science and technology: Abduction, logic, and computational discovery (pp. 221–237). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brier, S. (2008). Cybersemiotics: Why information is not enough! Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cannizzaro, S. (2012). Biosemiotics as systems theory: An investigation into biosemiotics as the grounding for a new cultural analysis. Doctoral thesis. London: London Metropolitan University.

  • Chalmers, D. (2006). Strong and weak emergence. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (Eds.), The re-emergence of emergence: The emergentist hypothesis from science to religion (pp. 244–254). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Champagne, M. (2013). A necessary condition for proof of abiotic semiosis. Semiotica, 197, 283–287.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2011). Incomplete nature: How mind emerged from matter. New York: W.W. Norton.

  • Deely, J. (2001). Four ages of understanding: The first postmodern survey of philosophy from ancient times to the turn of the twenty-first century. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Real patterns. The Journal of Philosophy, 88(1), 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • El-Hani, C. N., Queiroz, J., & Emmeche, C. (2009). Genes, information, and semiosis. Tartu: Tartu University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C. (1992). Modeling life: A note on the semiotics of emergence and computation in artificial and natural living systems. In T. Sebeok & J. Umiker-Sebeok (Eds.), Biosemiotics: The semiotics web 1991 (pp. 77–99). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faria, M. (2008). RNA as code makers: A biosemiotic view of RNAi and cell immunity. In M. Barbieri (Ed.), Introduction to biosemiotics: The new biological synthesis (pp. 347–364). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farias, P., & Queiroz, J. (2007). A diagrammatic approach to Peirce’s classification of signs. Semiotics, Evolution, Energy, and Development, 6(1), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, M. (1970). Mathematical games: The fantastic combinations of John Conway’s new solitary game ‘life’. Scientific American, 223, 120–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer, J. (2008). Semiotic scaffolding of living systems. In M. Barbieri (Ed.), Introduction to biosemiotics: The new biological synthesis (pp. 149–166). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hulswit, M. (2002). From cause to causation: A Peircean perspective. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Hulswit, M. (2005). How causal is downward causation? Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 36, 261–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. (2012). From physics to semiotics. In S. Rattasepp & T. Bennett (Eds.), Gatherings in biosemiotics (pp. 30–46). Tartu: Tartu University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiblinger, W. P. (2007). C. S. Peirce and Stuart Kauffman: evolution and subjectivity. Zygon, 42(1), 193–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1984). Concepts of supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 45(2), 153–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2010). Essays in the metaphysics of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K. (1998). On semiosis, umwelt and semiosphere. Semiotica, 120(3), 299–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kull, K. (2007). A brief history of biosemiotics. In M. Barbieri (Ed.), Biosemiotics: Information, codes and signs in living systems (pp. 1–25). New York: Nova.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macdonald, C., & Macdonald, G. (2010). Emergence and downward causation. In C. Macdonald & G. Macdonald (Eds.), Emergence in mind (pp. 139–168). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Markoš, A. (2014). Biosphere as semiosphere: variations on Lotman. Sign Systems Studies, 42(4), 487–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martinelli, D. (2010). A critical companion to zoosemiotics: People, paths, ideas. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B., & Bennett, K. (2014). Supervenience. The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL=<http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/supervenience/>.

  • Nöth, W. (1990). Handbook of semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nöth, W. (1994). Introduction. In W. Nöth (Ed.), Origins of semiosis: Sign evolution in nature and culture (pp. 1–12). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pattee, H. H. (2010). The physics and metaphysics of biosemiotics. In D. Favareau (Ed.), Essential readings in biosemiotics (pp. 519–540). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Romanini, V., & Fernández, E. (2014). Introduction. In V. Romanini & E. Fernández (Eds.), Peirce and biosemiotics: A guess at the riddle of life (pp. 1–8). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stephan, A. (1992). Emergence—a systematic view on its historical facets. In A. Beckermann, H. Flohr, & J. Kim (Eds.), Emergence or reduction? Essays on the prospects of nonreductive physicalism (pp. 25–48). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2007). Diagrammatology: An investigation on the borderlines of phenomenology, ontology, and semiotics. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stjernfelt, F. (2014). Natural propositions: The actuality of Peirce’s doctrine of dicisigns. Boston: Docent Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szívós, M. (2008). Introduction: the concept of emergence in philosophical and semiotic context. Semiotica, 170(1/4), 3–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Hateren, J. H. (2015). The natural emergence of (bio)semiosic phenomena. Biosemiotics, 8(3), 403–419.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, W. (2006). The whole creature: Complexity, biosemiotics and the evolution of culture. London: Lawrence and Wishart.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claudio Julio Rodríguez Higuera.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rodríguez Higuera, C.J. Just How Emergent is the Emergence of Semiosis?. Biosemiotics 9, 155–167 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-016-9265-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12304-016-9265-4

Keywords

Navigation